question answers

 

Tips on Reading Philosophy:

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
question answers
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

– Read a summary before reading philosophy texts, it will help you get the most out of your reading – especially as readings get more difficult (Summaries do NOT replace the reading)

– Highlight confusing passages, write down any questions you have – we can discuss these in class

– Look over the week’s discussion questions before reading, try to pick out philosophical ideas as you read

– Do the reading before lecture to best understand the ideas discussed in class

*Tips on Studying Philosophy:

– Write a paragraph or two summarizing the philosophical text in your own words after completing each reading

– Make a “T” chart comparing philosophers/philosophical ideas at the end of each week (the “study sheet” I’ve posted has a similar concept)

– List and define the 3-4 key ideas for each philosopher discussed in class – add an example from the story to support this idea

– Ensure your notes taken in class are clear, fill them in at the end of lecture (material posted on C4 is not enough for the exam)

– Make a study group or find a study partner, two brains are better than one!

  • Manifesto of the Communist Party
  • by Karl Marx and Frederick Engels

    February 1848

    Written: Late 1847;
    First Published: February 1848;
    Source: Marx/Engels Selected Works, Vol. One, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1969, pp. 98-137;
    Translated: Samuel Moore in cooperation with Frederick Engels, 1888;
    Transcribed: by Zodiac and Brian Baggins;
    Proofed: and corrected against 1888 English Edition by Andy Blunden 2004;
    Copyleft: Marxists Internet Archive (marxists.org) 1987, 2000, 2010. Permission is granted to
    distribute this document under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-Share-Alike License.

    Table of Contents
    Editorial Introduction ………………………………………………………………………………………………………. 2
    Preface to The 1872 German Edition …………………………………………………………………………………. 4
    Preface to The 1882 Russian Edition …………………………………………………………………………………. 5
    Preface to The 1883 German Edition …………………………………………………………………………………. 6
    Preface to The 1888 English Edition………………………………………………………………………………….. 7
    Preface to The 1890 German Edition ……………………………………………………………………………….. 10
    Preface to The 1892 Polish Edition ………………………………………………………………………………….. 12
    Preface to The 1893 Italian Edition………………………………………………………………………………….. 13
    Manifesto of the Communist Party…………………………………………………………………………………… 14
    I. Bourgeois and Proletarians ………………………………………………………………………………………….. 14
    II. Proletarians and Communists ……………………………………………………………………………………… 22
    III. Socialist and Communist Literature ……………………………………………………………………………. 28

    1. Reactionary Socialism …………………………………………………………………………………………. 28
    A. Feudal Socialism ………………………………………………………………………………………… 28
    B. Petty-Bourgeois Socialism …………………………………………………………………………… 29
    C. German or “True” Socialism ………………………………………………………………………… 29

    2. Conservative or Bourgeois Socialism ……………………………………………………………………. 31
    3. Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism………………………………………………………….. 32

    IV. Position of the Communists in Relation to the Various Existing Opposition Parties …………. 34
    Letter from Engels to Marx, 24 November 1847 ……………………………………………………………….. 35
    Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith ……………………………………………………………………….. 36
    The Principles of Communism ………………………………………………………………………………………… 41
    Demands of the Communist Party in Germany………………………………………………………………….. 55
    The Paris Commune. Address to the International Workingmen’s Association, May 1871……… 58
    Endnotes ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………. 67

    2 Introduction

    Editorial Introduction

    The “Manifesto of the Communist Party” was written by Marx and Engels as the Communist
    League’s programme on the instruction of its Second Congress (London, November 29-December 8,
    1847), which signified a victory for the followers of a new proletarian line during the discussion of the
    programme questions.
    When Congress was still in preparation, Marx and Engels arrived at the conclusion that the final
    programme document should be in the form of a Party manifesto (see Engels’ letter to Marx of
    November 23-24, 1847). The catechism form usual for the secret societies of the time and retained in
    the “Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith” and “Principles of Communism,” was not suitable for
    a full and substantial exposition of the new revolutionary world outlook, for a comprehensive
    formulation of the proletarian movement’s aims and tasks. See also “Demands of the Communist
    Party in Germany,” issued by Marx soon after publication of the Manifesto, which addressed the
    immediate demands of the movement.
    Marx and Engels began working together on the Manifesto while they were still in London
    immediately after the congress, and continued until about December 13 when Marx returned to
    Brussels; they resumed their work four days later (December 17) when Engels arrived there. After
    Engels’ departure for Paris at the end of December and up to his return on January 31, Marx worked
    on the Manifesto alone.
    Hurried by the Central Authority of the Communist League which provided him with certain
    documents (e.g., addresses of the People’s Chamber (Halle) of the League of the Just of November
    1846 and February 1847, and, apparently, documents of the First Congress of the Communist League
    pertaining to the discussion of the Party programme), Marx worked intensively on the Manifesto
    through almost the whole of January 1848. At the end of January the manuscript was sent on to
    London to be printed in the German Workers’ Educational Society’s print shop owned by a German
    emigrant J. E. Burghard, a member of the Communist League.
    The manuscript of the Manifesto has not survived. The only extant materials written in Marx’s hand
    are a draft plan for Section III, showing his efforts to improve the structure of the Manifesto, and a
    page of a rough copy.
    The Manifesto came off the press at the end of February 1848. On February 29, the Educational
    Society decided to cover all the printing expenses.
    The first edition of the Manifesto was a 23-page pamphlet in a dark green cover. In April-May 1848
    another edition was put out. The text took up 30 pages, some misprints of the first edition were
    corrected, and the punctuation improved. Subsequently this text was used by Marx and Engels as a
    basis for later authorised editions. Between March and July 1848 the Manifesto was printed in the
    Deutsche Londoner Zeitung, a democratic newspaper of the German emigrants. Already that same
    year numerous efforts were made to publish the Manifesto in other European languages. A Danish, a
    Polish (in Paris) and a Swedish (under a different title: “The Voice of Communism. Declaration of the
    Communist Party”) editions appeared in 1848. The translations into French, Italian and Spanish made
    at that time remained unpublished. In April 1848, Engels, then in Barmen, was translating the
    Manifesto into English, but he managed to translate only half of it, and the first English translation,
    made by Helen Macfarlane, was not published until two years later, between June and November 1850,
    in the Chartist journal The Red Republican. Its editor, Julian Harney, named the authors for the first
    time in the introduction to this publication. All earlier and many subsequent editions of the Manifesto
    were anonymous.
    The growing emancipation struggle of the proletariat in the ’60s and ’70s of the 19th century led to
    new editions of the Manifesto. The year 1872 saw a new German edition with minor corrections and a
    preface by Marx and Engels where they drew some conclusions from the experience of the Paris

    3 Introduction

    Commune of 1871. This and subsequent German editions (1883 and 1890) were entitled the
    Communist Manifesto. In 1872 the Manifesto was first published in America in Woodhull & Claflin’s
    Weekly.
    The first Russian edition of the Manifesto, translated by Mikhail Bakunin with some distortions,
    appeared in Geneva in 1869. The faults of this edition were removed in the 1882 edition (translation
    by Georgi Plekhanov), for which Marx and Engels, who attributed great significance to the
    dissemination of Marxism in Russia, had written a special preface.
    After Marx’s death, the Manifesto ran into several editions. Engels read through them all, wrote
    prefaces for the 1883 German edition and for the 1888 English edition in Samuel Moore’s translation,
    which he also edited and supplied with notes. This edition served as a basis for many subsequent
    editions of the Manifesto in English – in Britain, the United States and the USSR. In 1890, Engels
    prepared a further German edition, wrote a new preface to it, and added a number of notes. In 1885,
    the newspaper Le Socialiste published the French translation of the Manifesto made by Marx’s
    daughter Laura Lafargue and read by Engels. He also wrote prefaces to the 1892 Polish and 1893
    Italian editions.
    This edition includes the two earlier versions of the Manifesto, namely the draft “Communist
    Confession of Faith” and “The Principles of Communism,” both authored by Engels, as well as the
    letter from Engels to Marx which poses the idea of publishing a “manifesto,” rather than a catechism.
    The Manifesto addressed itself to a mass movement with historical significance, not a political sect.
    On the other hand, the “Demands of the Communist Party in Germany” is included to place the
    publication of the Manifesto in the context of the mass movement in Germany at the time, whose
    immediate demands are reflected by Marx in this pamphlet. Clearly the aims of the Manifesto were
    more far-reaching the movement in Germany at the time, and unlike the “Demands,” was intended to
    outlive the immediate conditions.
    The “Third Address to the International Workingmen’s Association” is included because in this
    speech Marx examines the movement of the working class manifested in the Paris Commune, and his
    observations here mark the only revisions to his social and historical vision made during his lifetime
    as a result of the development of the working class movement itself, clarifying some points and
    making others more concrete.

    Preface to The 1872 German Edition

    The Communist League, an international association of workers, which could of course be only a
    secret one, under conditions obtaining at the time, commissioned us, the undersigned, at the
    Congress held in London in November 1847, to write for publication a detailed theoretical and
    practical programme for the Party. Such was the origin of the following Manifesto, the
    manuscript of which travelled to London to be printed a few weeks before the February [French]
    Revolution [in 1848]. First published in German, it has been republished in that language in at
    least twelve different editions in Germany, England, and America. It was published in English for
    the first time in 1850 in the Red Republican, London, translated by Miss Helen Macfarlane, and
    in 1871 in at least three different translations in America. The French version first appeared in
    Paris shortly before the June insurrection of 1848, and recently in Le Socialiste of New York. A
    new translation is in the course of preparation. A Polish version appeared in London shortly after
    it was first published in Germany. A Russian translation was published in Geneva in the sixties1.
    Into Danish, too, it was translated shortly after its appearance.
    However much that state of things may have altered during the last twenty-five years, the general
    principles laid down in the Manifesto are, on the whole, as correct today as ever. Here and there,
    some detail might be improved. The practical application of the principles will depend, as the
    Manifesto itself states, everywhere and at all times, on the historical conditions for the time being
    existing, and, for that reason, no special stress is laid on the revolutionary measures proposed at
    the end of Section II. That passage would, in many respects, be very differently worded today. In
    view of the gigantic strides of Modern Industry since 1848, and of the accompanying improved
    and extended organization of the working class, in view of the practical experience gained, first in
    the February Revolution, and then, still more, in the Paris Commune, where the proletariat for the
    first time held political power for two whole months, this programme has in some details been
    antiquated. One thing especially was proved by the Commune, viz., that “the working class
    cannot simply lay hold of the ready-made state machinery, and wield it for its own purposes.”
    (See The Civil War in France: Address of the General Council of the International Working
    Men’s Association, 1871, where this point is further developed.) Further, it is self-evident that the
    criticism of socialist literature is deficient in relation to the present time, because it comes down
    only to 1847; also that the remarks on the relation of the Communists to the various opposition
    parties (Section IV), although, in principle still correct, yet in practice are antiquated, because the
    political situation has been entirely changed, and the progress of history has swept from off the
    earth the greater portion of the political parties there enumerated.
    But then, the Manifesto has become a historical document which we have no longer any right to
    alter. A subsequent edition may perhaps appear with an introduction bridging the gap from 1847
    to the present day; but this reprint was too unexpected to leave us time for that.

    Karl Marx & Frederick Engels
    June 24, 1872, London

    Preface to The 1882 Russian Edition

    The first Russian edition of the Manifesto of the Communist Party, translated by Bakunin, was
    published early in the ‘sixties by the printing office of the Kolokol [a reference to the Free
    Russian Printing House]. Then the West could see in it (the Russian edition of the Manifesto)
    only a literary curiosity. Such a view would be impossible today.
    What a limited field the proletarian movement occupied at that time (December 1847) is most
    clearly shown by the last section: the position of the Communists in relation to the various
    opposition parties in various countries. Precisely Russia and the United States are missing here. It
    was the time when Russia constituted the last great reserve of all European reaction, when the
    United States absorbed the surplus proletarian forces of Europe through immigration. Both
    countries provided Europe with raw materials and were at the same time markets for the sale of
    its industrial products. Both were, therefore, in one way of another, pillars of the existing
    European system.
    How very different today. Precisely European immigration fitted North American for a gigantic
    agricultural production, whose competition is shaking the very foundations of European landed
    property – large and small. At the same time, it enabled the United States to exploit its
    tremendous industrial resources with an energy and on a scale that must shortly break the
    industrial monopoly of Western Europe, and especially of England, existing up to now. Both
    circumstances react in a revolutionary manner upon America itself. Step by step, the small and
    middle land ownership of the farmers, the basis of the whole political constitution, is succumbing
    to the competition of giant farms; at the same time, a mass industrial proletariat and a fabulous
    concentration of capital funds are developing for the first time in the industrial regions.
    And now Russia! During the Revolution of 1848-9, not only the European princes, but the
    European bourgeois as well, found their only salvation from the proletariat just beginning to
    awaken in Russian intervention. The Tsar was proclaimed the chief of European reaction. Today,
    he is a prisoner of war of the revolution in Gatchina 2 , and Russia forms the vanguard of
    revolutionary action in Europe.
    The Communist Manifesto had, as its object, the proclamation of the inevitable impending
    dissolution of modern bourgeois property. But in Russia we find, face-to-face with the rapidly
    flowering capitalist swindle and bourgeois property, just beginning to develop, more than half the
    land owned in common by the peasants. Now the question is: can the Russian obshchina, though
    greatly undermined, yet a form of primeval common ownership of land, pass directly to the
    higher form of Communist common ownership? Or, on the contrary, must it first pass through the
    same process of dissolution such as constitutes the historical evolution of the West?
    The only answer to that possible today is this: If the Russian Revolution becomes the signal for a
    proletarian revolution in the West, so that both complement each other, the present Russian
    common ownership of land may serve as the starting point for a communist development.

    Karl Marx & Frederick Engels
    January 21, 1882, London

    Preface to The 1883 German Edition

    The preface to the present edition I must, alas, sign alone. Marx, the man to whom the whole
    working class of Europe and America owes more than to any one else – rests at Highgate
    Cemetery and over his grave the first grass is already growing. Since his death [March 14, 1883],
    there can be even less thought of revising or supplementing the Manifesto. But I consider it all the
    more necessary again to state the following expressly:
    The basic thought running through the Manifesto – that economic production, and the structure of
    society of every historical epoch necessarily arising therefrom, constitute the foundation for the
    political and intellectual history of that epoch; that consequently (ever since the dissolution of the
    primaeval communal ownership of land) all history has been a history of class struggles, of
    struggles between exploited and exploiting, between dominated and dominating classes at various
    stages of social evolution; that this struggle, however, has now reached a stage where the
    exploited and oppressed class (the proletariat) can no longer emancipate itself from the class
    which exploits and oppresses it (the bourgeoisie), without at the same time forever freeing the
    whole of society from exploitation, oppression, class struggles – this basic thought belongs solely
    and exclusively to Marx.*
    I have already stated this many times; but precisely now is it necessary that it also stand in front
    of the Manifesto itself.

    Frederick Engels
    June 28, 1883, London

    * “This proposition,” I wrote in the preface to the English translation, “which, in my opinion, is destined to do for
    history what Darwin’ s theory has done for biology, we both of us, had been gradually approaching for some years
    before 1845. How far I had independently progressed towards it is best shown by my Conditions of the Working Class
    in England. But when I again met Marx at Brussels, in spring 1845, he had it already worked out and put it before me
    in terms almost as clear as those in which I have stated it here.” [Note by Engels to the German edition of 1890]

    Preface to The 1888 English Edition

    The Manifesto was published as the platform of the Communist League, a working men’ s
    association, first exclusively German, later on international, and under the political conditions of
    the Continent before 1848, unavoidably a secret society. At a Congress of the League, held in
    November 1847, Marx and Engels were commissioned to prepare a complete theoretical and
    practical party programme. Drawn up in German, in January 1848, the manuscript was sent to the
    printer in London a few weeks before the French Revolution of February 24. A French translation
    was brought out in Paris shortly before the insurrection of June 1848. The first English
    translation, by Miss Helen Macfarlane, appeared in George Julian Harney’ s Red Republican,
    London, 1850. A Danish and a Polish edition had also been published.
    The defeat of the Parisian insurrection of June 1848 – the first great battle between proletariat and
    bourgeoisie – drove again into the background, for a time, the social and political aspirations of
    the European working class. Thenceforth, the struggle for supremacy was, again, as it had been
    before the Revolution of February, solely between different sections of the propertied class; the
    working class was reduced to a fight for political elbow-room, and to the position of extreme
    wing of the middle-class Radicals. Wherever independent proletarian movements continued to
    show signs of life, they were ruthlessly hunted down. Thus the Prussian police hunted out the
    Central Board of the Communist League, then located in Cologne. The members were arrested
    and, after eighteen months’ imprisonment, they were tried in October 1852. This celebrated
    “Cologne Communist Trial” lasted from October 4 till November 12; seven of the prisoners were
    sentenced to terms of imprisonment in a fortress, varying from three to six years. Immediately
    after the sentence, the League was formally dissolved by the remaining members. As to the
    Manifesto, it seemed henceforth doomed to oblivion.
    When the European workers had recovered sufficient strength for another attack on the ruling
    classes, the International Working Men’ s Association sprang up. But this association, formed
    with the express aim of welding into one body the whole militant proletariat of Europe and
    America, could not at once proclaim the principles laid down in the Manifesto. The International
    was bound to have a programme broad enough to be acceptable to the English trade unions, to the
    followers of Proudhon in France, Belgium, Italy, and Spain, and to the Lassalleans in Germany.*
    Marx, who drew up this programme to the satisfaction of all parties, entirely trusted to the
    intellectual development of the working class, which was sure to result from combined action and
    mutual discussion. The very events and vicissitudes in the struggle against capital, the defeats
    even more than the victories, could not help bringing home to men’ s minds the insufficiency of
    their various favorite nostrums, and preparing the way for a more complete insight into the true
    conditions for working-class emancipation. And Marx was right. The International, on its
    breaking in 1874, left the workers quite different men from what it found them in 1864.
    Proudhonism in France, Lassalleanism in Germany, were dying out, and even the conservative
    English trade unions, though most of them had long since severed their connection with the
    International, were gradually advancing towards that point at which, last year at Swansea, their
    president [W. Bevan] could say in their name: “Continental socialism has lost its terror for us.” In
    fact, the principles of the Manifesto had made considerable headway among the working men of
    all countries.

    * Lassalle personally, to us, always acknowledged himself to be a disciple of Marx, and, as such, stood on the ground of
    the Manifesto. But in his first public agitation, 1862-1864, he did not go beyond demanding co-operative workshops
    supported by state credit.

    8 Preface to the 1888 English Edition

    The Manifesto itself came thus to the front again. Since 1850, the German text had been reprinted
    several times in Switzerland, England, and America. In 1872, it was translated into English in
    New York, where the translation was published in Woorhull and Claflin’s Weekly. From this
    English version, a French one was made in Le Socialiste of New York. Since then, at least two
    more English translations, more or less mutilated, have been brought out in America, and one of
    them has been reprinted in England. The first Russian translation, made by Bakunin, was
    published at Herzen’ s Kolokol office in Geneva, about 1863; a second one, by the heroic Vera
    Zasulich, also in Geneva, in 1882. A new Danish edition is to be found in Socialdemokratisk
    Bibliothek, Copenhagen, 1885; a fresh French translation in Le Socialiste, Paris, 1886. From this
    latter, a Spanish version was prepared and published in Madrid, 1886. The German reprints are
    not to be counted; there have been twelve altogether at the least. An Armenian translation, which
    was to be published in Constantinople some months ago, did not see the light, I am told, because
    the publisher was afraid of bringing out a book with the name of Marx on it, while the translator
    declined to call it his own production. Of further translations into other languages I have heard
    but had not seen. Thus the history of the Manifesto reflects the history of the modern working-
    class movement; at present, it is doubtless the most wide spread, the most international
    production of all socialist literature, the common platform acknowledged by millions of working
    men from Siberia to California.
    Yet, when it was written, we could not have called it a socialist manifesto. By Socialists, in 1847,
    were understood, on the one hand the adherents of the various Utopian systems: Owenites in
    England, Fourierists in France, both of them already reduced to the position of mere sects, and
    gradually dying out; on the other hand, the most multifarious social quacks who, by all manner of
    tinkering, professed to redress, without any danger to capital and profit, all sorts of social
    grievances, in both cases men outside the working-class movement, and looking rather to the
    “educated” classes for support. Whatever portion of the working class had become convinced of
    the insufficiency of mere political revolutions, and had proclaimed the necessity of total social
    change, called itself Communist. It was a crude, rough-hewn, purely instinctive sort of
    communism; still, it touched the cardinal point and was powerful enough amongst the working
    class to produce the Utopian communism of Cabet in France, and of Weitling in Germany. Thus,
    in 1847, socialism was a middle-class movement, communism a working-class movement.
    Socialism was, on the Continent at least, “respectable”; communism was the very opposite. And
    as our notion, from the very beginning, was that “the emancipation of the workers must be the act
    of the working class itself,” there could be no doubt as to which of the two names we must take.
    Moreover, we have, ever since, been far from repudiating it.
    The Manifesto being our joint production, I consider myself bound to state that the fundamental
    proposition which forms the nucleus belongs to Marx. That proposition is: That in every
    historical epoch, the prevailing mode of economic production and exchange, and the social
    organization necessarily following from it, form the basis upon which it is built up, and from that
    which alone can be explained the political and intellectual history of that epoch; that consequently
    the whole history of mankind (since the dissolution of primitive tribal society, holding land in
    common ownership) has been a history of class struggles, contests between exploiting and
    exploited, ruling and oppressed classes; That the history of these class struggles forms a series of
    evolutions in which, nowadays, a stage has been reached where the exploited and oppressed class
    – the proletariat – cannot attain its emancipation from the sway of the exploiting and ruling class
    – the bourgeoisie – without, at the same time, and once and for all, emancipating society at large
    from all exploitation, oppression, class distinction, and class struggles.
    This proposition, which, in my opinion, is destined to do for history what Darwin’ s theory has
    done for biology, we both of us, had been gradually approaching for some years before 1845.
    How far I had independently progressed towards it is best shown by my “Conditions of the
    Working Class in England.” But when I again met Marx at Brussels, in spring 1845, he had it

    9 Preface to the 1888 English Edition

    already worked out and put it before me in terms almost as clear as those in which I have stated it
    here.
    From our joint preface to the German edition of 1872, I quote the following:

    “However much that state of things may have altered during the last twenty-five
    years, the general principles laid down in the Manifesto are, on the whole, as
    correct today as ever. Here and there, some detail might be improved. The
    practical application of the principles will depend, as the Manifesto itself states,
    everywhere and at all times, on the historical conditions for the time being
    existing, and, for that reason, no special stress is laid on the revolutionary
    measures proposed at the end of Section II. That passage would, in many respects,
    be very differently worded today. In view of the gigantic strides of Modern
    Industry since 1848, and of the accompanying improved and extended
    organization of the working class, in view of the practical experience gained, first
    in the February Revolution, and then, still more, in the Paris Commune, where the
    proletariat for the first time held political power for two whole months, this
    programme has in some details been antiquated. One thing especially was proved
    by the Commune, viz., that “the working class cannot simply lay hold of ready-
    made state machinery, and wield it for its own purposes.” (See The Civil War in
    France: Address of the General Council of the International Working Men’ s
    Association 1871, where this point is further developed.) Further, it is self-evident
    that the criticism of socialist literature is deficient in relation to the present time,
    because it comes down only to 1847; also that the remarks on the relation of the
    Communists to the various opposition parties (Section IV), although, in principle
    still correct, yet in practice are antiquated, because the political situation has been
    entirely changed, and the progress of history has swept from off the Earth the
    greater portion of the political parties there enumerated.
    “But then, the Manifesto has become a historical document which we have no
    longer any right to alter.”

    The present translation is by Mr Samuel Moore, the translator of the greater portion of Marx’ s
    “Capital.” We have revised it in common, and I have added a few notes explanatory of historical
    allusions.

    Frederick Engels
    January 30, 1888, London

    Preface to The 1890 German Edition

    Since [the first German preface of 1883] was written, a new German edition of the Manifesto has
    again become necessary, and much has also happened to the Manifesto which should be recorded
    here.
    A second Russian translation – by Vera Zasulich – appeared in Geneva in 1882; the preface to
    that edition was written by Marx and myself. Unfortunately, the original German manuscript has
    gone astray; I must therefore retranslate from the Russian which will in no way improve the text.
    It reads:

    [Reprint of the 1882 Russian Edition ]
    At about the same date, a new Polish version appeared in Geneva: Manifest Kommunistyczny.
    Furthermore, a new Danish translation has appeared in the Socialdemokratisk Bibliothek,
    Copenhagen, 1885. Unfortunately, it is not quite complete; certain essential passages, which seem
    to have presented difficulties to the translator, have been omitted, and, in addition, there are signs
    of carelessness here and there, which are all the more unpleasantly conspicuous since the
    translation indicates that had the translator taken a little more pains, he would have done an
    excellent piece of work.
    A new French version appeared in 1886, in Le Socialiste of Paris; it is the best published to date.
    From this latter, a Spanish version was published the same year in El Socialista of Madrid, and
    then reissued in pamphlet form: Manifesto del Partido Communista por Carlos Marx y F. Engels,
    Madrid, Administracion de El Socialista, Hernan Cortes 8.
    As a matter of curiosity, I may mention that in 1887 the manuscript of an Armenian translation
    was offered to a publisher in Constantinople. But the good man did not have the courage to
    publish something bearing the name of Marx and suggested that the translator set down his own
    name as author, which the latter however declined.
    After one, and then another, of the more or less inaccurate American translations had been
    repeatedly reprinted in England, an authentic version at last appeared in 1888. This was my friend
    Samuel Moore, and we went through it together once more before it went to press. It is entitled:
    Manifesto of the Communist Party, by Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. Authorized English
    translation, edited and annotated by Frederick Engels, 1888, London, William Reeves, 185 Fleet
    Street, E.C. I have added some of the notes of that edition to the present one.
    The Manifesto has had a history of its own. Greeted with enthusiasm, at the time of its
    appearance, by the not at all numerous vanguard of scientific socialism (as is proved by the
    translations mentioned in the first place), it was soon forced into the background by the reaction
    that began with the defeat of the Paris workers in June 1848, and was finally excommunicated
    “by law” in the conviction of the Cologne Communists in November 1852. With the
    disappearance from the public scene of the workers’ movement that had begun with the February
    Revolution, the Manifesto too passed into the background.
    When the European workers had again gathered sufficient strength for a new onslaught upon the
    power of the ruling classes, the International Working Men’ s Association came into being. Its
    aim was to weld together into one huge army the whole militant working class of Europe and
    America. Therefore it could not set out from the principles laid down in the Manifesto. It was
    bound to have a programme which would not shut the door on the English trade unions, the
    French, Belgian, Italian, and Spanish Proudhonists, and the German Lassalleans. This programme
    – the considerations underlying the Statutes of the International – was drawn up by Marx with a
    master hand acknowledged even by the Bakunin and the anarchists. For the ultimate final triumph

    11 Preface to the 1890 German Edition

    of the ideas set forth in the Manifesto, Marx relied solely upon the intellectual development of the
    working class, as it necessarily has to ensue from united action and discussion. The events and
    vicissitudes in the struggle against capital, the defeats even more than the successes, could not but
    demonstrate to the fighters the inadequacy of their former universal panaceas, and make their
    minds more receptive to a thorough understanding of the true conditions for working-class
    emancipation. And Marx was right. The working class of 1874, at the dissolution of the
    International, was altogether different from that of 1864, at its foundation. Proudhonism in the
    Latin countries, and the specific Lassalleanism in Germany, were dying out; and even the ten
    arch-conservative English trade unions were gradually approaching the point where, in 1887, the
    chairman of their Swansea Congress could say in their name: “Continental socialism has lost its
    terror for us.” Yet by 1887 continental socialism was almost exclusively the theory heralded in
    the Manifesto. Thus, to a certain extent, the history of the Manifesto reflects the history of the
    modern working-class movement since 1848. At present, it is doubtless the most widely
    circulated, the most international product of all socialist literature, the common programme of
    many millions of workers of all countries from Siberia to California.
    Nevertheless, when it appeared, we could not have called it a socialist manifesto. In 1847, two
    kinds of people were considered socialists. On the one hand were the adherents of the various
    utopian systems, notably the Owenites in England and the Fourierists in France, both of whom, at
    that date, had already dwindled to mere sects gradually dying out. On the other, the manifold
    types of social quacks who wanted to eliminate social abuses through their various universal
    panaceas and all kinds of patch-work, without hurting capital and profit in the least. In both cases,
    people who stood outside the labor movement and who looked for support rather to the
    “educated” classes. The section of the working class, however, which demanded a radical
    reconstruction of society, convinced that mere political revolutions were not enough, then called
    itself Communist. It was still a rough-hewn, only instinctive and frequently somewhat crude
    communism. Yet, it was powerful enough to bring into being two systems of utopian communism
    – in France, the “Icarian” communists of Cabet, and in Germany that of Weitling. Socialism in
    1847 signified a bourgeois movement, communism a working-class movement. Socialism was,
    on the Continent at least, quite respectable, whereas communism was the very opposite. And
    since we were very decidedly of the opinion as early as then that “the emancipation of the
    workers must be the task of the working class itself,” [from the General Rules of the
    International] we could have no hesitation as to which of the two names we should choose. Nor
    has it ever occurred to us to repudiate it.
    “Working men of all countries, unite!” But few voices responded when we proclaimed these
    words to the world 42 years ago, on the eve of the first Paris Revolution in which the proletariat
    came out with the demands of its own. On September 28, 1864, however, the proletarians of most
    of the Western European countries joined hands in the International Working Men’ s Association
    of glorious memory. True, the International itself lived only nine years. But that the eternal union
    of the proletarians of all countries created by it is still alive and lives stronger than ever, there is
    no better witness than this day. Because today3, as I write these lines, the European and American
    proletariat is reviewing its fighting forces, mobilized for the first time, mobilized as one army,
    under one flag, for one immediate aim: the standard eight-hour working day to be established by
    legal enactment, as proclaimed by the Geneva Congress of the International in 1866, and again by
    the Paris Workers’ Congress of 1889. And today’ s spectacle will open the eyes of the capitalists
    and landlords of all countries to the fact that today the proletarians of all countries are united
    indeed.
    If only Marx were still by my side to see this with his own eyes!

    Frederick Engels
    May 1, 1890, London

    Preface to The 1892 Polish Edition

    The fact that a new Polish edition of the Communist Manifesto has become necessary gives rise
    to various thoughts.
    First of all, it is noteworthy that of late the Manifesto has become an index, as it were, of the
    development of large-scale industry on the European continent. In proportion as large-scale
    industry expands in a given country, the demand grows among the workers of that country for
    enlightenment regarding their position as the working class in relation to the possessing classes,
    the socialist movement spreads among them and the demand for the Manifesto increases. Thus,
    not only the state of the labour movement but also the degree of development of large-scale
    industry can be measured with fair accuracy in every country by the number of copies of the
    Manifesto circulated in the language of that country.
    Accordingly, the new Polish edition indicates a decided progress of Polish industry. And there
    can be no doubt whatever that this progress since the previous edition published ten years ago has
    actually taken place. Russian Poland, Congress Poland, has become the big industrial region of
    the Russian Empire. Whereas Russian large-scale industry is scattered sporadically – a part round
    the Gulf of Finland, another in the centre (Moscow and Vladimir), a third along the coasts of the
    Black and Azov seas, and still others elsewhere – Polish industry has been packed into a
    relatively small area and enjoys both the advantages and disadvantages arising from such
    concentration. The competing Russian manufacturers acknowledged the advantages when they
    demanded protective tariffs against Poland, in spit of their ardent desire to transform the Poles
    into Russians. The disadvantages – for the Polish manufacturers and the Russian government –
    are manifest in the rapid spread of socialist ideas among the Polish workers and in the growing
    demand for the Manifesto.
    But the rapid development of Polish industry, outstripping that of Russia, is in its turn a new
    proof of the inexhaustible vitality of the Polish people and a new guarantee of its impending
    national restoration. And the restoration of an independent and strong Poland is a matter which
    concerns not only the Poles but all of us. A sincere international collaboration of the European
    nations is possible only if each of these nations is fully autonomous in its own house. The
    Revolution of 1848, which under the banner of the proletariat, after all, merely let the proletarian
    fighters do the work of the bourgeoisie, also secured the independence of Italy, Germany and
    Hungary through its testamentary executors, Louis Bonaparte and Bismarck; but Poland, which
    since 1792 had done more for the Revolution than all these three together, was left to its own
    resources when it succumbed in 1863 to a tenfold greater Russian force. The nobility could
    neither maintain nor regain Polish independence; today, to the bourgeoisie, this independence is,
    to say the last, immaterial. Nevertheless, it is a necessity for the harmonious collaboration of the
    European nations. It can be gained only by the young Polish proletariat, and in its hands it is
    secure. For the workers of all the rest of Europe need the independence of Poland just as much as
    the Polish workers themselves.

    F. Engels
    London, February 10, 1892

    Preface to The 1893 Italian Edition

    Publication of the Manifesto of the Communist Party coincided, one may say, with March 18,
    1848, the day of the revolution in Milan and Berlin, which were armed uprisings of the two
    nations situated in the centre, the one, of the continent of Europe, the other, of the Mediterranean;
    two nations until then enfeebled by division and internal strife, and thus fallen under foreign
    domination. While Italy was subject to the Emperor of Austria, Germany underwent the yoke, not
    less effective though more indirect, of the Tsar of all the Russias. The consequences of March 18,
    1848, freed both Italy and Germany from this disgrace; if from 1848 to 1871 these two great
    nations were reconstituted and somehow again put on their own, it was as Karl Marx used to say,
    because the men who suppressed the Revolution of 1848 were, nevertheless, its testamentary
    executors in spite of themselves.
    Everywhere that revolution was the work of the working class; it was the latter that built the
    barricades and paid with its lifeblood. Only the Paris workers, in overthrowing the government,
    had the very definite intention of overthrowing the bourgeois regime. But conscious though they
    were of the fatal antagonism existing between their own class and the bourgeoisie, still, neither
    the economic progress of the country nor the intellectual development of the mass of French
    workers had as yet reached the stage which would have made a social reconstruction possible. In
    the final analysis, therefore, the fruits of the revolution were reaped by the capitalist class. In the
    other countries, in Italy, in Germany, in Austria, the workers, from the very outset, did nothing
    but raise the bourgeoisie to power. But in any country the rule of the bourgeoisie is impossible
    without national independence Therefore, the Revolution of 1848 had to bring in its train the
    unity and autonomy of the nations that had lacked them up to then: Italy, Germany, Hungary.
    Poland will follow in turn.
    Thus, if the Revolution of 1848 was not a socialist revolution, it paved the way, prepared the
    ground for the latter. Through the impetus given to large-scaled industry in all countries, the
    bourgeois regime during the last forty-five years has everywhere created a numerous,
    concentrated and powerful proletariat. It has thus raised, to use the language of the Manifesto, its
    own grave-diggers. Without restoring autonomy and unity to each nation, it will be impossible to
    achieve the international union of the proletariat, or the peaceful and intelligent co-operation of
    these nations toward common aims. Just imagine joint international action by the Italian,
    Hungarian, German, Polish and Russian workers under the political conditions preceding 1848!
    The battles fought in 1848 were thus not fought in vain. Nor have the forty-five years separating
    us from that revolutionary epoch passed to no purpose. The fruits are ripening, and all I wish is
    that the publication of this Italian translation may augur as well for the victory of the Italian
    proletariat as the publication of the original did for the international revolution.
    The Manifesto does full justice to the revolutionary part played by capitalism in the past. The first
    capitalist nation was Italy. The close of the feudal Middle Ages, and the opening of the modern
    capitalist era are marked by a colossal figured: an Italian, Dante, both the last poet of the Middle
    Ages and the first poet of modern times. Today, as in 1300, a new historical era is approaching.
    Will Italy give us the new Dante, who will mark the hour of birth of this new, proletarian era?

    Frederick Engels
    London, February 1, 1893

    Manifesto of the Communist Party

    A spectre is haunting Europe – the spectre of communism. All the powers of old Europe have
    entered into a holy alliance to exorcise this spectre: Pope and Tsar, Metternich and Guizot,
    French Radicals and German police-spies.
    Where is the party in opposition that has not been decried as communistic by its opponents in
    power? Where is the opposition that has not hurled back the branding reproach of communism,
    against the more advanced opposition parties, as well as against its reactionary adversaries?
    Two things result from this fact:

    I. Communism is already acknowledged by all European powers to be itself a
    power.
    II. It is high time that Communists should openly, in the face of the whole world,
    publish their views, their aims, their tendencies, and meet this nursery tale of the
    Spectre of Communism with a manifesto of the party itself.

    To this end, Communists of various nationalities have assembled in London and sketched the
    following manifesto, to be published in the English, French, German, Italian, Flemish and Danish
    languages.

    I. Bourgeois and Proletarians*

    The history of all hitherto existing society† is the history of class struggles.
    Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guild-master‡ and journeyman, in a
    word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, carried on an
    uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary
    reconstitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes.
    In the earlier epochs of history, we find almost everywhere a complicated arrangement of society
    into various orders, a manifold gradation of social rank. In ancient Rome we have patricians,
    knights, plebeians, slaves; in the Middle Ages, feudal lords, vassals, guild-masters, journeymen,
    apprentices, serfs; in almost all of these classes, again, subordinate gradations.
    The modern bourgeois society that has sprouted from the ruins of feudal society has not done
    away with class antagonisms. It has but established new classes, new conditions of oppression,
    new forms of struggle in place of the old ones.

    * By bourgeoisie is meant the class of modern capitalists, owners of the means of social production and employers of
    wage labour. By proletariat, the class of modern wage labourers who, having no means of production of their own, are
    reduced to selling their labour power in order to live. [Engels, 1888 English edition]
    † That is, all written history. In 1847, the pre-history of society, the social organisation existing previous to recorded
    history, all but unknown. Since then, August von Haxthausen (1792-1866) discovered common ownership of land in
    Russia, Georg Ludwig von Maurer proved it to be the social foundation from which all Teutonic races started in history,
    and, by and by, village communities were found to be, or to have been, the primitive form of society everywhere from
    India to Ireland. The inner organisation of this primitive communistic society was laid bare, in its typical form, by
    Lewis Henry Morgan’s (1818-1861) crowning discovery of the true nature of the gens and its relation to the tribe. With
    the dissolution of the primeval communities, society begins to be differentiated into separate and finally antagonistic
    classes. I have attempted to retrace this dissolution in The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, second
    edition, Stuttgart, 1886. [Engels, 1888 English Edition and 1890 German Edition (with the last sentence omitted)]
    ‡ Guild-master, that is, a full member of a guild, a master within, not a head of a guild. [Engels, 1888 English Edition]

    http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1884/origin-family/index.htm

    15 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie, possesses, however, this distinct feature: it has
    simplified class antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two great
    hostile camps, into two great classes directly facing each other – Bourgeoisie and Proletariat.
    From the serfs of the Middle Ages sprang the chartered burghers of the earliest towns. From these
    burgesses the first elements of the bourgeoisie were developed.
    The discovery of America, the rounding of the Cape, opened up fresh ground for the rising
    bourgeoisie. The East-Indian and Chinese markets, the colonisation of America, trade with the
    colonies, the increase in the means of exchange and in commodities generally, gave to commerce,
    to navigation, to industry, an impulse never before known, and thereby, to the revolutionary
    element in the tottering feudal society, a rapid development.
    The feudal system of industry, in which industrial production was monopolised by closed guilds,
    now no longer sufficed for the growing wants of the new markets. The manufacturing system
    took its place. The guild-masters were pushed on one side by the manufacturing middle class;
    division of labour between the different corporate guilds vanished in the face of division of labour
    in each single workshop.
    Meantime the markets kept ever growing, the demand ever rising. Even manufacturer no longer
    sufficed. Thereupon, steam and machinery revolutionised industrial production. The place of
    manufacture was taken by the giant, Modern Industry; the place of the industrial middle class by
    industrial millionaires, the leaders of the whole industrial armies, the modern bourgeois.
    Modern industry has established the world market, for which the discovery of America paved the
    way. This market has given an immense development to commerce, to navigation, to
    communication by land. This development has, in its turn, reacted on the extension of industry;
    and in proportion as industry, commerce, navigation, railways extended, in the same proportion
    the bourgeoisie developed, increased its capital, and pushed into the background every class
    handed down from the Middle Ages.
    We see, therefore, how the modern bourgeoisie is itself the product of a long course of
    development, of a series of revolutions in the modes of production and of exchange.
    Each step in the development of the bourgeoisie was accompanied by a corresponding political
    advance of that class. An oppressed class under the sway of the feudal nobility, an armed and
    self-governing association in the medieval commune*: here independent urban republic (as in
    Italy and Germany); there taxable “third estate” of the monarchy (as in France); afterwards, in the
    period of manufacturing proper, serving either the semi-feudal or the absolute monarchy as a
    counterpoise against the nobility, and, in fact, cornerstone of the great monarchies in general, the
    bourgeoisie has at last, since the establishment of Modern Industry and of the world market,
    conquered for itself, in the modern representative State, exclusive political sway. The executive
    of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole
    bourgeoisie.
    The bourgeoisie, historically, has played a most revolutionary part.
    The bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to all feudal, patriarchal,
    idyllic relations. It has pitilessly torn asunder the motley feudal ties that bound man to his
    “natural superiors”, and has left remaining no other nexus between man and man than naked self-
    interest, than callous “cash payment”. It has drowned the most heavenly ecstasies of religious

    * This was the name given their urban communities by the townsmen of Italy and France, after they had purchased or
    conquered their initial rights of self-government from their feudal lords. [Engels, 1890 German edition] “Commune”
    was the name taken in France by the nascent towns even before they had conquered from their feudal lords and masters
    local self-government and political rights as the “Third Estate.” Generally speaking, for the economical development of
    the bourgeoisie, England is here taken as the typical country, for its political development, France. [Engels, 1888
    English Edition]

    16 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    fervour, of chivalrous enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism, in the icy water of egotistical
    calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange value, and in place of the numberless
    indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up that single, unconscionable freedom – Free Trade. In
    one word, for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it has substituted naked,
    shameless, direct, brutal exploitation.
    The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo every occupation hitherto honoured and looked up to with
    reverent awe. It has converted the physician, the lawyer, the priest, the poet, the man of science,
    into its paid wage labourers.
    The bourgeoisie has torn away from the family its sentimental veil, and has reduced the family
    relation to a mere money relation.
    The bourgeoisie has disclosed how it came to pass that the brutal display of vigour in the Middle
    Ages, which reactionaries so much admire, found its fitting complement in the most slothful
    indolence. It has been the first to show what man’s activity can bring about. It has accomplished
    wonders far surpassing Egyptian pyramids, Roman aqueducts, and Gothic cathedrals; it has
    conducted expeditions that put in the shade all former Exoduses of nations and crusades.
    The bourgeoisie cannot exist without constantly revolutionising the instruments of production,
    and thereby the relations of production, and with them the whole relations of society.
    Conservation of the old modes of production in unaltered form, was, on the contrary, the first
    condition of existence for all earlier industrial classes. Constant revolutionising of production,
    uninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions, everlasting uncertainty and agitation
    distinguish the bourgeois epoch from all earlier ones. All fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their
    train of ancient and venerable prejudices and opinions, are swept away, all new-formed ones
    become antiquated before they can ossify. All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is
    profaned, and man is at last compelled to face with sober senses his real conditions of life, and his
    relations with his kind.
    The need of a constantly expanding market for its products chases the bourgeoisie over the entire
    surface of the globe. It must nestle everywhere, settle everywhere, establish connexions
    everywhere.
    The bourgeoisie has through its exploitation of the world market given a cosmopolitan character
    to production and consumption in every country. To the great chagrin of Reactionists, it has
    drawn from under the feet of industry the national ground on which it stood. All old-established
    national industries have been destroyed or are daily being destroyed. They are dislodged by new
    industries, whose introduction becomes a life and death question for all civilised nations, by
    industries that no longer work up indigenous raw material, but raw material drawn from the
    remotest zones; industries whose products are consumed, not only at home, but in every quarter
    of the globe. In place of the old wants, satisfied by the production of the country, we find new
    wants, requiring for their satisfaction the products of distant lands and climes. In place of the old
    local and national seclusion and self-sufficiency, we have intercourse in every direction, universal
    inter-dependence of nations. And as in material, so also in intellectual production. The intellectual
    creations of individual nations become common property. National one-sidedness and narrow-
    mindedness become more and more impossible, and from the numerous national and local
    literatures, there arises a world literature.
    The bourgeoisie, by the rapid improvement of all instruments of production, by the immensely
    facilitated means of communication, draws all, even the most barbarian, nations into civilisation.
    The cheap prices of commodities are the heavy artillery with which it batters down all Chinese
    walls, with which it forces the barbarians’ intensely obstinate hatred of foreigners to capitulate. It
    compels all nations, on pain of extinction, to adopt the bourgeois mode of production; it compels
    them to introduce what it calls civilisation into their midst, i.e., to become bourgeois themselves.
    In one word, it creates a world after its own image.

    17 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    The bourgeoisie has subjected the country to the rule of the towns. It has created enormous cities,
    has greatly increased the urban population as compared with the rural, and has thus rescued a
    considerable part of the population from the idiocy of rural life. Just as it has made the country
    dependent on the towns, so it has made barbarian and semi-barbarian countries dependent on the
    civilised ones, nations of peasants on nations of bourgeois, the East on the West.
    The bourgeoisie keeps more and more doing away with the scattered state of the population, of
    the means of production, and of property. It has agglomerated population, centralised the means
    of production, and has concentrated property in a few hands. The necessary consequence of this
    was political centralisation. Independent, or but loosely connected provinces, with separate
    interests, laws, governments, and systems of taxation, became lumped together into one nation,
    with one government, one code of laws, one national class-interest, one frontier, and one
    customs-tariff.
    The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce one hundred years, has created more massive and more
    colossal productive forces than have all preceding generations together. Subjection of Nature’s
    forces to man, machinery, application of chemistry to industry and agriculture, steam-navigation,
    railways, electric telegraphs, clearing of whole continents for cultivation, canalisation of rivers,
    whole populations conjured out of the ground – what earlier century had even a presentiment that
    such productive forces slumbered in the lap of social labour?
    We see then: the means of production and of exchange, on whose foundation the bourgeoisie built
    itself up, were generated in feudal society. At a certain stage in the development of these means
    of production and of exchange, the conditions under which feudal society produced and
    exchanged, the feudal organisation of agriculture and manufacturing industry, in one word, the
    feudal relations of property became no longer compatible with the already developed productive
    forces; they became so many fetters. They had to be burst asunder; they were burst asunder.
    Into their place stepped free competition, accompanied by a social and political constitution
    adapted in it, and the economic and political sway of the bourgeois class.
    A similar movement is going on before our own eyes. Modern bourgeois society, with its
    relations of production, of exchange and of property, a society that has conjured up such gigantic
    means of production and of exchange, is like the sorcerer who is no longer able to control the
    powers of the nether world whom he has called up by his spells. For many a decade past the
    history of industry and commerce is but the history of the revolt of modern productive forces
    against modern conditions of production, against the property relations that are the conditions for
    the existence of the bourgeois and of its rule. It is enough to mention the commercial crises that
    by their periodical return put the existence of the entire bourgeois society on its trial, each time
    more threateningly. In these crises, a great part not only of the existing products, but also of the
    previously created productive forces, are periodically destroyed. In these crises, there breaks out
    an epidemic that, in all earlier epochs, would have seemed an absurdity – the epidemic of over-
    production. Society suddenly finds itself put back into a state of momentary barbarism; it appears
    as if a famine, a universal war of devastation, had cut off the supply of every means of
    subsistence; industry and commerce seem to be destroyed; and why? Because there is too much
    civilisation, too much means of subsistence, too much industry, too much commerce. The
    productive forces at the disposal of society no longer tend to further the development of the
    conditions of bourgeois property; on the contrary, they have become too powerful for these
    conditions, by which they are fettered, and so soon as they overcome these fetters, they bring
    disorder into the whole of bourgeois society, endanger the existence of bourgeois property. The
    conditions of bourgeois society are too narrow to comprise the wealth created by them. And how
    does the bourgeoisie get over these crises? On the one hand by enforced destruction of a mass of
    productive forces; on the other, by the conquest of new markets, and by the more thorough
    exploitation of the old ones. That is to say, by paving the way for more extensive and more
    destructive crises, and by diminishing the means whereby crises are prevented.

    18 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    The weapons with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the ground are now turned against
    the bourgeoisie itself.
    But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called
    into existence the men who are to wield those weapons – the modern working class – the
    proletarians.
    In proportion as the bourgeoisie, i.e., capital, is developed, in the same proportion is the
    proletariat, the modern working class, developed – a class of labourers, who live only so long as
    they find work, and who find work only so long as their labour increases capital. These labourers,
    who must sell themselves piecemeal, are a commodity, like every other article of commerce, and
    are consequently exposed to all the vicissitudes of competition, to all the fluctuations of the
    market.
    Owing to the extensive use of machinery, and to the division of labour, the work of the
    proletarians has lost all individual character, and, consequently, all charm for the workman. He
    becomes an appendage of the machine, and it is only the most simple, most monotonous, and
    most easily acquired knack, that is required of him. Hence, the cost of production of a workman is
    restricted, almost entirely, to the means of subsistence that he requires for maintenance, and for
    the propagation of his race. But the price of a commodity, and therefore also of labour, is equal to
    its cost of production. In proportion, therefore, as the repulsiveness of the work increases, the
    wage decreases. Nay more, in proportion as the use of machinery and division of labour
    increases, in the same proportion the burden of toil also increases, whether by prolongation of the
    working hours, by the increase of the work exacted in a given time or by increased speed of
    machinery, etc.
    Modern Industry has converted the little workshop of the patriarchal master into the great factory
    of the industrial capitalist. Masses of labourers, crowded into the factory, are organised like
    soldiers. As privates of the industrial army they are placed under the command of a perfect
    hierarchy of officers and sergeants. Not only are they slaves of the bourgeois class, and of the
    bourgeois State; they are daily and hourly enslaved by the machine, by the overlooker, and, above
    all, by the individual bourgeois manufacturer himself. The more openly this despotism proclaims
    gain to be its end and aim, the more petty, the more hateful and the more embittering it is.
    The less the skill and exertion of strength implied in manual labour, in other words, the more
    modern industry becomes developed, the more is the labour of men superseded by that of women.
    Differences of age and sex have no longer any distinctive social validity for the working class.
    All are instruments of labour, more or less expensive to use, according to their age and sex.
    No sooner is the exploitation of the labourer by the manufacturer, so far, at an end, that he
    receives his wages in cash, than he is set upon by the other portions of the bourgeoisie, the
    landlord, the shopkeeper, the pawnbroker, etc.
    The lower strata of the middle class – the small tradespeople, shopkeepers, and retired tradesmen
    generally, the handicraftsmen and peasants – all these sink gradually into the proletariat, partly
    because their diminutive capital does not suffice for the scale on which Modern Industry is
    carried on, and is swamped in the competition with the large capitalists, partly because their
    specialised skill is rendered worthless by new methods of production. Thus the proletariat is
    recruited from all classes of the population.
    The proletariat goes through various stages of development. With its birth begins its struggle with
    the bourgeoisie. At first the contest is carried on by individual labourers, then by the workpeople
    of a factory, then by the operative of one trade, in one locality, against the individual bourgeois
    who directly exploits them. They direct their attacks not against the bourgeois conditions of
    production, but against the instruments of production themselves; they destroy imported wares
    that compete with their labour, they smash to pieces machinery, they set factories ablaze, they
    seek to restore by force the vanished status of the workman of the Middle Ages.

    19 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    At this stage, the labourers still form an incoherent mass scattered over the whole country, and
    broken up by their mutual competition. If anywhere they unite to form more compact bodies, this
    is not yet the consequence of their own active union, but of the union of the bourgeoisie, which
    class, in order to attain its own political ends, is compelled to set the whole proletariat in motion,
    and is moreover yet, for a time, able to do so. At this stage, therefore, the proletarians do not fight
    their enemies, but the enemies of their enemies, the remnants of absolute monarchy, the
    landowners, the non-industrial bourgeois, the petty bourgeois. Thus, the whole historical
    movement is concentrated in the hands of the bourgeoisie; every victory so obtained is a victory
    for the bourgeoisie.
    But with the development of industry, the proletariat not only increases in number; it becomes
    concentrated in greater masses, its strength grows, and it feels that strength more. The various
    interests and conditions of life within the ranks of the proletariat are more and more equalised, in
    proportion as machinery obliterates all distinctions of labour, and nearly everywhere reduces
    wages to the same low level. The growing competition among the bourgeois, and the resulting
    commercial crises, make the wages of the workers ever more fluctuating. The increasing
    improvement of machinery, ever more rapidly developing, makes their livelihood more and more
    precarious; the collisions between individual workmen and individual bourgeois take more and
    more the character of collisions between two classes. Thereupon, the workers begin to form
    combinations (Trades’ Unions) against the bourgeois; they club together in order to keep up the
    rate of wages; they found permanent associations in order to make provision beforehand for these
    occasional revolts. Here and there, the contest breaks out into riots.
    Now and then the workers are victorious, but only for a time. The real fruit of their battles lies,
    not in the immediate result, but in the ever expanding union of the workers. This union is helped
    on by the improved means of communication that are created by modern industry, and that place
    the workers of different localities in contact with one another. It was just this contact that was
    needed to centralise the numerous local struggles, all of the same character, into one national
    struggle between classes. But every class struggle is a political struggle. And that union, to attain
    which the burghers of the Middle Ages, with their miserable highways, required centuries, the
    modern proletarian, thanks to railways, achieve in a few years.
    This organisation of the proletarians into a class, and, consequently into a political party, is
    continually being upset again by the competition between the workers themselves. But it ever
    rises up again, stronger, firmer, mightier. It compels legislative recognition of particular interests
    of the workers, by taking advantage of the divisions among the bourgeoisie itself. Thus, the ten-
    hours’ bill in England was carried.
    Altogether collisions between the classes of the old society further, in many ways, the course of
    development of the proletariat. The bourgeoisie finds itself involved in a constant battle. At first
    with the aristocracy; later on, with those portions of the bourgeoisie itself, whose interests have
    become antagonistic to the progress of industry; at all time with the bourgeoisie of foreign
    countries. In all these battles, it sees itself compelled to appeal to the proletariat, to ask for help,
    and thus, to drag it into the political arena. The bourgeoisie itself, therefore, supplies the
    proletariat with its own elements of political and general education, in other words, it furnishes
    the proletariat with weapons for fighting the bourgeoisie.
    Further, as we have already seen, entire sections of the ruling class are, by the advance of
    industry, precipitated into the proletariat, or are at least threatened in their conditions of existence.
    These also supply the proletariat with fresh elements of enlightenment and progress.
    Finally, in times when the class struggle nears the decisive hour, the progress of dissolution going
    on within the ruling class, in fact within the whole range of old society, assumes such a violent,
    glaring character, that a small section of the ruling class cuts itself adrift, and joins the
    revolutionary class, the class that holds the future in its hands. Just as, therefore, at an earlier

    20 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    period, a section of the nobility went over to the bourgeoisie, so now a portion of the bourgeoisie
    goes over to the proletariat, and in particular, a portion of the bourgeois ideologists, who have
    raised themselves to the level of comprehending theoretically the historical movement as a whole.
    Of all the classes that stand face to face with the bourgeoisie today, the proletariat alone is a
    really revolutionary class. The other classes decay and finally disappear in the face of Modern
    Industry; the proletariat is its special and essential product.
    The lower middle class, the small manufacturer, the shopkeeper, the artisan, the peasant, all these
    fight against the bourgeoisie, to save from extinction their existence as fractions of the middle
    class. They are therefore not revolutionary, but conservative. Nay more, they are reactionary, for
    they try to roll back the wheel of history. If by chance, they are revolutionary, they are only so in
    view of their impending transfer into the proletariat; they thus defend not their present, but their
    future interests, they desert their own standpoint to place themselves at that of the proletariat.
    The “dangerous class”, [lumpenproletariat] the social scum, that passively rotting mass thrown
    off by the lowest layers of the old society, may, here and there, be swept into the movement by a
    proletarian revolution; its conditions of life, however, prepare it far more for the part of a bribed
    tool of reactionary intrigue.
    In the condition of the proletariat, those of old society at large are already virtually swamped. The
    proletarian is without property; his relation to his wife and children has no longer anything in
    common with the bourgeois family relations; modern industry labour, modern subjection to
    capital, the same in England as in France, in America as in Germany, has stripped him of every
    trace of national character. Law, morality, religion, are to him so many bourgeois prejudices,
    behind which lurk in ambush just as many bourgeois interests.
    All the preceding classes that got the upper hand sought to fortify their already acquired status by
    subjecting society at large to their conditions of appropriation. The proletarians cannot become
    masters of the productive forces of society, except by abolishing their own previous mode of
    appropriation, and thereby also every other previous mode of appropriation. They have nothing of
    their own to secure and to fortify; their mission is to destroy all previous securities for, and
    insurances of, individual property.
    All previous historical movements were movements of minorities, or in the interest of minorities.
    The proletarian movement is the self-conscious, independent movement of the immense majority,
    in the interest of the immense majority. The proletariat, the lowest stratum of our present society,
    cannot stir, cannot raise itself up, without the whole superincumbent strata of official society
    being sprung into the air.
    Though not in substance, yet in form, the struggle of the proletariat with the bourgeoisie is at first
    a national struggle. The proletariat of each country must, of course, first of all settle matters with
    its own bourgeoisie.
    In depicting the most general phases of the development of the proletariat, we traced the more or
    less veiled civil war, raging within existing society, up to the point where that war breaks out into
    open revolution, and where the violent overthrow of the bourgeoisie lays the foundation for the
    sway of the proletariat.
    Hitherto, every form of society has been based, as we have already seen, on the antagonism of
    oppressing and oppressed classes. But in order to oppress a class, certain conditions must be
    assured to it under which it can, at least, continue its slavish existence. The serf, in the period of
    serfdom, raised himself to membership in the commune, just as the petty bourgeois, under the
    yoke of the feudal absolutism, managed to develop into a bourgeois. The modern labourer, on the
    contrary, instead of rising with the process of industry, sinks deeper and deeper below the
    conditions of existence of his own class. He becomes a pauper, and pauperism develops more
    rapidly than population and wealth. And here it becomes evident, that the bourgeoisie is unfit any
    longer to be the ruling class in society, and to impose its conditions of existence upon society as

    21 Manifesto of the Communist Party

    an over-riding law. It is unfit to rule because it is incompetent to assure an existence to its slave
    within his slavery, because it cannot help letting him sink into such a state, that it has to feed him,
    instead of being fed by him. Society can no longer live under this bourgeoisie, in other words, its
    existence is no longer compatible with society.
    The essential conditions for the existence and for the sway of the bourgeois class is the formation
    and augmentation of capital; the condition for capital is wage-labour. Wage-labour rests
    exclusively on competition between the labourers. The advance of industry, whose involuntary
    promoter is the bourgeoisie, replaces the isolation of the labourers, due to competition, by the
    revolutionary combination, due to association. The development of Modern Industry, therefore,
    cuts from under its feet the very foundation on which the bourgeoisie produces and appropriates
    products. What the bourgeoisie therefore produces, above all, are its own grave-diggers. Its fall
    and the victory of the proletariat are equally inevitable.

    II. Proletarians and Communists

    In what relation do the Communists stand to the proletarians as a whole?
    The Communists do not form a separate party opposed to the other working-class parties.
    They have no interests separate and apart from those of the proletariat as a whole.
    They do not set up any sectarian principles of their own, by which to shape and mould the
    proletarian movement.
    The Communists are distinguished from the other working-class parties by this only: 1. In the
    national struggles of the proletarians of the different countries, they point out and bring to the
    front the common interests of the entire proletariat, independently of all nationality. 2. In the
    various stages of development which the struggle of the working class against the bourgeoisie has
    to pass through, they always and everywhere represent the interests of the movement as a whole.
    The Communists, therefore, are on the one hand, practically, the most advanced and resolute
    section of the working-class parties of every country, that section which pushes forward all
    others; on the other hand, theoretically, they have over the great mass of the proletariat the
    advantage of clearly understanding the line of march, the conditions, and the ultimate general
    results of the proletarian movement.
    The immediate aim of the Communists is the same as that of all other proletarian parties:
    formation of the proletariat into a class, overthrow of the bourgeois supremacy, conquest of
    political power by the proletariat.
    The theoretical conclusions of the Communists are in no way based on ideas or principles that
    have been invented, or discovered, by this or that would-be universal reformer.
    They merely express, in general terms, actual relations springing from an existing class struggle,
    from a historical movement going on under our very eyes. The abolition of existing property
    relations is not at all a distinctive feature of communism.
    All property relations in the past have continually been subject to historical change consequent
    upon the change in historical conditions.
    The French Revolution, for example, abolished feudal property in favour of bourgeois property.
    The distinguishing feature of Communism is not the abolition of property generally, but the
    abolition of bourgeois property. But modern bourgeois private property is the final and most
    complete expression of the system of producing and appropriating products, that is based on class
    antagonisms, on the exploitation of the many by the few.
    In this sense, the theory of the Communists may be summed up in the single sentence: Abolition
    of private property.
    We Communists have been reproached with the desire of abolishing the right of personally
    acquiring property as the fruit of a man’s own labour, which property is alleged to be the
    groundwork of all personal freedom, activity and independence.
    Hard-won, self-acquired, self-earned property! Do you mean the property of petty artisan and of
    the small peasant, a form of property that preceded the bourgeois form? There is no need to
    abolish that; the development of industry has to a great extent already destroyed it, and is still
    destroying it daily.
    Or do you mean the modern bourgeois private property?
    But does wage-labour create any property for the labourer? Not a bit. It creates capital, i.e., that
    kind of property which exploits wage-labour, and which cannot increase except upon condition of
    begetting a new supply of wage-labour for fresh exploitation. Property, in its present form, is

    23 Chapter II: Proletarians and Communists

    based on the antagonism of capital and wage labour. Let us examine both sides of this
    antagonism.
    To be a capitalist, is to have not only a purely personal, but a social status in production. Capital
    is a collective product, and only by the united action of many members, nay, in the last resort,
    only by the united action of all members of society, can it be set in motion.
    Capital is therefore not only personal; it is a social power.
    When, therefore, capital is converted into common property, into the property of all members of
    society, personal property is not thereby transformed into social property. It is only the social
    character of the property that is changed. It loses its class character.
    Let us now take wage-labour.
    The average price of wage-labour is the minimum wage, i.e., that quantum of the means of
    subsistence which is absolutely requisite to keep the labourer in bare existence as a labourer.
    What, therefore, the wage-labourer appropriates by means of his labour, merely suffices to
    prolong and reproduce a bare existence. We by no means intend to abolish this personal
    appropriation of the products of labour, an appropriation that is made for the maintenance and
    reproduction of human life, and that leaves no surplus wherewith to command the labour of
    others. All that we want to do away with is the miserable character of this appropriation, under
    which the labourer lives merely to increase capital, and is allowed to live only in so far as the
    interest of the ruling class requires it.
    In bourgeois society, living labour is but a means to increase accumulated labour. In Communist
    society, accumulated labour is but a means to widen, to enrich, to promote the existence of the
    labourer.
    In bourgeois society, therefore, the past dominates the present; in Communist society, the present
    dominates the past. In bourgeois society capital is independent and has individuality, while the
    living person is dependent and has no individuality.
    And the abolition of this state of things is called by the bourgeois, abolition of individuality and
    freedom! And rightly so. The abolition of bourgeois individuality, bourgeois independence, and
    bourgeois freedom is undoubtedly aimed at.
    By freedom is meant, under the present bourgeois conditions of production, free trade, free
    selling and buying.
    But if selling and buying disappears, free selling and buying disappears also. This talk about free
    selling and buying, and all the other “brave words” of our bourgeois about freedom in general,
    have a meaning, if any, only in contrast with restricted selling and buying, with the fettered
    traders of the Middle Ages, but have no meaning when opposed to the Communistic abolition of
    buying and selling, of the bourgeois conditions of production, and of the bourgeoisie itself.
    You are horrified at our intending to do away with private property. But in your existing society,
    private property is already done away with for nine-tenths of the population; its existence for the
    few is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of those nine-tenths. You reproach us,
    therefore, with intending to do away with a form of property, the necessary condition for whose
    existence is the non-existence of any property for the immense majority of society.
    In one word, you reproach us with intending to do away with your property. Precisely so; that is
    just what we intend.
    From the moment when labour can no longer be converted into capital, money, or rent, into a
    social power capable of being monopolised, i.e., from the moment when individual property can
    no longer be transformed into bourgeois property, into capital, from that moment, you say,
    individuality vanishes.

    24 Chapter II: Proletarians and Communists

    You must, therefore, confess that by “individual” you mean no other person than the bourgeois,
    than the middle-class owner of property. This person must, indeed, be swept out of the way, and
    made impossible.
    Communism deprives no man of the power to appropriate the products of society; all that it does
    is to deprive him of the power to subjugate the labour of others by means of such appropriations.
    It has been objected that upon the abolition of private property, all work will cease, and universal
    laziness will overtake us.
    According to this, bourgeois society ought long ago to have gone to the dogs through sheer
    idleness; for those of its members who work, acquire nothing, and those who acquire anything do
    not work. The whole of this objection is but another expression of the tautology: that there can no
    longer be any wage-labour when there is no longer any capital.
    All objections urged against the Communistic mode of producing and appropriating material
    products, have, in the same way, been urged against the Communistic mode of producing and
    appropriating intellectual products. Just as, to the bourgeois, the disappearance of class property
    is the disappearance of production itself, so the disappearance of class culture is to him identical
    with the disappearance of all culture.
    That culture, the loss of which he laments, is, for the enormous majority, a mere training to act as
    a machine.
    But don’t wrangle with us so long as you apply, to our intended abolition of bourgeois property,
    the standard of your bourgeois notions of freedom, culture, law, &c. Your very ideas are but the
    outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your
    jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will whose essential character
    and direction are determined by the economical conditions of existence of your class.
    The selfish misconception that induces you to transform into eternal laws of nature and of reason,
    the social forms springing from your present mode of production and form of property –
    historical relations that rise and disappear in the progress of production – this misconception you
    share with every ruling class that has preceded you. What you see clearly in the case of ancient
    property, what you admit in the case of feudal property, you are of course forbidden to admit in
    the case of your own bourgeois form of property.
    Abolition [Aufhebung] of the family! Even the most radical flare up at this infamous proposal of
    the Communists.
    On what foundation is the present family, the bourgeois family, based? On capital, on private
    gain. In its completely developed form, this family exists only among the bourgeoisie. But this
    state of things finds its complement in the practical absence of the family among the proletarians,
    and in public prostitution.
    The bourgeois family will vanish as a matter of course when its complement vanishes, and both
    will vanish with the vanishing of capital.
    Do you charge us with wanting to stop the exploitation of children by their parents? To this crime
    we plead guilty.
    But, you say, we destroy the most hallowed of relations, when we replace home education by
    social.
    And your education! Is not that also social, and determined by the social conditions under which
    you educate, by the intervention direct or indirect, of society, by means of schools, &c.? The
    Communists have not invented the intervention of society in education; they do but seek to alter
    the character of that intervention, and to rescue education from the influence of the ruling class.
    The bourgeois clap-trap about the family and education, about the hallowed co-relation of parents
    and child, becomes all the more disgusting, the more, by the action of Modern Industry, all the

    25 Chapter II: Proletarians and Communists

    family ties among the proletarians are torn asunder, and their children transformed into simple
    articles of commerce and instruments of labour.
    But you Communists would introduce community of women, screams the bourgeoisie in chorus.
    The bourgeois sees his wife a mere instrument of production. He hears that the instruments of
    production are to be exploited in common, and, naturally, can come to no other conclusion that
    the lot of being common to all will likewise fall to the women.
    He has not even a suspicion that the real point aimed at is to do away with the status of women as
    mere instruments of production.
    For the rest, nothing is more ridiculous than the virtuous indignation of our bourgeois at the
    community of women which, they pretend, is to be openly and officially established by the
    Communists. The Communists have no need to introduce community of women; it has existed
    almost from time immemorial.
    Our bourgeois, not content with having wives and daughters of their proletarians at their disposal,
    not to speak of common prostitutes, take the greatest pleasure in seducing each other’s wives.
    Bourgeois marriage is, in reality, a system of wives in common and thus, at the most, what the
    Communists might possibly be reproached with is that they desire to introduce, in substitution for
    a hypocritically concealed, an openly legalised community of women. For the rest, it is self-
    evident that the abolition of the present system of production must bring with it the abolition of
    the community of women springing from that system, i.e., of prostitution both public and private.
    The Communists are further reproached with desiring to abolish countries and nationality.
    The working men have no country. We cannot take from them what they have not got. Since the
    proletariat must first of all acquire political supremacy, must rise to be the leading class of the
    nation, must constitute itself the nation, it is so far, itself national, though not in the bourgeois
    sense of the word.
    National differences and antagonism between peoples are daily more and more vanishing, owing
    to the development of the bourgeoisie, to freedom of commerce, to the world market, to
    uniformity in the mode of production and in the conditions of life corresponding thereto.
    The supremacy of the proletariat will cause them to vanish still faster. United action, of the
    leading civilised countries at least, is one of the first conditions for the emancipation of the
    proletariat.
    In proportion as the exploitation of one individual by another will also be put an end to, the
    exploitation of one nation by another will also be put an end to. In proportion as the antagonism
    between classes within the nation vanishes, the hostility of one nation to another will come to an
    end.
    The charges against Communism made from a religious, a philosophical and, generally, from an
    ideological standpoint, are not deserving of serious examination.
    Does it require deep intuition to comprehend that man’s ideas, views, and conception, in one
    word, man’s consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of his material
    existence, in his social relations and in his social life?
    What else does the history of ideas prove, than that intellectual production changes its character
    in proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of each age have ever been the
    ideas of its ruling class.
    When people speak of the ideas that revolutionise society, they do but express that fact that
    within the old society the elements of a new one have been created, and that the dissolution of the
    old ideas keeps even pace with the dissolution of the old conditions of existence.
    When the ancient world was in its last throes, the ancient religions were overcome by
    Christianity. When Christian ideas succumbed in the 18th century to rationalist ideas, feudal

    26 Chapter II: Proletarians and Communists

    society fought its death battle with the then revolutionary bourgeoisie. The ideas of religious
    liberty and freedom of conscience merely gave expression to the sway of free competition within
    the domain of knowledge.
    “Undoubtedly,” it will be said, “religious, moral, philosophical, and juridical ideas have been
    modified in the course of historical development. But religion, morality, philosophy, political
    science, and law, constantly survived this change.”
    “There are, besides, eternal truths, such as Freedom, Justice, etc., that are common to all states of
    society. But Communism abolishes eternal truths, it abolishes all religion, and all morality,
    instead of constituting them on a new basis; it therefore acts in contradiction to all past historical
    experience.”
    What does this accusation reduce itself to? The history of all past society has consisted in the
    development of class antagonisms, antagonisms that assumed different forms at different epochs.
    But whatever form they may have taken, one fact is common to all past ages, viz., the exploitation
    of one part of society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social consciousness of past ages,
    despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays, moves within certain common forms, or general
    ideas, which cannot completely vanish except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms.
    The Communist revolution is the most radical rupture with traditional property relations; no
    wonder that its development involved the most radical rupture with traditional ideas.
    But let us have done with the bourgeois objections to Communism.
    We have seen above, that the first step in the revolution by the working class is to raise the
    proletariat to the position of ruling class to win the battle of democracy.
    The proletariat will use its political supremacy to wrest, by degree, all capital from the
    bourgeoisie, to centralise all instruments of production in the hands of the State, i.e., of the
    proletariat organised as the ruling class; and to increase the total productive forces as rapidly as
    possible.
    Of course, in the beginning, this cannot be effected except by means of despotic inroads on the
    rights of property, and on the conditions of bourgeois production; by means of measures,
    therefore, which appear economically insufficient and untenable, but which, in the course of the
    movement, outstrip themselves, necessitate further inroads upon the old social order, and are
    unavoidable as a means of entirely revolutionising the mode of production.
    These measures will, of course, be different in different countries.
    Nevertheless, in most advanced countries, the following will be pretty generally applicable.

    1. Abolition of property in land and application of all rents of land to public
    purposes.
    2. A heavy progressive or graduated income tax.
    3. Abolition of all rights of inheritance.
    4. Confiscation of the property of all emigrants and rebels.
    5. Centralisation of credit in the hands of the state, by means of a national bank
    with State capital and an exclusive monopoly.
    6. Centralisation of the means of communication and transport in the hands of the
    State.
    7. Extension of factories and instruments of production owned by the State; the
    bringing into cultivation of waste-lands, and the improvement of the soil generally
    in accordance with a common plan.
    8. Equal liability of all to work. Establishment of industrial armies, especially for
    agriculture.
    9. Combination of agriculture with manufacturing industries; gradual abolition of
    all the distinction between town and country by a more equable distribution of the

    27 Chapter II: Proletarians and Communists

    populace over the country.
    10. Free education for all children in public schools. Abolition of children’s
    factory labour in its present form. Combination of education with industrial
    production, &c, &c.

    When, in the course of development, class distinctions have disappeared, and all production has
    been concentrated in the hands of a vast association of the whole nation, the public power will
    lose its political character. Political power, properly so called, is merely the organised power of
    one class for oppressing another. If the proletariat during its contest with the bourgeoisie is
    compelled, by the force of circumstances, to organise itself as a class, if, by means of a
    revolution, it makes itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps away by force the old conditions
    of production, then it will, along with these conditions, have swept away the conditions for the
    existence of class antagonisms and of classes generally, and will thereby have abolished its own
    supremacy as a class.
    In place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class antagonisms, we shall have an
    association, in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of
    all.

    III. Socialist and Communist Literature

    1. Reactionary Socialism

    A. Feudal Socialism
    Owing to their historical position, it became the vocation of the aristocracies of France and
    England to write pamphlets against modern bourgeois society. In the French Revolution of July
    1830, and in the English reform agitation4, these aristocracies again succumbed to the hateful
    upstart. Thenceforth, a serious political struggle was altogether out of the question. A literary
    battle alone remained possible. But even in the domain of literature the old cries of the restoration
    period had become impossible.*
    In order to arouse sympathy, the aristocracy was obliged to lose sight, apparently, of its own
    interests, and to formulate their indictment against the bourgeoisie in the interest of the exploited
    working class alone. Thus, the aristocracy took their revenge by singing lampoons on their new
    masters and whispering in his ears sinister prophesies of coming catastrophe.
    In this way arose feudal Socialism: half lamentation, half lampoon; half an echo of the past, half
    menace of the future; at times, by its bitter, witty and incisive criticism, striking the bourgeoisie
    to the very heart’s core; but always ludicrous in its effect, through total incapacity to comprehend
    the march of modern history.
    The aristocracy, in order to rally the people to them, waved the proletarian alms-bag in front for a
    banner. But the people, so often as it joined them, saw on their hindquarters the old feudal coats
    of arms, and deserted with loud and irreverent laughter.
    One section of the French Legitimists and “Young England” exhibited this spectacle.
    In pointing out that their mode of exploitation was different to that of the bourgeoisie, the
    feudalists forget that they exploited under circumstances and conditions that were quite different
    and that are now antiquated. In showing that, under their rule, the modern proletariat never
    existed, they forget that the modern bourgeoisie is the necessary offspring of their own form of
    society.
    For the rest, so little do they conceal the reactionary character of their criticism that their chief
    accusation against the bourgeois amounts to this, that under the bourgeois régime a class is being
    developed which is destined to cut up root and branch the old order of society.
    What they upbraid the bourgeoisie with is not so much that it creates a proletariat as that it creates
    a revolutionary proletariat.
    In political practice, therefore, they join in all coercive measures against the working class; and in
    ordinary life, despite their high-falutin phrases, they stoop to pick up the golden apples dropped
    from the tree of industry, and to barter truth, love, and honour, for traffic in wool, beetroot-sugar,
    and potato spirits.†
    As the parson has ever gone hand in hand with the landlord, so has Clerical Socialism with
    Feudal Socialism.

    * Not the English Restoration (1660-1689), but the French Restoration (1814-1830). [Note by Engels to the English
    edition of 1888.]
    † This applies chiefly to Germany, where the landed aristocracy and squirearchy have large portions of their estates
    cultivated for their own account by stewards, and are, moreover, extensive beetroot-sugar manufacturers and distillers
    of potato spirits. The wealthier British aristocracy are, as yet, rather above that; but they, too, know how to make up for
    declining rents by lending their names to floaters or more or less shady joint-stock companies. [Note by Engels to the
    English edition of 1888.]

    29 Chapter III: Socialist and Communist Literature

    Nothing is easier than to give Christian asceticism a Socialist tinge. Has not Christianity
    declaimed against private property, against marriage, against the State? Has it not preached in the
    place of these, charity and poverty, celibacy and mortification of the flesh, monastic life and
    Mother Church? Christian Socialism is but the holy water with which the priest consecrates the
    heart-burnings of the aristocrat.

    B. Petty-Bourgeois Socialism
    The feudal aristocracy was not the only class that was ruined by the bourgeoisie, not the only
    class whose conditions of existence pined and perished in the atmosphere of modern bourgeois
    society. The medieval burgesses and the small peasant proprietors were the precursors of the
    modern bourgeoisie. In those countries which are but little developed, industrially and
    commercially, these two classes still vegetate side by side with the rising bourgeoisie.
    In countries where modern civilisation has become fully developed, a new class of petty
    bourgeois has been formed, fluctuating between proletariat and bourgeoisie, and ever renewing
    itself as a supplementary part of bourgeois society. The individual members of this class,
    however, are being constantly hurled down into the proletariat by the action of competition, and,
    as modern industry develops, they even see the moment approaching when they will completely
    disappear as an independent section of modern society, to be replaced in manufactures,
    agriculture and commerce, by overlookers, bailiffs and shopmen.
    In countries like France, where the peasants constitute far more than half of the population, it was
    natural that writers who sided with the proletariat against the bourgeoisie should use, in their
    criticism of the bourgeois régime, the standard of the peasant and petty bourgeois, and from the
    standpoint of these intermediate classes, should take up the cudgels for the working class. Thus
    arose petty-bourgeois Socialism. Sismondi was the head of this school, not only in France but
    also in England.
    This school of Socialism dissected with great acuteness the contradictions in the conditions of
    modern production. It laid bare the hypocritical apologies of economists. It proved,
    incontrovertibly, the disastrous effects of machinery and division of labour; the concentration of
    capital and land in a few hands; overproduction and crises; it pointed out the inevitable ruin of the
    petty bourgeois and peasant, the misery of the proletariat, the anarchy in production, the crying
    inequalities in the distribution of wealth, the industrial war of extermination between nations, the
    dissolution of old moral bonds, of the old family relations, of the old nationalities.
    In its positive aims, however, this form of Socialism aspires either to restoring the old means of
    production and of exchange, and with them the old property relations, and the old society, or to
    cramping the modern means of production and of exchange within the framework of the old
    property relations that have been, and were bound to be, exploded by those means. In either case,
    it is both reactionary and Utopian.
    Its last words are: corporate guilds for manufacture; patriarchal relations in agriculture.
    Ultimately, when stubborn historical facts had dispersed all intoxicating effects of self-deception,
    this form of Socialism ended in a miserable fit of the blues.

    C. German or “True” Socialism
    The Socialist and Communist literature of France, a literature that originated under the pressure
    of a bourgeoisie in power, and that was the expressions of the struggle against this power, was
    introduced into Germany at a time when the bourgeoisie, in that country, had just begun its
    contest with feudal absolutism.
    German philosophers, would-be philosophers, and beaux esprits (men of letters), eagerly seized
    on this literature, only forgetting, that when these writings immigrated from France into
    Germany, French social conditions had not immigrated along with them. In contact with German

    30 Chapter III: Socialist and Communist Literature

    social conditions, this French literature lost all its immediate practical significance and assumed a
    purely literary aspect. Thus, to the German philosophers of the Eighteenth Century, the demands
    of the first French Revolution were nothing more than the demands of “Practical Reason” in
    general, and the utterance of the will of the revolutionary French bourgeoisie signified, in their
    eyes, the laws of pure Will, of Will as it was bound to be, of true human Will generally.
    The work of the German literati consisted solely in bringing the new French ideas into harmony
    with their ancient philosophical conscience, or rather, in annexing the French ideas without
    deserting their own philosophic point of view.
    This annexation took place in the same way in which a foreign language is appropriated, namely,
    by translation.
    It is well known how the monks wrote silly lives of Catholic Saints over the manuscripts on
    which the classical works of ancient heathendom had been written. The German literati reversed
    this process with the profane French literature. They wrote their philosophical nonsense beneath
    the French original. For instance, beneath the French criticism of the economic functions of
    money, they wrote “Alienation of Humanity”, and beneath the French criticism of the bourgeois
    state they wrote “Dethronement of the Category of the General”, and so forth.
    The introduction of these philosophical phrases at the back of the French historical criticisms,
    they dubbed “Philosophy of Action”, “True Socialism”, “German Science of Socialism”,
    “Philosophical Foundation of Socialism”, and so on.
    The French Socialist and Communist literature was thus completely emasculated. And, since it
    ceased in the hands of the German to express the struggle of one class with the other, he felt
    conscious of having overcome “French one-sidedness” and of representing, not true requirements,
    but the requirements of Truth; not the interests of the proletariat, but the interests of Human
    Nature, of Man in general, who belongs to no class, has no reality, who exists only in the misty
    realm of philosophical fantasy.
    This German socialism, which took its schoolboy task so seriously and solemnly, and extolled its
    poor stock-in-trade in such a mountebank fashion, meanwhile gradually lost its pedantic
    innocence.
    The fight of the Germans, and especially of the Prussian bourgeoisie, against feudal aristocracy
    and absolute monarchy, in other words, the liberal movement, became more earnest.
    By this, the long-wished for opportunity was offered to “True” Socialism of confronting the
    political movement with the Socialist demands, of hurling the traditional anathemas against
    liberalism, against representative government, against bourgeois competition, bourgeois freedom
    of the press, bourgeois legislation, bourgeois liberty and equality, and of preaching to the masses
    that they had nothing to gain, and everything to lose, by this bourgeois movement. German
    Socialism forgot, in the nick of time, that the French criticism, whose silly echo it was,
    presupposed the existence of modern bourgeois society, with its corresponding economic
    conditions of existence, and the political constitution adapted thereto, the very things those
    attainment was the object of the pending struggle in Germany.
    To the absolute governments, with their following of parsons, professors, country squires, and
    officials, it served as a welcome scarecrow against the threatening bourgeoisie.
    It was a sweet finish, after the bitter pills of flogging and bullets, with which these same
    governments, just at that time, dosed the German working-class risings.
    While this “True” Socialism thus served the government as a weapon for fighting the German
    bourgeoisie, it, at the same time, directly represented a reactionary interest, the interest of German
    Philistines. In Germany, the petty-bourgeois class, a relic of the sixteenth century, and since then
    constantly cropping up again under the various forms, is the real social basis of the existing state
    of things.

    31 Chapter III: Socialist and Communist Literature

    To preserve this class is to preserve the existing state of things in Germany. The industrial and
    political supremacy of the bourgeoisie threatens it with certain destruction – on the one hand,
    from the concentration of capital; on the other, from the rise of a revolutionary proletariat. “True”
    Socialism appeared to kill these two birds with one stone. It spread like an epidemic.
    The robe of speculative cobwebs, embroidered with flowers of rhetoric, steeped in the dew of
    sickly sentiment, this transcendental robe in which the German Socialists wrapped their sorry
    “eternal truths”, all skin and bone, served to wonderfully increase the sale of their goods amongst
    such a public.
    And on its part German Socialism recognised, more and more, its own calling as the bombastic
    representative of the petty-bourgeois Philistine.
    It proclaimed the German nation to be the model nation, and the German petty Philistine to be the
    typical man. To every villainous meanness of this model man, it gave a hidden, higher, Socialistic
    interpretation, the exact contrary of its real character. It went to the extreme length of directly
    opposing the “brutally destructive” tendency of Communism, and of proclaiming its supreme and
    impartial contempt of all class struggles. With very few exceptions, all the so-called Socialist and
    Communist publications that now (1847) circulate in Germany belong to the domain of this foul
    and enervating literature.*

    2. Conservative or Bourgeois Socialism
    A part of the bourgeoisie is desirous of redressing social grievances in order to secure the
    continued existence of bourgeois society.
    To this section belong economists, philanthropists, humanitarians, improvers of the condition of
    the working class, organisers of charity, members of societies for the prevention of cruelty to
    animals, temperance fanatics, hole-and-corner reformers of every imaginable kind. This form of
    socialism has, moreover, been worked out into complete systems.
    We may cite Proudhon’s Philosophie de la Misère as an example of this form.
    The Socialistic bourgeois want all the advantages of modern social conditions without the
    struggles and dangers necessarily resulting therefrom. They desire the existing state of society,
    minus its revolutionary and disintegrating elements. They wish for a bourgeoisie without a
    proletariat. The bourgeoisie naturally conceives the world in which it is supreme to be the best;
    and bourgeois Socialism develops this comfortable conception into various more or less complete
    systems. In requiring the proletariat to carry out such a system, and thereby to march straightway
    into the social New Jerusalem, it but requires in reality, that the proletariat should remain within
    the bounds of existing society, but should cast away all its hateful ideas concerning the
    bourgeoisie.
    A second, and more practical, but less systematic, form of this Socialism sought to depreciate
    every revolutionary movement in the eyes of the working class by showing that no mere political
    reform, but only a change in the material conditions of existence, in economical relations, could
    be of any advantage to them. By changes in the material conditions of existence, this form of
    Socialism, however, by no means understands abolition of the bourgeois relations of production,
    an abolition that can be affected only by a revolution, but administrative reforms, based on the
    continued existence of these relations; reforms, therefore, that in no respect affect the relations
    between capital and labour, but, at the best, lessen the cost, and simplify the administrative work,
    of bourgeois government.

    * The revolutionary storm of 1848 swept away this whole shabby tendency and cured its protagonists of the desire to
    dabble in socialism. The chief representative and classical type of this tendency is Mr Karl Gruen. [Note by Engels to
    the German edition of 1890.]

    32 Chapter III: Socialist and Communist Literature

    Bourgeois Socialism attains adequate expression when, and only when, it becomes a mere figure
    of speech.
    Free trade: for the benefit of the working class. Protective duties: for the benefit of the working
    class. Prison Reform: for the benefit of the working class. This is the last word and the only
    seriously meant word of bourgeois socialism.
    It is summed up in the phrase: the bourgeois is a bourgeois – for the benefit of the working class.

    3. Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism
    We do not here refer to that literature which, in every great modern revolution, has always given
    voice to the demands of the proletariat, such as the writings of Babeuf and others.
    The first direct attempts of the proletariat to attain its own ends, made in times of universal
    excitement, when feudal society was being overthrown, necessarily failed, owing to the then
    undeveloped state of the proletariat, as well as to the absence of the economic conditions for its
    emancipation, conditions that had yet to be produced, and could be produced by the impending
    bourgeois epoch alone. The revolutionary literature that accompanied these first movements of
    the proletariat had necessarily a reactionary character. It inculcated universal asceticism and
    social levelling in its crudest form.
    The Socialist and Communist systems, properly so called, those of Saint-Simon, Fourier, Owen,
    and others, spring into existence in the early undeveloped period, described above, of the struggle
    between proletariat and bourgeoisie (see Section I. Bourgeois and Proletarians).
    The founders of these systems see, indeed, the class antagonisms, as well as the action of the
    decomposing elements in the prevailing form of society. But the proletariat, as yet in its infancy,
    offers to them the spectacle of a class without any historical initiative or any independent political
    movement.
    Since the development of class antagonism keeps even pace with the development of industry, the
    economic situation, as they find it, does not as yet offer to them the material conditions for the
    emancipation of the proletariat. They therefore search after a new social science, after new social
    laws, that are to create these conditions.
    Historical action is to yield to their personal inventive action; historically created conditions of
    emancipation to fantastic ones; and the gradual, spontaneous class organisation of the proletariat
    to an organisation of society especially contrived by these inventors. Future history resolves
    itself, in their eyes, into the propaganda and the practical carrying out of their social plans.
    In the formation of their plans, they are conscious of caring chiefly for the interests of the
    working class, as being the most suffering class. Only from the point of view of being the most
    suffering class does the proletariat exist for them.
    The undeveloped state of the class struggle, as well as their own surroundings, causes Socialists
    of this kind to consider themselves far superior to all class antagonisms. They want to improve
    the condition of every member of society, even that of the most favoured. Hence, they habitually
    appeal to society at large, without the distinction of class; nay, by preference, to the ruling class.
    For how can people, when once they understand their system, fail to see in it the best possible
    plan of the best possible state of society?
    Hence, they reject all political, and especially all revolutionary action; they wish to attain their
    ends by peaceful means, necessarily doomed to failure, and by the force of example, to pave the
    way for the new social Gospel.
    Such fantastic pictures of future society, painted at a time when the proletariat is still in a very
    undeveloped state and has but a fantastic conception of its own position, correspond with the first
    instinctive yearnings of that class for a general reconstruction of society.

    33 Chapter III: Socialist and Communist Literature

    But these Socialist and Communist publications contain also a critical element. They attack every
    principle of existing society. Hence, they are full of the most valuable materials for the
    enlightenment of the working class. The practical measures proposed in them – such as the
    abolition of the distinction between town and country, of the family, of the carrying on of
    industries for the account of private individuals, and of the wage system, the proclamation of
    social harmony, the conversion of the function of the state into a more superintendence of
    production – all these proposals point solely to the disappearance of class antagonisms which
    were, at that time, only just cropping up, and which, in these publications, are recognised in their
    earliest indistinct and undefined forms only. These proposals, therefore, are of a purely Utopian
    character.
    The significance of Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism bears an inverse relation to
    historical development. In proportion as the modern class struggle develops and takes definite
    shape, this fantastic standing apart from the contest, these fantastic attacks on it, lose all practical
    value and all theoretical justification. Therefore, although the originators of these systems were,
    in many respects, revolutionary, their disciples have, in every case, formed mere reactionary
    sects. They hold fast by the original views of their masters, in opposition to the progressive
    historical development of the proletariat. They, therefore, endeavour, and that consistently, to
    deaden the class struggle and to reconcile the class antagonisms. They still dream of experimental
    realisation of their social Utopias, of founding isolated “phalansteres”, of establishing “Home
    Colonies”, or setting up a “Little Icaria”* – duodecimo editions of the New Jerusalem – and to
    realise all these castles in the air, they are compelled to appeal to the feelings and purses of the
    bourgeois. By degrees, they sink into the category of the reactionary [or] conservative Socialists
    depicted above, differing from these only by more systematic pedantry, and by their fanatical and
    superstitious belief in the miraculous effects of their social science.
    They, therefore, violently oppose all political action on the part of the working class; such action,
    according to them, can only result from blind unbelief in the new Gospel.
    The Owenites in England, and the Fourierists in France, respectively, oppose the Chartists and the
    Réformistes.

    * Phalanstéres were Socialist colonies on the plan of Charles Fourier; Icaria was the name given by Cabet to his Utopia
    and, later on, to his American Communist colony. [Note by Engels to the English edition of 1888.]
    “Home Colonies” were what Owen called his Communist model societies. Phalanstéres was the name of the public
    palaces planned by Fourier. Icaria was the name given to the Utopian land of fancy, whose Communist institutions
    Cabet portrayed. [Note by Engels to the German edition of 1890.]

    IV. Position of the Communists in Relation to the
    Various Existing Opposition Parties

    Section II has made clear the relations of the Communists to the existing working-class parties,
    such as the Chartists in England and the Agrarian Reformers in America.
    The Communists fight for the attainment of the immediate aims, for the enforcement of the
    momentary interests of the working class; but in the movement of the present, they also represent
    and take care of the future of that movement. In France, the Communists ally with the Social-
    Democrats* against the conservative and radical bourgeoisie, reserving, however, the right to take
    up a critical position in regard to phases and illusions traditionally handed down from the great
    Revolution.
    In Switzerland, they support the Radicals, without losing sight of the fact that this party consists
    of antagonistic elements, partly of Democratic Socialists, in the French sense, partly of radical
    bourgeois.
    In Poland, they support the party that insists on an agrarian revolution as the prime condition for
    national emancipation, that party which fomented the insurrection of Cracow in 1846.
    In Germany, they fight with the bourgeoisie whenever it acts in a revolutionary way, against the
    absolute monarchy, the feudal squirearchy, and the petty bourgeoisie.
    But they never cease, for a single instant, to instil into the working class the clearest possible
    recognition of the hostile antagonism between bourgeoisie and proletariat, in order that the
    German workers may straightway use, as so many weapons against the bourgeoisie, the social
    and political conditions that the bourgeoisie must necessarily introduce along with its supremacy,
    and in order that, after the fall of the reactionary classes in Germany, the fight against the
    bourgeoisie itself may immediately begin.
    The Communists turn their attention chiefly to Germany, because that country is on the eve of a
    bourgeois revolution that is bound to be carried out under more advanced conditions of European
    civilisation and with a much more developed proletariat than that of England was in the
    seventeenth, and France in the eighteenth century, and because the bourgeois revolution in
    Germany will be but the prelude to an immediately following proletarian revolution.
    In short, the Communists everywhere support every revolutionary movement against the existing
    social and political order of things.
    In all these movements, they bring to the front, as the leading question in each, the property
    question, no matter what its degree of development at the time.
    Finally, they labour everywhere for the union and agreement of the democratic parties of all
    countries.
    The Communists disdain to conceal their views and aims. They openly declare that their ends can
    be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions. Let the ruling classes
    tremble at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains. They
    have a world to win.
    Working Men of All Countries, Unite!5

    * The party then represented in Parliament by Ledru-Rollin, in literature by Louis Blanc, in the daily
    press by the Réforme. The name of Social-Democracy signifies, with these its inventors, a section of
    the Democratic or Republican Party more or less tinged with socialism. [Engels, English Edition
    1888]

    Letter from Engels to Marx, 24 November 1847*

    Paris, 23-24 November 1847
    Dear Marx,
    Not until this evening was it decided that I should be coming. Saturday evening, then, in Ostend,
    Hôtel de la Couronne, just opposite the railway station beside the harbour, and Sunday morning
    across the water. If you take the train that leaves between 4 and 5, you’ll arrive at about the
    same time as I do. …

    Tuesday evening
    Verte [PTO]
    Give a little thought to the “Confession of Faith.” I think we would do best to abandon the
    catechetical form and call the thing “Communist Manifesto.” Since a certain amount of history
    has to be narrated in it, the form hitherto adopted is quite unsuitable. I shall be bringing with me
    the one from here, which I did [“Principles of Communism”]; it is in simple narrative form, but
    wretchedly worded, in a tearing hurry. I start off by asking: What is communism? and then
    straight on to the proletariat – the history of its origins, how it differs from earlier workers,
    development of the antithesis between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie, crises, conclusions. In
    between, all kinds of secondary matter and, finally, the communists’ party policy, in so far as it
    should be made public. The one here has not yet been submitted in its entirety for endorsement
    but, save for a few quite minor points, I think I can get it through in such a form that at least there
    is nothing in it which conflicts with our views. …

    * From MECW Volume 38, p. 146; Written: 24 November 1847; First published: in Der Briefwechsel zwischen F.
    Engels und K. Marx, 1913.

    http://marx.org\../../1848/communist-manifesto/index.htm

    Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith*

    This document is the draft programme discussed at the First Congress of the Communist League in
    London on June 2-9, 1847.
    The Congress was a final stage in the reorganisation of the League of the Just – an organisation of
    German workers and craftsmen, which was founded in Paris in 1836-37 and soon acquired an
    international character, having communities in Germany, France, Switzerland, Britain and Sweden.
    The activity of Marx and Engels directed towards the ideological and organisational unity of the
    socialists and advanced workers prompted the leaders of the League (Karl Schapper, Joseph Moll,
    Heinrich Bauer), who resided in London front November 1846, to ask for their help in reorganising
    the League and drafting its new program me. When Marx and Engels were convinced that the leaders
    of the League of the Just were ready to accept the principles of scientific communism as its
    programme they accepted the offer to join the League made to them late in January 1847.
    Engels’ active participation in the work of the Congress (Marx was unable to go to London) affected
    the course and the results of its proceedings. The League was renamed the Communist League, the old
    motto of the League of the Just “All men are brothers” was replaced by a new, Marxist one: “Working
    Men of All Countries, Unite! “ The draft programme and the draft Rules of the League were approved
    at the last sitting on June 9, 1847.
    The full text of the “Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith” (Credo) became known only in 1968.
    It was found by the Swiss scholar Bert Andréas together with the draft Rules and the circular of the
    First Congress to the members of the League in the archives of Joachim Friedrich Martens, an active
    member of the Communist League, which are kept in the State and University Library in Hamburg.
    This discovery made it possible to ascertain a number of important points in the history of the
    Communist League and the drafting of its programme documents. It had been previously assumed that
    the First Congress did no more than adopt a decision to draw up a programme and that the draft itself
    was made by the London Central Authority of the Communist League (Joseph Moll, Karl Schapper
    and Heinrich Bauer) after the Congress between June and August 1847. The new documents show that
    the draft was ready by June 9, 1847 and that its author was Engels (the manuscript found in Martens’
    archives, with the exception of some inserted words, the concluding sentence and the signatures of the
    president and the secretary of the Congress, was written in Engels’ hand).
    The document testifies to Engels’ great influence on the discussion of the programme at the Congress
    – the formulation of the answers to most of the questions is a Marxist one. Besides, while drafting the
    programme, Engels had to take into account that the members of the League had not yet freed
    themselves from the influence of utopian ideas and this was reflected in the formulation of the first six
    questions and answers. The form of a “revolutionary catechism” was also commonly used in the
    League of the Just and other organisations of workers and craftsmen at the time. It may he assumed
    that Engels intended to give greater precision to some of the formulations of the programme document
    in the course of further discussion and revision.
    After the First Congress of the Communist League, the “Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith”
    was sent, together with the draft Rules, to the communities for discussion, the results of which were to
    be taken into account at the time of the final approval of the programme and the Rules at the Second
    Congress. When working on another, improved draft programme, the Principles of Communism, in
    late October 1847, Engels made direct use of the “Confession of Faith”, as can be seen from the
    coincidences of the texts, and also from references in the Principles to the earlier document when
    Engels had apparently decided to leave formulations of some of the answers as they were.

    * From MECW Volume 6, p. 92; written by Engels, June 9 1847; first published in Gründungsdokumente des Bundes
    der Kommunisten, Hamburg, 1969, in English in Birth of the Communist Manifesto, International Publishers, 1971.

    37 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    A Communist Confession of Faith
    Question 1: Are you a Communist?

    Answer: Yes.

    Question 2: What is the aim of the Communists?
    Answer: To organise society in such a way that every member of it can develop
    and use all his capabilities and powers in complete freedom and without thereby
    infringing the basic conditions of this society.

    Question 3: How do you wish to achieve this aim?
    Answer: By the elimination of private property and its replacement by community
    of property.

    Question 4: On what do you base your community of property?
    Answer: Firstly, on the mass of productive forces and means of subsistence
    resulting from the development of industry, agriculture, trade and colonisation,
    and on the possibility inherent in machinery, chemical and other resources of their
    infinite extension.
    Secondly, on the fact that in the consciousness or feeling of every individual there
    exist certain irrefutable basic principles which, being the result of the whole of
    historical development, require no proof.

    Question 5: What are such principles?
    Answer: For example, every individual strives to be happy. The happiness of the
    individual is inseparable from the happiness of all, etc.

    Question 6: How do you wish to prepare the way for your community of property?
    Answer: By enlightening and uniting the proletariat.

    Question 7: What is the proletariat?
    Answer: The proletariat is that class of society which lives exclusively by its
    labour and not on the profit from any kind of capital; that class whose weal and
    woe, whose life and death, therefore, depend on the alternation of times of good
    and bad business;. in a word, on the fluctuations of competition.

    Question 8: Then there have not always been proletarians?
    Answer: No. There have always been poor and working classes; and those who
    worked were almost always the poor. But there have not always been proletarians,
    just as competition has not always been free.

    Question 9: How did the proletariat arise?
    Answer: The proletariat came into being as a result of the introduction of the
    machines which have been invented since the middle of the last century and the
    most important of which are: the steam-engine, the spinning machine and the
    power loom. These machines, which were very expensive and could therefore
    only be purchased by rich people, supplanted the workers of the time, because by
    the use of machinery it was possible to produce commodities more quickly and
    cheaply than could the workers with their imperfect spinning wheels and hand-
    looms. The machines thus delivered industry entirely into the hands of the big
    capitalists and rendered the workers’ scanty property which consisted mainly of
    their tools, looms, etc., quite worthless, so that the capitalist was left with
    everything, the worker with nothing. In this way the factory system was

    38 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    introduced. Once the capitalists saw how advantageous this was for them, they
    sought to extend it to more and more branches of labour. They divided work more
    and more between the workers so that workers who formerly had made a whole
    article now produced only a part of it. Labour simplified in this way produced
    goods more quickly and therefore more cheaply and only now was it found in
    almost every branch of labour that here also machines could be used. As soon as
    any branch of labour went over to factory production it ended up, just as in the
    case of spinning and weaving. in the hands of the big capitalists, and the workers
    were deprived of the last remnants of their independence. We have gradually
    arrived at the position where almost all branches of labour are run on a factory
    basis. This has increasingly brought about the ruin of the previously existing
    middle class, especially of the small master craftsmen, completely transformed the
    previous position of the workers, and two new classes which are gradually
    swallowing up all other classes have come into being, namely:
    I. The, class of the big capitalists, who in all advanced countries are in almost
    exclusive possession of the means of subsistence and those means (machines,
    factories, workshops, etc.) by which these means of subsistence are produced.
    This is the bourgeois class, or the bourgeoisie.
    II. The class of the completely propertyless, who are compelled to sell their labour
    to the first class, the bourgeois, simply to obtain from them in return their means
    of subsistence. Since the parties to this trading in labour are not equal, but the
    bourgeois have the advantage, the propertyless must submit to the bad conditions
    laid down by the bourgeois. This class, dependent on the bourgeois, is called the
    class of the proletarians or the proletariat.

    Question 10: In what way does the proletarian differ from the slave?
    Answer: The slave is sold once and for all, the proletarian has to sell himself by
    the day and by the hour. The slave is the property of one master and for that very
    reason has a guaranteed subsistence, however wretched it may be. The proletarian
    is, so to speak, the slave of the entire bourgeois class, not of one master, and
    therefore has no guaranteed subsistence, since nobody buys his labour if he does
    not need it. The slave is accounted a thing and not a member of civil society. The
    proletarian is recognised as a person, as a member of civil society. The slave may,
    therefore, have a better subsistence than the proletarian but the latter stands at a
    higher stage of development. The slave frees himself by becoming a proletarian,
    abolishing from the totality of property relationships only the relationship of
    slavery. The proletarian can free himself only by abolishing property in general.

    Question 11: In what way does the proletarian differ from the serf?
    Answer: The serf has the use of a piece of land, that is, of an instrument of
    production, in return for handing over a greater or lesser portion of the yield. The
    proletarian works with instruments of production which belong to someone else
    who, in return for his labour, hands over to him a portion, determined by
    competition, of the products. In the case of the serf, the share of the labourer is
    determined by his own labour, that is, by himself. In the case of the proletarian it
    is determined by competition, therefore in the first place by the bourgeois. The
    serf has guaranteed subsistence, the proletarian has not. The serf frees himself by
    driving out his feudal lord and becoming a property owner himself, thus entering
    into competition and joining for the time being the possessing class, the privileged
    class. The proletarian frees himself by doing away with property, competition, and
    all class differences.

    39 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    Question 12: In what way does the proletarian differ from the handicraftsman?
    Answer: As opposed to the proletarian, the so-called handicraftsman, who still
    existed nearly everywhere during the last century and still exists here and there, is
    at most a temporary proletarian. His aim is to acquire capital himself and so to
    exploit other workers. He can often achieve this aim where the craft guilds still
    exist or where freedom to follow a trade has not yet led to the organisation of
    handwork on a factory basis and to intense competition. But as soon as the factory
    system is introduced into handwork and competition is in full swing, this prospect
    is eliminated and the handicraftsman becomes more and more a proletarian. The
    handicraftsman therefore frees himself either by becoming a bourgeois or in
    general passing over into the middle class, or, by becoming a proletarian as a
    result of competition (as now happens in most cases) and joining the movement of
    the proletariat – i. e., the more or less conscious communist movement.

    Question 13: Then you do not believe that community of property has been possible at any time?
    Answer: No. Communism has only arisen since machinery and other inventions
    made it possible to hold out the prospect of an all-sided development, a happy
    existence, for all members of society. Communism is the theory of a liberation
    which was not possible for the slaves, the serfs, or the handicraftsmen, but only
    for the proletarians and hence it belongs of necessity to the 19th century and was
    not possible in any earlier period.

    Question 14: Let m go back to the sixth question. As you wish to prepare for community of
    property by the enlightening and uniting of the proletariat, then you reject revolution?

    Answer: We are convinced not only of the uselessness but even of the
    harmfulness of all conspiracies. We are also aware that revolutions are not made
    deliberately and arbitrarily but that everywhere and at all times they are the
    necessary consequence of circumstances which are not in any way whatever
    dependent either on the will or on the leadership of individual parties or of whole
    classes. But we also see that the development of the proletariat in almost all
    countries of the world is forcibly repressed by the possessing classes and that thus
    a revolution is being forcibly worked for by the opponents of communism. If, in
    the end, the oppressed proletariat is thus driven into a revolution, then we will
    defend the cause of the proletariat just as well by our deeds as now by our words.

    Question 15: Do you intend to replace the existing social order by community of Property at one
    stroke?

    Answer: We have no such intention. The development of the masses cannot he
    ordered by decree. It is determined by the development of the conditions in which
    these masses live, and therefore proceeds gradually.

    Question 16: How do you think the transition from the present situation to community of
    Property is to be effected?

    Answer: The first, fundamental condition for the introduction of community of
    property is the political liberation of the proletariat through a democratic
    constitution.

    Question 17: What will be your first measure once you have established democracy?
    Answer: Guaranteeing the subsistence of the proletariat.

    Question 18: How will you do this?

    40 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    Answer. I. By limiting private property in such a way that it gradually prepares
    the way for its transformation into social property, e. g., by progressive taxation,
    limitation of the right of inheritance in favour of the state, etc., etc.
    II. By employing workers in national workshops and factories and on national
    estates.
    III. By educating all children at the expense of the state.

    Question 19: How will you arrange this kind of education during the period of transition?
    Answer: All children will be educated in state establishments from the time when
    they can do without the first maternal care.

    Question 20: Will not the introduction of community of property be accompanied by the
    proclamation of the community of women?

    Answer: By no means. We will only interfere in the personal relationship between
    men and women or with the family in general to the extent that the maintenance of
    the existing institution would disturb the new social order. Besides, we are well
    aware that the family relationship has been modified in the course of history by
    the property relationships and by periods of development, and that consequently
    the ending of private property will also have a most important influence on it.

    Question 21: Will nationalities continue to exist under communism?
    Answer: The nationalities of the peoples who join together according to the
    principle of community will be just as much compelled by this union to merge
    with one another and thereby supersede themselves as the various differences
    between estates and classes disappear through the superseding of their basis –
    private property.

    Question 22. Do Communists reject existing religions?
    Answer: All religions which have existed hitherto were expressions of historical
    stages of development of individual peoples or groups of peoples. But
    communism is that stage of historical development which makes all existing
    religions superfluous and supersedes them.

    In the name and on the mandate of the Congress.
    Secretary: Heide [Alias of Wilhelm Wolff in the League of the Just]
    President: Karl Schill [Alias of Karl Schapper in the League of the Just]
    London, June 9, 1847

    The Principles of Communism*

    In 1847 Engels wrote two draft programmes for the Communist League in the form of a catechism,
    one in June and the other in October. The latter, which is known as Principles of Communism, was
    first published in 1914. The earlier document “Draft of the Communist Confession of Faith”, was only
    found in 1968. It was first published in 1969 in Hamburg, together with four other documents
    pertaining to the first congress of the Communist League, in a booklet entitled Gründungs Dokumente
    des Bundes der Kommunisten (Juni bis September 1847) [Founding Documents of the Communist
    League].
    At the June 1847 Congress of the League of the Just, which was also the founding conference of the
    Communist League, it was decided to issue a draft “confession of faith” to be submitted for discussion
    to the sections of the League. The document which has now come to light is almost certainly this
    draft. Comparison of the two documents shows that Principles of Communism is a revised edition of
    this earlier draft. In Principles of Communism, Engels left three questions unanswered, in two cases
    with the notation “unchanged” (bleibt); this clearly refers to the answers provided in the earlier draft.
    The new draft for the programme was worked out by Engels on the instructions of the leading body of
    the Paris circle of the Communist League. The instructions were decided on after Engels’ sharp
    criticism at the committee meeting, on October 22, 1847, of the draft programme drawn up by the
    “true socialist“ Moses Hess, which was then rejected.
    Still considering Principles of Communism as a preliminary draft, Engels expressed the view, in a
    letter to Marx dated November 23-24 1847, that it would be best to drop the old catechistic form and
    draw up a programme in the form of a manifesto.
    At the second congress of the Communist League (November 29-December 8, 1847) Marx and Engels
    defended the fundamental scientific principles of communism and were trusted with drafting a
    programme in the form of a manifesto of the Communist Party. In writing the manifesto the founders
    of Marxism made use of the propositions enunciated in Principles of Communism.
    Engels uses the term Manufaktur, and its derivatives, which have been translated “manufacture”,
    “manufacturing”, etc., Engels used this word literally, to indicate production by hand, not factory
    production for which Engels uses “big industry”. Manufaktur differs from handicraft (guild production
    in mediaeval towns), in that the latter was carried out by independent artisans. Manufacktur is carried
    out by homeworkers working for merchant capitalists, or by groups of craftspeople working together
    in large workshops owned by capitalists. It is therefore a transitional mode of production, between
    guild (handicraft) and modern (capitalist) forms of production.

    * Written: October-November 1847; Source: Selected Works, Volume One, p. 81-97, Progress Publishers, Moscow,
    1969; first published: 1914, by Eduard Bernstein in the German Social Democratic Party’s Vorwärts!; translated: Paul
    Sweezy; Transcribed: Zodiac, MEA 1993; marxists.org 1999; proofed and corrected by Andy Blunden, February 2005.
    Footnotes are from the Chinese Edition of Marx/Engels Selected Works Peking, Foreign Languages Press, 1977, with
    editorial additions by marxists.org.

    42 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    The Principles of Communism

    – 1 –
    What is Communism?

    Communism is the doctrine of the conditions of the liberation of the proletariat.

    – 2 –
    What is the proletariat?

    The proletariat is that class in society which lives entirely from the sale of its labor and does not
    draw profit from any kind of capital; whose weal and woe, whose life and death, whose sole
    existence depends on the demand for labor – hence, on the changing state of business, on the
    vagaries of unbridled competition. The proletariat, or the class of proletarians, is, in a word, the
    working class of the 19th century.6

    – 3 –
    Proletarians, then, have not always existed?

    No. There have always been poor and working classes; and the working class have mostly been
    poor. But there have not always been workers and poor people living under conditions as they are
    today; in other words, there have not always been proletarians, any more than there has always
    been free unbridled competitions.

    – 4 –
    How did the proletariat originate?

    The Proletariat originated in the industrial revolution, which took place in England in the last half
    of the last (18th) century, and which has since then been repeated in all the civilized countries of
    the world.
    This industrial revolution was precipitated by the discovery of the steam engine, various spinning
    machines, the mechanical loom, and a whole series of other mechanical devices. These machines,
    which were very expensive and hence could be bought only by big capitalists, altered the whole
    mode of production and displaced the former workers, because the machines turned out cheaper
    and better commodities than the workers could produce with their inefficient spinning wheels and
    handlooms. The machines delivered industry wholly into the hands of the big capitalists and
    rendered entirely worthless the meagre property of the workers (tools, looms, etc.). The result was
    that the capitalists soon had everything in their hands and nothing remained to the workers. This
    marked the introduction of the factory system into the textile industry.
    Once the impulse to the introduction of machinery and the factory system had been given, this
    system spread quickly to all other branches of industry, especially cloth- and book-printing,
    pottery, and the metal industries.
    Labor was more and more divided among the individual workers so that the worker who
    previously had done a complete piece of work now did only a part of that piece. This division of
    labor made it possible to produce things faster and cheaper. It reduced the activity of the
    individual worker to simple, endlessly repeated mechanical motions which could be performed
    not only as well but much better by a machine. In this way, all these industries fell, one after
    another, under the dominance of steam, machinery, and the factory system, just as spinning and
    weaving had already done.
    But at the same time, they also fell into the hands of big capitalists, and their workers were
    deprived of whatever independence remained to them. Gradually, not only genuine manufacture
    but also handicrafts came within the province of the factory system as big capitalists increasingly

    43 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    displaced the small master craftsmen by setting up huge workshops, which saved many expenses
    and permitted an elaborate division of labor.
    This is how it has come about that in civilized countries at the present time nearly all kinds of
    labor are performed in factories – and, in nearly all branches of work, handicrafts and
    manufacture have been superseded. This process has, to an ever greater degree, ruined the old
    middle class, especially the small handicraftsmen; it has entirely transformed the condition of the
    workers; and two new classes have been created which are gradually swallowing up all the others.
    These are:

    (i) The class of big capitalists, who, in all civilized countries, are already in almost
    exclusive possession of all the means of subsistence and of the instruments
    (machines, factories) and materials necessary for the production of the means of
    subsistence. This is the bourgeois class, or the bourgeoisie.
    (ii) The class of the wholly propertyless, who are obliged to sell their labor to the
    bourgeoisie in order to get, in exchange, the means of subsistence for their
    support. This is called the class of proletarians, or the proletariat.

    – 5 –
    Under what conditions does this sale of the

    labor of the proletarians to the bourgeoisie take place?
    Labor is a commodity, like any other, and its price is therefore determined by exactly the same
    laws that apply to other commodities. In a regime of big industry or of free competition – as we
    shall see, the two come to the same thing – the price of a commodity is, on the average, always
    equal to its cost of production. Hence, the price of labor is also equal to the cost of production of
    labor.
    But, the costs of production of labor consist of precisely the quantity of means of subsistence
    necessary to enable the worker to continue working, and to prevent the working class from dying
    out. The worker will therefore get no more for his labor than is necessary for this purpose; the
    price of labor, or the wage, will, in other words, be the lowest, the minimum, required for the
    maintenance of life.
    However, since business is sometimes better and sometimes worse, it follows that the worker
    sometimes gets more and sometimes gets less for his commodities. But, again, just as the
    industrialist, on the average of good times and bad, gets no more and no less for his commodities
    than what they cost, similarly on the average the worker gets no more and no less than his
    minimum.
    This economic law of wages operates the more strictly the greater the degree to which big
    industry has taken possession of all branches of production.

    – 6 –
    What working classes were there before the industrial

    revolution?
    The working classes have always, according to the different stages of development of society,
    lived in different circumstances and had different relations to the owning and ruling classes.
    In antiquity, the workers were the slaves of the owners, just as they still are in many backward
    countries and even in the southern part of the United States.
    In the Middle Ages, they were the serfs of the land-owning nobility, as they still are in Hungary,
    Poland, and Russia. In the Middle Ages, and indeed right up to the industrial revolution, there
    were also journeymen in the cities who worked in the service of petty bourgeois masters.

    44 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    Gradually, as manufacture developed, these journeymen became manufacturing workers who
    were even then employed by larger capitalists.

    – 7 –
    In what way do proletarians differ from slaves?

    The slave is sold once and for all; the proletarian must sell himself daily and hourly.
    The individual slave, property of one master, is assured an existence, however miserable it may
    be, because of the master’s interest. The individual proletarian, property as it were of the entire
    bourgeois class which buys his labor only when someone has need of it, has no secure existence.
    This existence is assured only to the class as a whole.
    The slave is outside competition; the proletarian is in it and experiences all its vagaries.
    The slave counts as a thing, not as a member of society. Thus, the slave can have a better
    existence than the proletarian, while the proletarian belongs to a higher stage of social
    development and, himself, stands on a higher social level than the slave.
    The slave frees himself when, of all the relations of private property, he abolishes only the
    relation of slavery and thereby becomes a proletarian; the proletarian can free himself only by
    abolishing private property in general.

    – 8 –
    In what way do proletarians differ from serfs?

    The serf possesses and uses an instrument of production, a piece of land, in exchange for which
    he gives up a part of his product or part of the services of his labor.
    The proletarian works with the instruments of production of another, for the account of this other,
    in exchange for a part of the product.
    The serf gives up, the proletarian receives. The serf has an assured existence, the proletarian has
    not. The serf is outside competition, the proletarian is in it.
    The serf liberates himself in one of three ways: either he runs away to the city and there becomes
    a handicraftsman; or, instead of products and services, he gives money to his lord and thereby
    becomes a free tenant; or he overthrows his feudal lord and himself becomes a property owner. In
    short, by one route or another, he gets into the owning class and enters into competition. The
    proletarian liberates himself by abolishing competition, private property, and all class differences.

    – 9 –
    In what way do proletarians differ from handicraftsmen?

    In contrast to the proletarian, the so-called handicraftsman, as he still existed almost everywhere
    in the past (eighteenth) century and still exists here and there at present, is a proletarian at most
    temporarily. His goal is to acquire capital himself wherewith to exploit other workers. He can
    often achieve this goal where guilds still exist or where freedom from guild restrictions has not
    yet led to the introduction of factory-style methods into the crafts nor yet to fierce competition
    But as soon as the factory system has been introduced into the crafts and competition flourishes
    fully, this perspective dwindles away and the handicraftsman becomes more and more a
    proletarian. The handicraftsman therefore frees himself by becoming either bourgeois or entering
    the middle class in general, or becoming a proletarian because of competition (as is now more
    often the case). In which case he can free himself by joining the proletarian movement, i.e., the
    more or less communist movement.7

    45 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    – 10 –
    In what way do proletarians differ from manufacturing

    workers?
    The manufacturing worker of the 16th to the 18th centuries still had, with but few exception, an
    instrument of production in his own possession – his loom, the family spinning wheel, a little plot
    of land which he cultivated in his spare time. The proletarian has none of these things.
    The manufacturing worker almost always lives in the countryside and in a more or less
    patriarchal relation to his landlord or employer; the proletarian lives, for the most part, in the city
    and his relation to his employer is purely a cash relation.
    The manufacturing worker is torn out of his patriarchal relation by big industry, loses whatever
    property he still has, and in this way becomes a proletarian.

    – 11 –
    What were the immediate consequences of the industrial
    revolution and of the division of society into bourgeoisie

    and proletariat?
    First, the lower and lower prices of industrial products brought about by machine labor totally
    destroyed, in all countries of the world, the old system of manufacture or industry based upon
    hand labor.
    In this way, all semi-barbarian countries, which had hitherto been more or less strangers to
    historical development, and whose industry had been based on manufacture, were violently
    forced out of their isolation. They bought the cheaper commodities of the English and allowed
    their own manufacturing workers to be ruined. Countries which had known no progress for
    thousands of years – for example, India – were thoroughly revolutionized, and even China is now
    on the way to a revolution.
    We have come to the point where a new machine invented in England deprives millions of
    Chinese workers of their livelihood within a year’s time.
    In this way, big industry has brought all the people of the Earth into contact with each other, has
    merged all local markets into one world market, has spread civilization and progress everywhere
    and has thus ensured that whatever happens in civilized countries will have repercussions in all
    other countries.
    It follows that if the workers in England or France now liberate themselves, this must set off
    revolution in all other countries – revolutions which, sooner or later, must accomplish the
    liberation of their respective working class.
    Second, wherever big industries displaced manufacture, the bourgeoisie developed in wealth and
    power to the utmost and made itself the first class of the country. The result was that wherever
    this happened, the bourgeoisie took political power into its own hands and displaced the hitherto
    ruling classes, the aristocracy, the guildmasters, and their representative, the absolute monarchy.
    The bourgeoisie annihilated the power of the aristocracy, the nobility, by abolishing the
    entailment of estates – in other words, by making landed property subject to purchase and sale,
    and by doing away with the special privileges of the nobility. It destroyed the power of the
    guildmasters by abolishing guilds and handicraft privileges. In their place, it put competition –
    that is, a state of society in which everyone has the right to enter into any branch of industry, the
    only obstacle being a lack of the necessary capital.
    The introduction of free competition is thus public declaration that from now on the members of
    society are unequal only to the extent that their capitals are unequal, that capital is the decisive
    power, and that therefore the capitalists, the bourgeoisie, have become the first class in society.

    46 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    Free competition is necessary for the establishment of big industry, because it is the only
    condition of society in which big industry can make its way.
    Having destroyed the social power of the nobility and the guildmasters, the bourgeois also
    destroyed their political power. Having raised itself to the actual position of first class in society,
    it proclaims itself to be also the dominant political class. This it does through the introduction of
    the representative system which rests on bourgeois equality before the law and the recognition of
    free competition, and in European countries takes the form of constitutional monarchy. In these
    constitutional monarchies, only those who possess a certain capital are voters – that is to say, only
    members of the bourgeoisie. These bourgeois voters choose the deputies, and these bourgeois
    deputies, by using their right to refuse to vote taxes, choose a bourgeois government.
    Third, everywhere the proletariat develops in step with the bourgeoisie. In proportion, as the
    bourgeoisie grows in wealth, the proletariat grows in numbers. For, since the proletarians can be
    employed only by capital, and since capital extends only through employing labor, it follows that
    the growth of the proletariat proceeds at precisely the same pace as the growth of capital.
    Simultaneously, this process draws members of the bourgeoisie and proletarians together into the
    great cities where industry can be carried on most profitably, and by thus throwing great masses
    in one spot it gives to the proletarians a consciousness of their own strength.
    Moreover, the further this process advances, the more new labor-saving machines are invented,
    the greater is the pressure exercised by big industry on wages, which, as we have seen, sink to
    their minimum and therewith render the condition of the proletariat increasingly unbearable. The
    growing dissatisfaction of the proletariat thus joins with its rising power to prepare a proletarian
    social revolution.

    – 12 –
    What were the further consequences of the industrial

    revolution?
    Big industry created in the steam engine, and other machines, the means of endlessly expanding
    industrial production, speeding it up, and cutting its costs. With production thus facilitated, the
    free competition, which is necessarily bound up with big industry, assumed the most extreme
    forms; a multitude of capitalists invaded industry, and, in a short while, more was produced than
    was needed.
    As a consequence, finished commodities could not be sold, and a so-called commercial crisis
    broke out. Factories had to be closed, their owners went bankrupt, and the workers were without
    bread. Deepest misery reigned everywhere.
    After a time, the superfluous products were sold, the factories began to operate again, wages rose,
    and gradually business got better than ever.
    But it was not long before too many commodities were again produced and a new crisis broke
    out, only to follow the same course as its predecessor.
    Ever since the beginning of this (19th) century, the condition of industry has constantly fluctuated
    between periods of prosperity and periods of crisis; nearly every five to seven years, a fresh crisis
    has intervened, always with the greatest hardship for workers, and always accompanied by
    general revolutionary stirrings and the direct peril to the whole existing order of things.

    – 13 –
    What follows from these periodic commercial crises?

    First:
    That, though big industry in its earliest stage created free competition, it has now
    outgrown free competition;

    47 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    that, for big industry, competition and generally the individualistic organization of
    production have become a fetter which it must and will shatter;
    that, so long as big industry remains on its present footing, it can be maintained
    only at the cost of general chaos every seven years, each time threatening the
    whole of civilization and not only plunging the proletarians into misery but also
    ruining large sections of the bourgeoisie;
    hence, either that big industry must itself be given up, which is an absolute
    impossibility, or that it makes unavoidably necessary an entirely new organization
    of society in which production is no longer directed by mutually competing
    individual industrialists but rather by the whole society operating according to a
    definite plan and taking account of the needs of all.

    Second: That big industry, and the limitless expansion of production which it makes possible,
    bring within the range of feasibility a social order in which so much is produced that every
    member of society will be in a position to exercise and develop all his powers and faculties in
    complete freedom.
    It thus appears that the very qualities of big industry which, in our present-day society, produce
    misery and crises are those which, in a different form of society, will abolish this misery and
    these catastrophic depressions.
    We see with the greatest clarity:

    (i) That all these evils are from now on to be ascribed solely to a social order
    which no longer corresponds to the requirements of the real situation; and
    (ii) That it is possible, through a new social order, to do away with these evils
    altogether.

    – 14 –
    What will this new social order have to be like?

    Above all, it will have to take the control of industry and of all branches of production out of the
    hands of mutually competing individuals, and instead institute a system in which all these
    branches of production are operated by society as a whole – that is, for the common account,
    according to a common plan, and with the participation of all members of society.
    It will, in other words, abolish competition and replace it with association.
    Moreover, since the management of industry by individuals necessarily implies private property,
    and since competition is in reality merely the manner and form in which the control of industry
    by private property owners expresses itself, it follows that private property cannot be separated
    from competition and the individual management of industry. Private property must, therefore, be
    abolished and in its place must come the common utilization of all instruments of production and
    the distribution of all products according to common agreement – in a word, what is called the
    communal ownership of goods.
    In fact, the abolition of private property is, doubtless, the shortest and most significant way to
    characterize the revolution in the whole social order which has been made necessary by the
    development of industry – and for this reason it is rightly advanced by communists as their main
    demand.

    48 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    – 15 –
    Was not the abolition of private property possible at an

    earlier time?
    No. Every change in the social order, every revolution in property relations, is the necessary
    consequence of the creation of new forces of production which no longer fit into the old property
    relations.
    Private property has not always existed.
    When, towards the end of the Middle Ages, there arose a new mode of production which could
    not be carried on under the then existing feudal and guild forms of property, this manufacture,
    which had outgrown the old property relations, created a new property form, private property.
    And for manufacture and the earliest stage of development of big industry, private property was
    the only possible property form; the social order based on it was the only possible social order.
    So long as it is not possible to produce so much that there is enough for all, with more left over
    for expanding the social capital and extending the forces of production – so long as this is not
    possible, there must always be a ruling class directing the use of society’s productive forces, and
    a poor, oppressed class. How these classes are constituted depends on the stage of development.
    The agrarian Middle Ages give us the baron and the serf; the cities of the later Middle Ages show
    us the guildmaster and the journeyman and the day laborer; the 17th century has its
    manufacturing workers; the 19th has big factory owners and proletarians.
    It is clear that, up to now, the forces of production have never been developed to the point where
    enough could be developed for all, and that private property has become a fetter and a barrier in
    relation to the further development of the forces of production.
    Now, however, the development of big industry has ushered in a new period. Capital and the
    forces of production have been expanded to an unprecedented extent, and the means are at hand
    to multiply them without limit in the near future. Moreover, the forces of production have been
    concentrated in the hands of a few bourgeois, while the great mass of the people are more and
    more falling into the proletariat, their situation becoming more wretched and intolerable in
    proportion to the increase of wealth of the bourgeoisie. And finally, these mighty and easily
    extended forces of production have so far outgrown private property and the bourgeoisie, that
    they threaten at any moment to unleash the most violent disturbances of the social order. Now,
    under these conditions, the abolition of private property has become not only possible but
    absolutely necessary.

    – 16 –
    Will the peaceful abolition of private property be possible?

    It would be desirable if this could happen, and the communists would certainly be the last to
    oppose it. Communists know only too well that all conspiracies are not only useless, but even
    harmful. They know all too well that revolutions are not made intentionally and arbitrarily, but
    that, everywhere and always, they have been the necessary consequence of conditions which were
    wholly independent of the will and direction of individual parties and entire classes.
    But they also see that the development of the proletariat in nearly all civilized countries has been
    violently suppressed, and that in this way the opponents of communism have been working
    toward a revolution with all their strength. If the oppressed proletariat is finally driven to
    revolution, then we communists will defend the interests of the proletarians with deeds as we now
    defend them with words.

    49 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    – 17 –
    Will it be possible for private property to be abolished at

    one stroke?
    No, no more than existing forces of production can at one stroke be multiplied to the extent
    necessary for the creation of a communal society.
    In all probability, the proletarian revolution will transform existing society gradually and will be
    able to abolish private property only when the means of production are available in sufficient
    quantity.

    – 18 –
    What will be the course of this revolution?

    Above all, it will establish a democratic constitution, and through this, the direct or indirect
    dominance of the proletariat. Direct in England, where the proletarians are already a majority of
    the people. Indirect in France and Germany, where the majority of the people consists not only of
    proletarians, but also of small peasants and petty bourgeois who are in the process of falling into
    the proletariat, who are more and more dependent in all their political interests on the proletariat,
    and who must, therefore, soon adapt to the demands of the proletariat. Perhaps this will cost a
    second struggle, but the outcome can only be the victory of the proletariat.
    Democracy would be wholly valueless to the proletariat if it were not immediately used as a
    means for putting through measures directed against private property and ensuring the livelihood
    of the proletariat. The main measures, emerging as the necessary result of existing relations, are
    the following:

    (i) Limitation of private property through progressive taxation, heavy inheritance
    taxes, abolition of inheritance through collateral lines (brothers, nephews, etc.)
    forced loans, etc.
    (ii) Gradual expropriation of landowners, industrialists, railroad magnates and
    shipowners, partly through competition by state industry, partly directly through
    compensation in the form of bonds.
    (iii) Confiscation of the possessions of all emigrants and rebels against the
    majority of the people.
    (iv) Organization of labor or employment of proletarians on publicly owned land,
    in factories and workshops, with competition among the workers being abolished
    and with the factory owners, in so far as they still exist, being obliged to pay the
    same high wages as those paid by the state.
    (v) An equal obligation on all members of society to work until such time as
    private property has been completely abolished. Formation of industrial armies,
    especially for agriculture.
    (vi) Centralization of money and credit in the hands of the state through a national
    bank with state capital, and the suppression of all private banks and bankers.
    (vii) Increase in the number of national factories, workshops, railroads, ships;
    bringing new lands into cultivation and improvement of land already under
    cultivation – all in proportion to the growth of the capital and labor force at the
    disposal of the nation.
    (viii) Education of all children, from the moment they can leave their mother’s
    care, in national establishments at national cost. Education and production
    together.

    50 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    (ix) Construction, on public lands, of great palaces as communal dwellings for
    associated groups of citizens engaged in both industry and agriculture and
    combining in their way of life the advantages of urban and rural conditions while
    avoiding the one-sidedness and drawbacks of each.
    (x) Destruction of all unhealthy and jerry-built dwellings in urban districts.
    (xi) Equal inheritance rights for children born in and out of wedlock.
    (xii) Concentration of all means of transportation in the hands of the nation.

    It is impossible, of course, to carry out all these measures at once. But one will always bring
    others in its wake. Once the first radical attack on private property has been launched, the
    proletariat will find itself forced to go ever further, to concentrate increasingly in the hands of the
    state all capital, all agriculture, all transport, all trade. All the foregoing measures are directed to
    this end; and they will become practicable and feasible, capable of producing their centralizing
    effects to precisely the degree that the proletariat, through its labor, multiplies the country’s
    productive forces.
    Finally, when all capital, all production, all exchange have been brought together in the hands of
    the nation, private property will disappear of its own accord, money will become superfluous, and
    production will so expand and man so change that society will be able to slough off whatever of
    its old economic habits may remain.

    – 19 –
    Will it be possible for this revolution to take place in one

    country alone?
    No. By creating the world market, big industry has already brought all the peoples of the Earth,
    and especially the civilized peoples, into such close relation with one another that none is
    independent of what happens to the others.
    Further, it has co-ordinated the social development of the civilized countries to such an extent
    that, in all of them, bourgeoisie and proletariat have become the decisive classes, and the struggle
    between them the great struggle of the day. It follows that the communist revolution will not
    merely be a national phenomenon but must take place simultaneously in all civilized countries –
    that is to say, at least in England, America, France, and Germany.
    It will develop in each of the these countries more or less rapidly, according as one country or the
    other has a more developed industry, greater wealth, a more significant mass of productive forces.
    Hence, it will go slowest and will meet most obstacles in Germany, most rapidly and with the
    fewest difficulties in England. It will have a powerful impact on the other countries of the world,
    and will radically alter the course of development which they have followed up to now, while
    greatly stepping up its pace.
    It is a universal revolution and will, accordingly, have a universal range.

    – 20 –
    What will be the consequences of the

    ultimate disappearance of private property?
    Society will take all forces of production and means of commerce, as well as the exchange and
    distribution of products, out of the hands of private capitalists and will manage them in
    accordance with a plan based on the availability of resources and the needs of the whole society.
    In this way, most important of all, the evil consequences which are now associated with the
    conduct of big industry will be abolished.
    There will be no more crises; the expanded production, which for the present order of society is
    overproduction and hence a prevailing cause of misery, will then be insufficient and in need of

    51 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    being expanded much further. Instead of generating misery, overproduction will reach beyond the
    elementary requirements of society to assure the satisfaction of the needs of all; it will create new
    needs and, at the same time, the means of satisfying them. It will become the condition of, and the
    stimulus to, new progress, which will no longer throw the whole social order into confusion, as
    progress has always done in the past. Big industry, freed from the pressure of private property,
    will undergo such an expansion that what we now see will seem as petty in comparison as
    manufacture seems when put beside the big industry of our own day. This development of
    industry will make available to society a sufficient mass of products to satisfy the needs of
    everyone.
    The same will be true of agriculture, which also suffers from the pressure of private property and
    is held back by the division of privately owned land into small parcels. Here, existing
    improvements and scientific procedures will be put into practice, with a resulting leap forward
    which will assure to society all the products it needs.
    In this way, such an abundance of goods will be able to satisfy the needs of all its members.
    The division of society into different, mutually hostile classes will then become unnecessary.
    Indeed, it will be not only unnecessary but intolerable in the new social order. The existence of
    classes originated in the division of labor, and the division of labor, as it has been known up to
    the present, will completely disappear. For mechanical and chemical processes are not enough to
    bring industrial and agricultural production up to the level we have described; the capacities of
    the men who make use of these processes must undergo a corresponding development.
    Just as the peasants and manufacturing workers of the last century changed their whole way of
    life and became quite different people when they were drawn into big industry, in the same way,
    communal control over production by society as a whole, and the resulting new development, will
    both require an entirely different kind of human material.
    People will no longer be, as they are today, subordinated to a single branch of production, bound
    to it, exploited by it; they will no longer develop one of their faculties at the expense of all others;
    they will no longer know only one branch, or one branch of a single branch, of production as a
    whole. Even industry as it is today is finding such people less and less useful.
    Industry controlled by society as a whole, and operated according to a plan, presupposes well-
    rounded human beings, their faculties developed in balanced fashion, able to see the system of
    production in its entirety.
    The form of the division of labor which makes one a peasant, another a cobbler, a third a factory
    worker, a fourth a stock-market operator, has already been undermined by machinery and will
    completely disappear. Education will enable young people quickly to familiarize themselves with
    the whole system of production and to pass from one branch of production to another in response
    to the needs of society or their own inclinations. It will, therefore, free them from the one-sided
    character which the present-day division of labor impresses upon every individual. Communist
    society will, in this way, make it possible for its members to put their comprehensively developed
    faculties to full use. But, when this happens, classes will necessarily disappear. It follows that
    society organized on a communist basis is incompatible with the existence of classes on the one
    hand, and that the very building of such a society provides the means of abolishing class
    differences on the other.
    A corollary of this is that the difference between city and country is destined to disappear. The
    management of agriculture and industry by the same people rather than by two different classes
    of people is, if only for purely material reasons, a necessary condition of communist association.
    The dispersal of the agricultural population on the land, alongside the crowding of the industrial
    population into the great cities, is a condition which corresponds to an undeveloped state of both
    agriculture and industry and can already be felt as an obstacle to further development.

    52 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    The general co-operation of all members of society for the purpose of planned exploitation of the
    forces of production, the expansion of production to the point where it will satisfy the needs of
    all, the abolition of a situation in which the needs of some are satisfied at the expense of the needs
    of others, the complete liquidation of classes and their conflicts, the rounded development of the
    capacities of all members of society through the elimination of the present division of labor,
    through industrial education, through engaging in varying activities, through the participation by
    all in the enjoyments produced by all, through the combination of city and country – these are the
    main consequences of the abolition of private property.

    – 21 –
    What will be the influence of communist society on the

    family?
    It will transform the relations between the sexes into a purely private matter which concerns only
    the persons involved and into which society has no occasion to intervene. It can do this since it
    does away with private property and educates children on a communal basis, and in this way
    removes the two bases of traditional marriage – the dependence rooted in private property, of the
    women on the man, and of the children on the parents.
    And here is the answer to the outcry of the highly moral philistines against the “community of
    women”. Community of women is a condition which belongs entirely to bourgeois society and
    which today finds its complete expression in prostitution. But prostitution is based on private
    property and falls with it. Thus, communist society, instead of introducing community of women,
    in fact abolishes it.

    – 22 –
    What will be the attitude of communism to existing

    nationalities?
    The nationalities of the peoples associating themselves in accordance with the principle of
    community will be compelled to mingle with each other as a result of this association and thereby
    to dissolve themselves, just as the various estate and class distinctions must disappear through the
    abolition of their basis, private property.8

    – 23 –
    What will be its attitude to existing religions?

    All religions so far have been the expression of historical stages of development of individual
    peoples or groups of peoples. But communism is the stage of historical development which
    makes all existing religions superfluous and brings about their disappearance.9

    – 24 –
    How do communists differ from socialists?

    The so-called socialists are divided into three categories.

    [ Reactionary Socialists: ]
    The first category consists of adherents of a feudal and patriarchal society which has already been
    destroyed, and is still daily being destroyed, by big industry and world trade and their creation,
    bourgeois society. This category concludes, from the evils of existing society, that feudal and
    patriarchal society must be restored because it was free of such evils. In one way or another, all
    their proposals are directed to this end.

    53 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    This category of reactionary socialists, for all their seeming partisanship and their scalding tears
    for the misery of the proletariat, is nevertheless energetically opposed by the communists for the
    following reasons:

    (i) It strives for something which is entirely impossible.
    (ii) It seeks to establish the rule of the aristocracy, the guildmasters, the small
    producers, and their retinue of absolute or feudal monarchs, officials, soldiers, and
    priests – a society which was, to be sure, free of the evils of present-day society
    but which brought it at least as many evils without even offering to the oppressed
    workers the prospect of liberation through a communist revolution.
    (iii) As soon as the proletariat becomes revolutionary and communist, these
    reactionary socialists show their true colors by immediately making common
    cause with the bourgeoisie against the proletarians.

    [ Bourgeois Socialists: ]
    The second category consists of adherents of present-day society who have been frightened for its
    future by the evils to which it necessarily gives rise. What they want, therefore, is to maintain this
    society while getting rid of the evils which are an inherent part of it.
    To this end, some propose mere welfare measures – while others come forward with grandiose
    systems of reform which, under the pretense of re-organizing society, are in fact intended to
    preserve the foundations, and hence the life, of existing society.
    Communists must unremittingly struggle against these bourgeois socialists because they work for
    the enemies of communists and protect the society which communists aim to overthrow.

    [ Democratic Socialists: ]
    Finally, the third category consists of democratic socialists who favor some of the same measures
    the communists advocate, as described in Question 18, not as part of the transition to
    communism, however, but as measures which they believe will be sufficient to abolish the misery
    and evils of present-day society.
    These democratic socialists are either proletarians who are not yet sufficiently clear about the
    conditions of the liberation of their class, or they are representatives of the petty bourgeoisie, a
    class which, prior to the achievement of democracy and the socialist measures to which it gives
    rise, has many interests in common with the proletariat.
    It follows that, in moments of action, the communists will have to come to an understanding with
    these democratic socialists, and in general to follow as far as possible a common policy with them
    – provided that these socialists do not enter into the service of the ruling bourgeoisie and attack
    the communists.
    It is clear that this form of co-operation in action does not exclude the discussion of differences.

    – 25 –
    What is the attitude of the communists to the

    other political parties of our time?
    This attitude is different in the different countries.
    In England, France, and Belgium, where the bourgeoisie rules, the communists still have a
    common interest with the various democratic parties, an interest which is all the greater the more
    closely the socialistic measures they champion approach the aims of the communists – that is, the
    more clearly and definitely they represent the interests of the proletariat and the more they depend
    on the proletariat for support. In England, for example, the working-class Chartists10 are infinitely
    closer to the communists than the democratic petty bourgeoisie or the so-called Radicals.

    54 Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith

    In America, where a democratic constitution has already been established, the communists must
    make the common cause with the party which will turn this constitution against the bourgeoisie
    and use it in the interests of the proletariat – that is, with the agrarian National Reformers.11
    In Switzerland, the Radicals, though a very mixed party, are the only group with which the
    communists can co-operate, and, among these Radicals, the Vaudois and Genevese are the most
    advanced.
    In Germany, finally, the decisive struggle now on the order of the day is that between the
    bourgeoisie and the absolute monarchy. Since the communists cannot enter upon the decisive
    struggle between themselves and the bourgeoisie until the bourgeoisie is in power, it follows that
    it is in the interest of the communists to help the bourgeoisie to power as soon as possible in order
    the sooner to be able to overthrow it. Against the governments, therefore, the communists must
    continually support the radical liberal party, taking care to avoid the self-deceptions of the
    bourgeoisie and not fall for the enticing promises of benefits which a victory for the bourgeoisie
    would allegedly bring to the proletariat. The sole advantages which the proletariat would derive
    from a bourgeois victory would consist

    (i) in various concessions which would facilitate the unification of the proletariat
    into a closely knit, battle-worthy, and organized class; and
    (ii) in the certainly that, on the very day the absolute monarchies fall, the struggle
    between bourgeoisie and proletariat will start. From that day on, the policy of the
    communists will be the same as it now is in the countries where the bourgeoisie is
    already in power.

    Demands of the Communist Party in Germany

    “Demands of the Communist Party in Germany” were written by Karl Marx and Frederick Engels in
    Paris between March 21 (when Engels arrived in Paris from Brussels) and March 24, 1848. This
    document was discussed by members of the Central Authority, who approved and signed it as the.
    political programme of the Communist League in the revolution that broke out in Germany. In March
    it was printed as a leaflet, for distribution among revolutionary German emigrant workers who were
    about to return home. Austrian and German diplomats in Paris informed their respective governments
    about this as early as March 27, 28 and 29. (The Austrian Ambassador enclosed in his letter a copy of
    the leaflet which he dated “March 25”.) The leaflet soon reached members of the Communist League
    in other countries, in particular, German emigrant workers in London.
    Early in April, the “Demands of the Communist Party in Germany” were published in such German
    democratic papers as Berliner Zeitungs-Halle (special supplement to No. 82, April 5, 1848),
    Düsseldorfer Zeitung (No. 96, April 5, 1848), Mannheimer Abendzeitung (No. 96, April 6, 1848),
    Trier’sche Zeitung (No. 97, April 6, 1848, supplement), Deutsche Allgemeine Zeitung (No. 100, April
    9, 1848, supplement), and Zeitung für das deutsche Volk (No. 2 1, April 9, 1848).
    Marx and Engels, who left for Germany round about April 6 and some time later settled in Cologne,
    did their best along with their followers to popularise this programme document during the revolution.
    In 1848 and 1849 it was repeatedly published in the periodical press and in leaflet form. Not later than
    September 10, 1848, the “Demands” were printed in Cologne as a leaflet for circulation by the
    Cologne Workers’ Association both in the town itself and in a number of districts of Rhenish Prussia.
    In addition to minor stylistic changes, point 10 in the text of the leaflet was worded differently from
    that published in March-April 1848. At the Second Democratic Congress held in Berlin in October
    1848, Friedrich Beust, delegate from the Cologne Workers’ Association, spoke, on behalf of the social
    question commission, in favour of adopting a programme of action closely following the “Demands”.
    In November and December 1848, various points of the “Demands” were discussed at meetings of the
    Cologne Workers’ Association. Many editions of the “Demands” published during the revolution and
    after its defeat have survived to this day in their original form, some of them as copies kept in the
    police archives.
    At the end of 1848 or the beginning of 1849 an abridged version of the “Demands” was published in
    pamphlet form by Weller Publishers in Leipzig. The slogan at the beginning of the document, the
    second paragraph of point 9 and the last sentence of point 10 were omitted, and the words “The
    Committee” were not included among the signatories. In 1853, an abridged version of the “Demands”
    was printed, together with other documents of the Communist League, in the first part of the book Die
    Communisten-Verschworungen des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts published in Berlin for purposes of
    information by Wermuth and Stieber, two police officials, who staged a trial against the Communists
    in Cologne in 1852. Later Engels reproduced the main points of the “Demands” in his essay On the
    History of the Communist League, published in November 1885 in the newspaper Sozialdemokrat, and
    as an introduction to the pamphlet: K. Marx, Enthüllungen über den Kommunisten Prozess zu Köln,
    Hottingen-Zürich, 1885.
    English translations of the “Demands of the Communist Party in Germany” appeared in the
    collections: The Communist Manifesto of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels with an introduction and
    explanatory notes by D. Ryazanoff, Martin Lawrence, London (1930); K. Marx, Selected Works, Vol.
    II, ed. V. Adoratsky, Moscow-Leningrad, Co-operative Publishing Society of Foreign Workers in the
    USSR (1936); ibid., New York (1 936); Birth of the Communist Manifesto, edited and annotated, with
    an Introduction by D. J. Struik, International Publishers, New York, 197 1, and in other publications.
    The text is from From MECW Volume 7, p. 3.

    56 Demands of the Communist Party in Germany

    Demands of the Communist Party in Germany

    “Workers of all countries, unite!”

    1. The whole of Germany shall be declared a single and indivisible republic.

    2. Every German, having reached the age of 21, shall have the right to vote and to be elected,
    provided he has not been convicted of a criminal offence.

    3. Representatives of the people shall receive payment so that workers, too, shall be able to
    become members of the German parliament.

    4. Universal arming of the people. In future the armies shall be simultaneously labour armies, so
    that the troops shall not, as formerly, merely consume, but shall produce more than is necessary
    for their upkeep.
    This will moreover be conducive to the organisation of labour.

    5. Legal services shall be free of charge.

    6. All feudal obligations, dues, corvées, tithes etc., which have hitherto weighed upon the rural
    population, shall be abolished without compensation.

    7. Princely and other feudal estates, together with mines, pits, and so forth, shall become the
    property of the state. The estates shall be cultivated on a large scale and with the most up-to-date
    scientific devices in the interests of the whole of society.

    8. Mortgages on peasant lands shall be declared the property of the state. Interest on such
    mortgages shall be paid by the peasants to the state.

    9. In localities where the tenant system is developed, the land rent or the quit-rent shall be paid to
    the state as a tax.
    The measures specified in Nos. 6, 7, 8 and 9 are to be adopted in order to reduce the communal
    and other burdens hitherto imposed upon the peasants and small tenant farmers without curtailing
    the means available for defraying state expenses and without imperilling production.
    The landowner in the strict sense, who is neither a peasant nor a tenant farmer, has no share in
    production. Consumption on his part is, therefore, nothing but abuse.

    10. A state bank, whose paper issues are legal tender, shall replace all private banks.
    This measure will make it possible to regulate the credit system in the interest of the people as a
    whole, and will thus undermine the dominion of the big financial magnates. Further, by gradually
    substituting paper money for gold and silver coin, the universal means of exchange (that
    indispensable prerequisite of bourgeois trade and commerce) will be cheapened, and gold and
    silver will be set free for use in foreign trade. Finally, this measure is necessary in order to bind
    the interests of the conservative bourgeoisie to the Government.

    11. All the means of transport, railways, canals, steamships, roads, the posts etc. shall be taken
    over by the state. They shall become the property of the state and shall be placed free at the
    disposal of the impecunious classes.

    12. All civil servants shall receive the same salary, the only exception being that civil servants
    who have a family to support and who therefore have greater requirements, shall receive a higher
    salary.

    13. Complete separation of Church and State. The clergy of every denomination shall be paid
    only by the voluntary contributions of their congregations.

    14. The right of inheritance to be curtailed.

    57 Demands of the Communist Party in Germany

    15. The introduction of steeply graduated taxes, and the abolition of taxes on articles of
    consumption.

    16. Inauguration of national workshops. The state guarantees a livelihood to all workers and
    provides for those who are incapacitated for work.

    17. Universal and free education of the people.
    It is to the interest of the German proletariat, the petty bourgeoisie and the small peasants to
    support these demands with all possible energy. Only by the realisation of these demands will the
    millions in Germany, who have hitherto been exploited by a handful of persons and whom the
    exploiters would like to keep in further subjection, win the rights and attain to that power to
    which they are entitled as the producers of all wealth.

    The Committee
    Karl Marx, Karl Schapper, H. Bauer, F. Engels, J. Moll, W. Wolff

    The Paris Commune.
    Address to the International Workingmen’s Association, May 1871

    The “Paris Commune” was composed by Karl Marx as an address to the General Council of the
    International, and included in a book, “The Civil War in France,” with the aim of distributing to
    workers of all countries a clear understanding of the character and world-wide significance of the
    heroic struggle of the Communards and their historical experience to learn from. The book was widely
    circulated by 1872 it was translated into several languages and published throughout Europe and the
    United States.
    The first address was delivered on July 23rd, 1870, five days after the beginning of the Franco-
    Prussian War. The second address, delivered on September 9, 1870, gave a historical overview of the
    events a week after the army of Bonaparte was defeated. The third address, delivered on May 30,
    1871, two days after the defeat of the Paris Commune – detailed the significance and the underlining
    causes of the first workers government ever created.
    The Civil War in France was originally published by Marx as only the third address, only the first
    half of which is reproduced here. In 1891, on the 20th anniversary of the Paris Commune, Engels
    put together a new collection of the work. Engels decided to include the first two addresses that
    Marx made to the International.
    The Address is included here because it can be regarded as an amendment to the Manifesto,
    clarifying a number of issues relating to the state based on the experience of the Commune.

    On the dawn of March 18, Paris arose to the thunder-burst of “Vive la Commune!” What is the
    Commune, that sphinx so tantalizing to the bourgeois mind?
    “The proletarians of Paris,” said the Central Committee in its manifesto of March 18, “amidst the
    failures and treasons of the ruling classes, have understood that the hour has struck for them to
    save the situation by taking into their own hands the direction of public affairs…. They have
    understood that it is their imperious duty, and their absolute right, to render themselves masters of
    their own destinies, by seizing upon the governmental power.”
    But the working class cannot simply lay hold of the ready-made state machinery, and wield
    it for its own purposes.
    The centralized state power, with its ubiquitous organs of standing army, police, bureaucracy,
    clergy, and judicature – organs wrought after the plan of a systematic and hierarchic division of
    labor – originates from the days of absolute monarchy, serving nascent bourgeois society as a
    mighty weapon in its struggle against feudalism. Still, its development remained clogged by all
    manner of medieval rubbish, seignorial rights, local privileges, municipal and guild monopolies,
    and provincial constitutions. The gigantic broom of the French Revolution of the 18th century
    swept away all these relics of bygone times, thus clearing simultaneously the social soil of its last
    hindrances to the superstructure of the modern state edifice raised under the First Empire, itself
    the offspring of the coalition wars of old semi-feudal Europe against modern France.
    During the subsequent regimes, the government, placed under parliamentary control – that is,
    under the direct control of the propertied classes – became not only a hotbed of huge national
    debts and crushing taxes; with its irresistible allurements of place, pelf, and patronage, it became
    not only the bone of contention between the rival factions and adventurers of the ruling classes;
    but its political character changed simultaneously with the economic changes of society. At the
    same pace at which the progress of modern industry developed, widened, intensified the class
    antagonism between capital and labor, the state power assumed more and more the character of
    the national power of capital over labor, of a public force organized for social enslavement, of an
    engine of class despotism.

    59 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    After every revolution marking a progressive phase in the class struggle, the purely repressive
    character of the state power stands out in bolder and bolder relief. The Revolution of 1830,
    resulting in the transfer of government from the landlords to the capitalists, transferred it from the
    more remote to the more direct antagonists of the working men. The bourgeois republicans, who,
    in the name of the February Revolution, took the state power, used it for the June [1848]
    massacres, in order to convince the working class that “social” republic means the republic
    entrusting their social subjection, and in order to convince the royalist bulk of the bourgeois and
    landlord class that they might safely leave the cares and emoluments of government to the
    bourgeois “republicans.”
    However, after their one heroic exploit of June, the bourgeois republicans had, from the front, to
    fall back to the rear of the “Party of Order” – a combination formed by all the rival fractions and
    factions of the appropriating classes. The proper form of their joint-stock government was the
    parliamentary republic, with Louis Bonaparte for its president. Theirs was a regime of avowed
    class terrorism and deliberate insult towards the “vile multitude.”
    If the parliamentary republic, as M. Thiers said, “divided them [the different fractions of the
    ruling class] least,” it opened an abyss between that class and the whole body of society outside
    their spare ranks. The restraints by which their own divisions had under former regimes still
    checked the state power, were removed by their union; and in view of the threatening upheaval of
    the proletariat, they now used that state power mercilessly and ostentatiously as the national war
    engine of capital against labor.
    In their uninterrupted crusade against the producing masses, they were, however, bound not only
    to invest the executive with continually increased powers of repression, but at the same time to
    divest their own parliamentary stronghold – the National Assembly – one by one, of all its own
    means of defence against the Executive. The Executive, in the person of Louis Bonaparte, turned
    them out. The natural offspring of the “Party of Order” republic was the Second Empire.
    The empire, with the coup d’état for its birth certificate, universal suffrage for its sanction, and
    the sword for its sceptre, professed to rest upon the peasantry, the large mass of producers not
    directly involved in the struggle of capital and labor. It professed to save the working class by
    breaking down parliamentarism, and, with it, the undisguised subserviency of government to the
    propertied classes. It professed to save the propertied classes by upholding their economic
    supremacy over the working class; and, finally, it professed to unite all classes by reviving for all
    the chimera of national glory.
    In reality, it was the only form of government possible at a time when the bourgeoisie had already
    lost, and the working class had not yet acquired, the faculty of ruling the nation. It was acclaimed
    throughout the world as the savior of society. Under its sway, bourgeois society, freed from
    political cares, attained a development unexpected even by itself. Its industry and commerce
    expanded to colossal dimensions; financial swindling celebrated cosmopolitan orgies; the misery
    of the masses was set off by a shameless display of gorgeous, meretricious and debased luxury.
    The state power, apparently soaring high above society and the very hotbed of all its corruptions.
    Its own rottenness, and the rottenness of the society it had saved, were laid bare by the bayonet of
    Prussia, herself eagerly bent upon transferring the supreme seat of that regime from Paris to
    Berlin. Imperialism is, at the same time, the most prostitute and the ultimate form of the state
    power which nascent bourgeois society had commenced to elaborate as a means of its own
    emancipation from feudalism, and which full-grown bourgeois society had finally transformed
    into a means for the enslavement of labor by capital.
    The direct antithesis to the empire was the Commune. The cry of “social republic,” with which
    the February [1848] Revolution was ushered in by the Paris proletariat, did but express a vague
    aspiration after a republic that was not only to supercede the monarchical form of class rule, but
    class rule itself. The Commune was the positive form of that republic.

    60 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    Paris, the central seat of the old governmental power, and, at the same time, the social stronghold
    of the French working class, had risen in arms against the attempt of Thiers and the Rurals to
    restore and perpetuate that old governmental power bequeathed to them by the empire. Paris
    could resist only because, in consequence of the siege, it had got rid of the army, and replaced it
    by a National Guard, the bulk of which consisted of working men. This fact was now to be
    transformed into an institution. The first decree of the Commune, therefore, was the suppression
    of the standing army, and the substitution for it of the armed people.
    The Commune was formed of the municipal councillors, chosen by universal suffrage in the
    various wards of the town, responsible and revocable at short terms. The majority of its members
    were naturally working men, or acknowledged representatives of the working class. The
    Commune was to be a working, not a parliamentary body, executive and legislative at the same
    time.
    Instead of continuing to be the agent of the Central Government, the police was at once stripped
    of its political attributes, and turned into the responsible, and at all times revocable, agent of the
    Commune. So were the officials of all other branches of the administration. From the members of
    the Commune downwards, the public service had to be done at workman’s wage. The vested
    interests and the representation allowances of the high dignitaries of state disappeared along with
    the high dignitaries themselves. Public functions ceased to be the private property of the tools of
    the Central Government. Not only municipal administration, but the whole initiative hitherto
    exercised by the state was laid into the hands of the Commune.
    Having once got rid of the standing army and the police – the physical force elements of the old
    government – the Commune was anxious to break the spiritual force of repression, the “parson-
    power,” by the disestablishment and disendowment of all churches as proprietary bodies. The
    priests were sent back to the recesses of private life, there to feed upon the alms of the faithful in
    imitation of their predecessors, the apostles.
    The whole of the educational institutions were opened to the people gratuitously, and at the same
    time cleared of all interference of church and state. Thus, not only was education made accessible
    to all, but science itself freed from the fetters which class prejudice and governmental force had
    imposed upon it.
    The judicial functionaries were to be divested of that sham independence which had but served to
    mask their abject subserviency to all succeeding governments to which, in turn, they had taken,
    and broken, the oaths of allegiance. Like the rest of public servants, magistrates and judges were
    to be elective, responsible, and revocable.
    The Paris Commune was, of course, to serve as a model to all the great industrial centres of
    France. The communal regime once established in Paris and the secondary centres, the old
    centralized government would in the provinces, too, have to give way to the self-government of
    the producers.
    In a rough sketch of national organisation, which the Commune had no time to develop, it states
    clearly that the Commune was to be the political form of even the smallest country hamlet, and
    that in the rural districts the standing army was to be replaced by a national militia, with an
    extremely short term of service. The rural communities of every district were to administer their
    common affairs by an assembly of delegates in the central town, and these district assemblies
    were again to send deputies to the National Delegation in Paris, each delegate to be at any time
    revocable and bound by the mandat imperatif (formal instructions) of his constituents. The few
    but important functions which would still remain for a central government were not to be
    suppressed, as has been intentionally misstated, but were to be discharged by Communal and
    thereafter responsible agents.
    The unity of the nation was not to be broken, but, on the contrary, to be organized by Communal
    Constitution, and to become a reality by the destruction of the state power which claimed to be

    61 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    the embodiment of that unity independent of, and superior to, the nation itself, from which it was
    but a parasitic excrescence.
    While the merely repressive organs of the old governmental power were to be amputated, its
    legitimate functions were to be wrested from an authority usurping pre-eminence over society
    itself, and restored to the responsible agents of society. Instead of deciding once in three or six
    years which member of the ruling class was to misrepresent the people in Parliament, universal
    suffrage was to serve the people, constituted in Communes, as individual suffrage serves every
    other employer in the search for the workmen and managers in his business. And it is well-known
    that companies, like individuals, in matters of real business generally know how to put the right
    man in the right place, and, if they for once make a mistake, to redress it promptly. On the other
    hand, nothing could be more foreign to the spirit of the Commune than to supercede universal
    suffrage by hierarchical investiture.12
    It is generally the fate of completely new historical creations to be mistaken for the counterparts
    of older, and even defunct, forms of social life, to which they may bear a certain likeness. Thus,
    this new Commune, which breaks with the modern state power, has been mistaken for a
    reproduction of the medieval Communes, which first preceded, and afterward became the
    substratum of, that very state power. The Communal Constitution has been mistaken for an
    attempt to break up into the federation of small states, as dreamt of by Montesquieu and the
    Girondins13, that unity of great nations which, if originally brought about by political force, has
    now become a powerful coefficient of social production. The antagonism of the Commune
    against the state power has been mistaken for an exaggerated form of the ancient struggle against
    over-centralization. Peculiar historical circumstances may have prevented the classical
    development, as in France, of the bourgeois form of government, and may have allowed, as in
    England, to complete the great central state organs by corrupt vestries, jobbing councillors, and
    ferocious poor-law guardians in the towns, and virtually hereditary magistrates in the counties.
    The Communal Constitution would have restored to the social body all the forces hitherto
    absorbed by the state parasite feeding upon, and clogging the free movement of, society. By this
    one act, it would have initiated the regeneration of France.
    The provincial French bourgeois saw in the Commune an attempt to restore the sway their order
    had held over the country under Louis Philippe, and which, under Louis Napoleon, was
    supplanted by the pretended rule of the country over the towns. In reality, the Communal
    Constitution brought the rural producers under the intellectual lead of the central towns of their
    districts, and there secured to them, in the working men, the natural trustees of their interests. The
    very existence of the Commune involved, as a matter of course, local municipal liberty, but no
    longer as a check upon the now superseded state power. It could only enter into the head of a
    Bismarck – who, when not engaged on his intrigues of blood and iron, always likes to resume his
    old trade, so befitting his mental calibre, of contributor to Kladderadatsch (the Berlin Punch14) –
    it could only enter into such a head to ascribe to the Paris Commune aspirations after the
    caricature of the old French municipal organization of 1791, the Prussian municipal constitution
    which degrades the town governments to mere secondary wheels in the police machinery of the
    Prussian state. The Commune made that catchword of bourgeois revolutions – cheap government
    – a reality by destroying the two greatest sources of expenditure: the standing army and state
    functionarism. Its very existence presupposed the non-existence of monarchy, which, in Europe at
    least, is the normal encumbrance and indispensable cloak of class rule. It supplied the republic
    with the basis of really democratic institutions. But neither cheap government nor the “true
    republic” was its ultimate aim; they were its mere concomitants.
    The multiplicity of interpretations to which the Commune has been subjected, and the multiplicity
    of interests which construed it in their favor, show that it was a thoroughly expansive political
    form, while all the previous forms of government had been emphatically repressive. Its true secret
    was this: It was essentially a working class government, the product of the struggle of the

    62 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    producing against the appropriating class, the political form at last discovered under which to
    work out the economical emancipation of labor.
    Except on this last condition, the Communal Constitution would have been an impossibility and a
    delusion. The political rule of the producer cannot co-exist with the perpetuation of his social
    slavery. The Commune was therefore to serve as a lever for uprooting the economical foundation
    upon which rests the existence of classes, and therefore of class rule. With labor emancipated,
    every man becomes a working man, and productive labor ceases to be a class attribute.
    It is a strange fact. In spite of all the tall talk and all the immense literature, for the last 60 years,
    about emancipation of labor, no sooner do the working men anywhere take the subject into their
    own hands with a will, than uprises at once all the apologetic phraseology of the mouthpieces of
    present society with its two poles of capital and wage-slavery (the landlord now is but the
    sleeping partner of the capitalist), as if the capitalist society was still in its purest state of virgin
    innocence, with its antagonisms still undeveloped, with its delusions still unexploded, with its
    prostitute realities not yet laid bare. The Commune, they exclaim, intends to abolish property, the
    basis of all civilization!
    Yes, gentlemen, the Commune intended to abolish that class property which makes the labor of
    the many the wealth of the few. It aimed at the expropriation of the expropriators. It wanted to
    make individual property a truth by transforming the means of production, land, and capital, now
    chiefly the means of enslaving and exploiting labor, into mere instruments of free and associated
    labor. But this is communism, “impossible” communism! Why, those member of the ruling
    classes who are intelligent enough to perceive the impossibility of continuing the present system
    – and they are many – have become the obtrusive and full-mouthed apostles of co-operative
    production. If co-operative production is not to remain a sham and a snare; if it is to supersede the
    capitalist system; if united co-operative societies are to regulate national production upon
    common plan, thus taking it under their own control, and putting an end to the constant anarchy
    and periodical convulsions which are the fatality of capitalist production – what else, gentlemen,
    would it be but communism, “possible” communism?
    The working class did not expect miracles from the Commune. They have no ready-made utopias
    to introduce par decret du peuple. They know that in order to work out their own emancipation,
    and along with it that higher form to which present society is irresistibly tending by its own
    economical agencies, they will have to pass through long struggles, through a series of historic
    processes, transforming circumstances and men. They have no ideals to realize, but to set free the
    elements of the new society with which old collapsing bourgeois society itself is pregnant. In the
    full consciousness of their historic mission, and with the heroic resolve to act up to it, the working
    class can afford to smile at the coarse invective of the gentlemen’s gentlemen with pen and
    inkhorn, and at the didactic patronage of well-wishing bourgeois-doctrinaires, pouring forth their
    ignorant platitudes and sectarian crotchets in the oracular tone of scientific infallibility.
    When the Paris Commune took the management of the revolution in its own hands; when plain
    working men for the first time dared to infringe upon the governmental privilege of their “natural
    superiors,” and, under circumstances of unexampled difficulty, performed it at salaries the highest
    of which barely amounted to one-fifth what, according to high scientific authority*, is the
    minimum required for a secretary to a certain metropolitan school-board – the old world writhed
    in convulsions of rage at the sight of the Red Flag, the symbol of the Republic of Labor, floating
    over the Hôtel de Ville.
    And yet, this was the first revolution in which the working class was openly acknowledged as the
    only class capable of social initiative, even by the great bulk of the Paris bourgeois –
    shopkeepers, tradesmen, merchants – the wealthy capitalist alone excepted. The Commune had

    * Professor Huxley. [Note to the German addition of 1871.]

    63 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    saved them by a sagacious settlement of that ever recurring cause of dispute among the bourgeois
    themselves – the debtor and creditor accounts.15 The same portion of the bourgeois, after they had
    assisted in putting down the working men’s insurrection of June 1848, had been at once
    unceremoniously sacrificed to their creditors16 by the then Constituent Assembly. But this was
    not their only motive for now rallying around the working class. They felt there was but one
    alternative – the Commune, or the empire – under whatever name it might reappear. The empire
    had ruined them economically by the havoc it made of public wealth, by the wholesale financial
    swindling it fostered, by the props it lent to the artificially accelerated centralization of capital,
    and the concomitant expropriation of their own ranks. It had suppressed them politically, it had
    shocked them morally by its orgies, it had insulted their Voltairianism by handing over the
    education of their children to the fréres Ignorantins,17 it had revolted their national feeling as
    Frenchmen by precipitating them headlong into a war which left only one equivalent for the ruins
    it made – the disappearance of the empire. In fact, after the exodus from Paris of the high
    Bonapartist and capitalist boheme, the true bourgeois Party of Order came out in the shape of the
    “Union Republicaine,”18 enrolling themselves under the colors of the Commune and defending it
    against the wilful misconstructions of Thiers. Whether the gratitude of this great body of the
    bourgeois will stand the present severe trial, time must show.
    The Commune was perfectly right in telling the peasants that “its victory was their only hope.” Of
    all the lies hatched at Versailles and re-echoed by the glorious European penny-a-liner, one of the
    most tremendous was that the Rurals represented the French peasantry. Think only of the love of
    the French peasant for the men to whom, after 1815, he had to pay the milliard indemnity.19 In the
    eyes of the French peasant, the very existence of a great landed proprietor is in itself an
    encroachment on his conquests of 1789. The bourgeois, in 1848, had burdened his plot of land
    with the additional tax of 45 cents, in the franc; but then he did so in the name of the revolution;
    while now he had fomented a civil war against revolution, to shift on to the peasant’s shoulders
    the chief load of the 5 milliards of indemnity to be paid to the Prussian. The Commune, on the
    other hand, in one of its first proclamations, declared that the true originators of the war would be
    made to pay its cost. The Commune would have delivered the peasant of the blood tax – would
    have given him a cheap government – transformed his present blood-suckers, the notary,
    advocate, executor, and other judicial vampires, into salaried communal agents, elected by, and
    responsible to, himself. It would have freed him of the tyranny of the garde champetre, the
    gendarme, and the prefect; would have put enlightenment by the schoolmaster in the place of
    stultification by the priest. And the French peasant is, above all, a man of reckoning. He would
    find it extremely reasonable that the pay of the priest, instead of being extorted by the tax-
    gatherer, should only depend upon the spontaneous action of the parishioners’ religious instinct.
    Such were the great immediate boons which the rule of the Commune – and that rule alone – held
    out to the French peasantry. It is, therefore, quite superfluous here to expatiate upon the more
    complicated but vital problems which the Commune alone was able, and at the same time
    compelled, to solve in favor of the peasant – viz., the hypothecary debt, lying like an incubus
    upon his parcel of soil, the prolétariat foncier (the rural proletariat), daily growing upon it, and
    his expropriation from it enforced, at a more and more rapid rate, by the very development of
    modern agriculture and the competition of capitalist farming.
    The French peasant had elected Louis Bonaparte president of the republic; but the Party of Order
    created the empire. What the French peasant really wants he commenced to show in 1849 and
    1850, by opposing his maire to the government’s prefect, his school-master to the government’s
    priest, and himself to the government’s gendarme. All the laws made by the Party of Order in
    January and February 1850 were avowed measures of repression against the peasant. The peasant
    was a Bonapartist, because the Great Revolution, with all its benefits to him, was, in his eyes,
    personified in Napoleon. This delusion, rapidly breaking down under the Second Empire (and in

    64 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    its very nature hostile to the Rurals), this prejudice of the past, how could it have withstood the
    appeal of the Commune to the living interests and urgent wants of the peasantry?
    The Rurals – this was, in fact, their chief apprehension – knew that three months’ free
    communication of Communal Paris with the provinces would bring about a general rising of the
    peasants, and hence their anxiety to establish a police blockade around Paris, so as to stop the
    spread of the rinderpest [cattle pest – contagious disease].
    If the Commune was thus the true representative of all the healthy elements of French society,
    and therefore the truly national government, it was, at the same time, as a working men’s
    government, as the bold champion of the emancipation of labor, emphatically international.
    Within sight of that Prussian army, that had annexed to Germany two French provinces, the
    Commune annexed to France the working people all over the world.
    The Second Empire had been the jubilee of cosmopolitan blackleggism, the rakes of all countries
    rushing in at its call for a share in its orgies and in the plunder of the French people. Even at this
    moment, the right hand of Thiers is Ganessco, the foul Wallachian, and his left hand is
    Markovsky, the Russian spy. The Commune admitted all foreigners to the honor of dying for an
    immortal cause. Between the foreign war lost by their treason, and the civil war fomented by their
    conspiracy with the foreign invader, the bourgeoisie had found the time to display their patriotism
    by organizing police hunts upon the Germans in France. The Commune made a German working
    man [Leo Frankel] its Minister of Labor. Thiers, the bourgeoisie, the Second Empire, had
    continually deluded Poland by loud professions of sympathy, while in reality betraying her to,
    and doing the dirty work of, Russia. The Commune honoured the heroic sons of Poland [J.
    Dabrowski and W. Wróblewski] by placing them at the head of the defenders of Paris. And, to
    broadly mark the new era of history it was conscious of initiating, under the eyes of the
    conquering Prussians on one side, and the Bonapartist army, led by Bonapartist generals, on the
    other, the Commune pulled down that colossal symbol of martial glory, the Vendôme Column.20
    The great social measure of the Commune was its own working existence. Its special measures
    could but betoken the tendency of a government of the people by the people. Such were the
    abolition of the nightwork of journeymen bakers; the prohibition, under penalty, of the
    employers’ practice to reduce wages by levying upon their workpeople fines under manifold
    pretexts – a process in which the employer combines in his own person the parts of legislator,
    judge, and executor, and filches the money to boot. Another measure of this class was the
    surrender to associations of workmen, under reserve of compensation, of all closed workshops
    and factories, no matter whether the respective capitalists had absconded or preferred to strike
    work.
    The financial measures of the Commune, remarkable for their sagacity and moderation, could
    only be such as were compatible with the state of a besieged town. Considering the colossal
    robberies committed upon the city of Paris by the great financial companies and contractors,
    under the protection of Haussman,21 the Commune would have had an incomparably better title to
    confiscate their property than Louis Napoleon had against the Orleans family. The Hohenzollern
    and the English oligarchs, who both have derived a good deal of their estates from church
    plunders, were, of course, greatly shocked at the Commune clearing but 8,000f out of
    secularization.
    While the Versailles government, as soon as it had recovered some spirit and strength, used the
    most violent means against the Commune; while it put down the free expression of opinion all
    over France, even to the forbidding of meetings of delegates from the large towns; while it
    subjected Versailles and the rest of France to an espionage far surpassing that of the Second
    Empire; while it burned by its gendarme inquisitors all papers printed at Paris, and sifted all
    correspondence from and to Paris; while in the National Assembly the most timid attempts to put
    in a word for Paris were howled down in a manner unknown even to the Chambre introuvable of

    65 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    1816; with the savage warfare of Versailles outside, and its attempts at corruption and conspiracy
    inside Paris – would the Commune not have shamefully betrayed its trust by affecting to keep all
    the decencies and appearances of liberalism as in a time of profound peace? Had the government
    of the Commune been akin to that of M. Thiers, there would have been no more occasion to
    suppress Party of Order papers at Paris that there was to suppress Communal papers at Versailles.
    It was irritating indeed to the Rurals that at the very same time they declared the return to the
    church to be the only means of salvation for France, the infidel Commune unearthed the peculiar
    mysteries of the Picpus nunnery22, and of the Church of St. Laurent. It was a satire upon M.
    Thiers that, while he showered grand crosses upon the Bonapartist generals in acknowledgment
    of their mastery in losing battles, singing capitulations, and turning cigarettes at Wilhelmshöhe,23
    the Commune dismissed and arrested its generals whenever they were suspected of neglecting
    their duties. The expulsion from, and arrest by, the Commune of one of its members [Blanchet]
    who had slipped in under a false name, and had undergone at Lyons six days’ imprisonment for
    simple bankruptcy, was it not a deliberate insult hurled at the forger, Jules Favre, then still the
    foreign minister of France, still selling France to Bismarck, and still dictating his orders to that
    paragon government of Belgium? But indeed the Commune did not pretend to infallibility, the
    invariable attribute of all governments of the old stamp. It published its doings and sayings, it
    initiated the public into all its shortcomings.
    In every revolution there intrude, at the side of its true agents, men of different stamp; some of
    them survivors of and devotees to past revolutions, without insight into the present movement,
    but preserving popular influence by their known honesty and courage, or by the sheer force of
    tradition; others mere brawlers who, by dint of repeating year after year the same set of
    stereotyped declarations against the government of the day, have sneaked into the reputation of
    revolutionists of the first water. After March 18, some such men did also turn up, and in some
    cases contrived to play pre-eminent parts. As far as their power went, they hampered the real
    action of the working class, exactly as men of that sort have hampered the full development of
    every previous revolution. They are an unavoidable evil: with time they are shaken off; but time
    was not allowed to the Commune.
    Wonderful, indeed, was the change the Commune had wrought in Paris! No longer any trace of
    the tawdry Paris of the Second Empire! No longer was Paris the rendezvous of British landlords,
    Irish absentees, 24 American ex-slaveholders and shoddy men, Russian ex-serfowners, and
    Wallachian boyards. No more corpses at the morgue, no nocturnal burglaries, scarcely any
    robberies; in fact, for the first time since the days of February 1848, the streets of Paris were safe,
    and that without any police of any kind.
    “We,” said a member of the Commune, “hear no longer of assassination, theft, and personal
    assault; it seems indeed as if the police had dragged along with it to Versailles all its Conservative
    friends.”
    The cocottes had refound the scent of their protectors – the absconding men of family, religion,
    and, above all, of property. In their stead, the real women of Paris showed again at the surface –
    heroic, noble, and devoted, like the women of antiquity. Working, thinking fighting, bleeding
    Paris – almost forgetful, in its incubation of a new society, of the Cannibals at its gates – radiant
    in the enthusiasm of its historic initiative!
    Opposed to this new world at Paris, behold the old world at Versailles – that assembly of the
    ghouls of all defunct regimes, Legitimists and Orleanists, eager to feed upon the carcass of the
    nation – with a tail of antediluvian republicans, sanctioning, by their presence in the Assembly,
    the slaveholders’ rebellion, relying for the maintenance of their parliamentary republic upon the
    vanity of the senile mountebank at its head, and caricaturing 1789 by holding their ghastly

    66 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    meetings in the Jeu de Paume.1 There it was, this Assembly, the representative of everything dead
    in France, propped up to the semblance of life by nothing but the swords of the generals of Louis
    Bonaparte. Paris all truth, Versailles all lie; and that lie vented through the mouth of Thiers.
    Thiers tells a deputation of the mayors of the Seine-et-Oise – “You may rely upon my word,
    which I have never broken!”
    He tells the Assembly itself that “it was the most freely elected and most liberal Assembly France
    ever possessed”; he tells his motley soldiery that it was “the admiration of the world, and the
    finest army France ever possessed”; he tells the provinces that the bombardment of Paris by him
    was a myth: “If some cannon-shots have been fired, it was not the deed of the army of Versailles,
    but of some insurgents trying to make believe that they are fighting, while they dare not show
    their faces.” He again tells the provinces that “the artillery of Versailles does not bombard Paris,
    but only cannonades it.” He tells the Archbishop of Paris that the pretended executions and
    reprisals (!) attributed to the Versailles troops were all moonshine. He tells Paris that he was only
    anxious “to free it from the hideous tyrants who oppress it,” and that, in fact, the Paris of the
    Commune was “but a handful of criminals.”
    The Paris of M. Thiers was not the real Paris of the “vile multitude,” but a phantom Paris, the
    Paris of the francs-fileurs,25 the Paris of the Boulevards, male and female – the rich, the capitalist,
    the gilded, the idle Paris, now thronging with its lackeys, its blacklegs, its literary bohome, and its
    cocottes at Versailles, Saint-Denis, Rueil, and Saint-Germain; considering the civil war but an
    agreeable diversion, eyeing the battle going on through telescopes, counting the rounds of
    cannon, swearing by their own honour and that of their prostitutes, that the performance was far
    better got up than it used to be at the Porte St. Martin. The men who fell were really dead; the
    cries of the wounded were cries in good earnest; and, besides, the whole thing was so intensely
    historical.
    This is the Paris of M. Thiers, as the emigration of Coblenz was the France of M. de Calonne.26

    1 The tennis court where the National Assembly of 1789 adopted its famous decisions. [Note to the German addition of
    1871.]

    67 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    Endnotes

    1 The first Russian translation of the Manifesto of the Communist Party was made by Bakunin, who
    despite being one of Marx and Engels’ most pronounced opponents in the working class movement,
    saw the great revolutionary importance contained within the Manifesto. Published in Geneva in 1869
    (printing it in Russia was impossible due to state censorship), Bakunin’ s translation was not
    completely accurate, and was replaced a decade later by Plekhanov’s translation in 1882, for which
    both Marx and Engels wrote a preface.
    2 A reference to the events that occurred in Russia after the assassination, on March, 1, 1881, of
    Emperor Alexander II by Narodnaya Volya members. Alexander III, his successor, was staying in
    Gatchina for fear of further terrorism.
    3 This preface was written by Engels on May 1, 1890, when, in accordance with the decision of the
    Paris Congress of the Second International (July 1889), mass demonstrations, strikes and meetings
    were held in numerous European and American countries. The workers put forward the demand for an
    8 hour working day and other demands set forth by the Congress. From that day forward workers all
    over the world celebrate the first of May as a day of international proletarian solidarity.
    4 A reference to the movement for an electoral reform which, under the pressure of the working class,
    was passed by the British House of Commons in 1831 and finally endorsed by the House of Lords in
    June, 1832. The reform was directed against monopoly rule of the landed and finance aristocracy and
    opened the way to Parliament for the representatives of the industrial bourgeoisie. Neither workers nor
    the petty-bourgeois were allowed electoral rights, despite assurances they would.
    5 The famous final phrase of the Manifesto, “Working Men of All Countries, Unite!”, in the original
    German is: “Proletarier aller Länder, vereinigt euch!” Thus, a more correct translation would be
    “Proletarians of all countries, Unite!”
    “Workers of the World, Unite. You have nothing to lose but your chains!” is a popularisation of the
    last three sentences, and is not found in any official translation. Since this English translation was
    approved by Engels, we have kept the original intact.
    6 In their works written in later periods, Marx and Engels substituted the more accurate concepts of
    “sale of labour power”, “value of labour power” and “price of labour power” (first introduced by
    Marx) for “sale of labour”, “value of labour” and “price of labour”, as used here.
    7 Engels left half a page blank here in the manuscript. The “Draft of the Communist Confession of
    Faith,” has the answer shown for the same question (Number 12).
    8 Engels’ put “unchanged” here, referring to the answer in the June draft under No. 21 as shown.
    9 Similarly, this refers to the answer to Question 23 in the June draft.
    10 The Chartists were the participants in the political movement of the British workers which lasted
    from the 1830s to the middle 1850s and had as its slogan the adoption of a People’s Charter,
    demanding universal franchise and a series of conditions guaranteeing voting rights for all workers.
    Lenin defined Chartism as the world’s “first broad, truly mass and politically organized proletarian
    revolutionary movement” (Collected Works, Eng. ed., Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1965, Vol. 29, p.
    309.) The decline of the Chartist movement was due to the strengthening of Britain’s industrial and
    commercial monopoly and the bribing of the upper stratum of the working class (“the labour
    aristocracy”) by the British bourgeoisie out of its super-profits. Both factors led to the strengthening of
    opportunist tendencies in this stratum as expressed, in particular, by the refusal of the trade union
    leaders to support Chartism.
    11 Probably a references to the National Reform Association, founded during the 1840s by George H.
    Evans, with headquarters in New York City, which had for its motto, “Vote Yourself a Farm”.

    68 Third Address to the International Working Men’s Association, May 1871

    12 A top-down system of appointing officials in bourgeois systems, where high-up officials appoint
    many or all lower officials.
    13 Girondins – The party of the influential bourgeoisie during the French revolution at the end of the
    18th century. (The name is derived from the Department of Gironde.) It came out against the Jacobin
    government and the revolutionary masses which supported it, under the banner of defending the
    departments’ right to autonomy and federation.
    14 The party of the influential bourgeoisie during the French revolution at the end of the 18th century.
    (The name is derived from the Department of Gironde.) It came out against the Jacobin government
    and the revolutionary masses which supported it, under the banner of defending the departments’ right
    to autonomy and federation.
    15 A reference to the Paris Commune’s decree of April 16, 1871, providing for payment of all debts in
    instalments over three years and abolition of interest on them.
    16 On Aug. 22, 1848, the Constituent Assembly rejected the bill on “amiable agreements” (concordats
    á l’amiable) aimed to introduce the deferred payment of debts. As a result of this measure, a
    considerable section of the petty-bourgeoisie were utterly ruined and found themselves completely
    dependent on the creditors of the richest bourgeoisie.
    17 Fréres Ignorantins – Ignorant Brothers, a nickname for a religious order, founded in Rheims in
    1680, whose members pledged themselves to educate children of the poor. The pupils received a
    predominantly religious education and barely any knowledge otherwise.
    18 Alliance républicaine des Départements – a political association of petty-bourgeois representatives
    from the various departments of France, who lived in Paris; calling on the people to fight against the
    Versailles government and the monarchist National Assembly and to support the Commune
    throughout the country.
    19 The law of April 27, 1825 on the payment of compensation to the former émigrés for the landed
    states confiscated from them during the preceding French Revolution.
    20 The Vendôme Column was erected between 1806 and 1810 in Paris in honour of the victories of
    Napoleonic France; it was made out of the bronze captured from enemy guns and was crowned by a
    statue of Napoleon. On May 16, 1871, by order of the Paris Commune, the Vendôme Column was
    pulled down.
    21 During the Second Empire, Baron Haussmann was Prefect of the Department of the Seine (the City
    of Paris). He introduced a number of changes in the layout of the city for the purpose of crushing
    workers’ revolts.
    22 In the Picpus nunnery cases of the nuns being incarcerated in cells for many years were exposed and
    instruments of torture were found; in the church of St. Laurent a secret cemetery was found attesting
    to the murders that had been committed there. These facts were exposed by the Commune’s
    newspaper Mot d’Ordre on May 5, 1871, and in a pamphlet Les Crimes des congrégations religieuses.
    23 The chief occupation of the French prisoners of war in Wilhelmshöhe (those captured after the
    Battle of Sedan) was making cigars for their own use.
    24 Rich landowners who hardly ever visited their estates, but instead had their land managed by agents
    or leased it to petty-bourgeois who, in their turn, sub-leased the land at high rents.
    25 Francs-fileurs – literally rendered: “free absconder,” the nickname given to the Paris bourgeois who
    fled from the city during the siege. The name carried brazen historical irony as a result of its
    resemblance to the word “francs-tireurs” (“free sharpshooters”) – French guerrillas who actively
    fought against the Prussians.
    26 A city in Germany; during the French Revolution at the end of the 18th-century it was the centre
    where the landlord monarchist emigrés made preparations for intervention against revolutionary
    France. Coblenz was the seat of the emigré government headed by the rabid reactionary de Calonne, a
    former minister of Louis XVI.

      Manifesto of the Communist Party
      Editorial Introduction
      Preface to The 1872 German Edition
      Preface to The 1882 Russian Edition
      Preface to The 1883 German Edition
      Preface to The 1888 English Edition
      Preface to The 1890 German Edition
      Preface to The 1892 Polish Edition
      Preface to The 1893 Italian Edition
      Manifesto of the Communist Party
      I. Bourgeois and Proletarians*
      II. Proletarians and Communists
      III. Socialist and Communist Literature
      A. Feudal Socialism
      B. Petty-Bourgeois Socialism
      C. German or “True” Socialism

      IV. Position of the Communists in Relation to the Various Ex
      Letter from Engels to Marx, 24 November 1847*
      Draft of a Communist Confession of Faith*
      The Principles of Communism*
      Demands of the Communist Party in Germany
      The Paris Commune.�Address to the International Workingmen’s
      Endnotes

    WARM-UP:

    ■ What makes man different from machines?

    ■ Is there anything that can make man into a machine?

    THE COMMUNIST
    MANIFESTO

    Karl Marx & Friedrich Engels

    Introduction to the Authors

    ■ Karl Marx

    – 1818 – 1883,

    Germany

    – Studied Law & Philosophy

    – Marxism: Philosophies of society, economics, and
    politics

    – Founder of the communist movement, influenced by
    industrial revolution

    ■ Friedrich Engels

    – 1820-1895, Germany

    – Philosopher, communist, social scientist

    – Co-wrote and gave financial backing to Marx

    The Communist Manifesto

    ■ Opening: “A spectre is haunting Europe – the spectre of

    communism”

    ■ Closing: “The proletarians have nothing to lose but their

    chains. They have a world to win. Working men of all

    countries, unite.”

    Historical Context

    ■ Modern Industrial Society

    – Globalization

    – Increasing technology

    – Emergence of capitalist society

    ■ French Revolution recent (1789)

    ■ Following the publication were the 1848 revolutions in

    Germany

    ■ 19th century philosophy reflected on history and human

    consciousness

    History of Oppression

    ■ Ancient and Medieval
    Societies:

    – Ancient Rome and
    Feudal system had
    complicated
    hierarchies

    – People have always
    been divided into
    classes based on
    economic
    circumstances

    – Conflict between
    classes, oppressed
    and oppressor

    ■ Modern Society

    – New struggle
    between the
    bourgeoisie and the
    proletariat

    – Simpler division,
    classes dissolved into

    each other

    ■ The status quo is
    challenged when
    productive systems
    become too strong

    The Bourgeois

    ■ “Man of the borough”

    ■ Increased globalization,
    markets, trade

    ■ Middle-class working in
    industry and
    manufacturing

    ■ Outgrew feudalism, series
    of class struggles

    ■ Owning property and
    wealth, take over feudal
    lords

    ■ Extremely “civilized

    capitalist” society

    ■ Family dynamics change

    ■ “Society is momentary in

    barbarism… too much

    civilization, too much

    industry, too much

    commerce”

    The Proletariat

    ■ The working class

    ■ “Selling” themselves as a
    commodity to the
    bourgeois

    ■ Treated as a machine

    – Long hours

    – Poor conditions

    – Low wages

    ■ Become part of the
    machine

    ■ Alienated:

    – Loss of individuality

    – Loss of connection

    – Skills no longer
    needed

    – No longer Free

    ■ Enslaved to bourgeois
    and machines

    ■ Organized like soldiers

    Potential Collective Strength

    ■ Small revolts, short-term

    victories

    ■ Learn skills fighting

    bourgeois battles

    (monarchy, landowners,

    etc.)

    ■ Improved communication

    led to possibility of

    collective and union

    ■ Problem?

    – Competing against

    each other

    – Bourgeoisie is

    fighting for their

    oppression (barely

    enough to survive as

    is)

    Proletariat Revolution

    If collective strength is realized…

    “The proletarians cannot become masters of the productive

    forces of society, except by abolishing their own previous mode

    of appropriation, and thereby also every other previous mode of

    appropriation. They have nothing of their own to secure and to

    fortify; their mission is to destroy all previous securities for, and

    insurances of, individual property”

    The Bourgeois:
    “Its own grave-digger”

    ■ Mission is to always

    expand technology,

    industry, and grow wealth

    ■ Enters workers into a

    slavish existence –

    cannot meet the

    conditions of existence

    ■ Proletariat do not want to

    work because it is not

    enough

    ■ The slaves are so poor

    that the bourgeoisie will

    need to support them

    ■ Structure of society is no

    longer compatible, it is

    not possible to maintain

    ■ Inevitable for Proletariat

    to revolt

    Capitalist Structure

    ■ Modern Industrial Society relied on capitalism

    ■ Requires wage labour

    ■ Wage labour requires competition

    ■ Competition is reduced by:

    – Machines replacing physical labour

    – Men no longer wanting to work

    ■ The impact of capitalism on human nature

    Communist Expectations

    ■ Goal:

    – Stop exploitation of
    others

    – Abolish the
    corrupted Bourgeois
    family structure

    – Education be
    successful

    – Proletariat
    overthrow Bourgeois

    ■ Ten Changes that can be
    generally applicable

    – Overhaul society

    – Prevent dominating
    powers

    – Remove competitive
    element from
    society

    – End of property is an
    end of the class
    struggle cycle

    Ten Changes of Communism

    ■ Abolition of property in land and application of all
    rents and land to public purposes.

    ■ A heavy progressive or graduated income tax.

    ■ Abolition of all rights of inheritance.

    ■ Confiscation of the property of all emigrants and
    rebels.

    ■ Centralization of credit is in the banks of the state,
    by means of a national bank with state capital and
    an exclusive monopoly.

    ■ Centralization of the means of communication and
    transport in the hands of the state.

    ■ Extension of factories and instruments of
    production owned by the state, the bringing into
    cultivation of waste lands, and the improvements of
    the soil generally in accordance with a common
    plan.

    ■ Equal obligation of all to work. Establishment of
    industrial armies, especially for agriculture.

    ■ Combination of agriculture with manufacturing
    industries, gradual abolition of all the distinction
    between town and country by a more equable
    distribution of the populace over the country.

    ■ Free education for all children in public schools.
    Abolition of children’s factory labour in its present
    form. Combination of education with industrial
    education, etc.

    Do these changes improve society?

    Why does Marx believe Communism is the solution?

    Philosophical Ideas:

    ■ Alienation / Exploitation

    ■ Identity and Individuality

    ■ Social Classes

    ■ Power Relationships

    (Master/Slave)

    ■ Communism

    ■ Inequality

    ■ Materialism

    ■ Private Property

    ■ Human Value

    ■ Human Condition

    ■ Fairness of Labour

    ■ Freedom

    ■ Capitalism

    ■ Historical Impact

    Discussion Questions:

    ■ Who are the bourgeoisie? Who are the proletariat?
    What do they represent?

    ■ How is capitalism praised in this reading? Why is
    capitalism regarded a good thing?

    ■ What does the Manifesto say about the impact of
    the proletariat on capitalism? How does this relate
    to making the revolution?

    ■ Discuss the view on abolition of property. How are
    the various criticisms answered? How do they
    relate to other texts we have read?

    ■ How do you describe the concept of “freedom” and
    “free will” in this reading?

    ■ How do Marx and Engels characterize the current
    age? What is happening? How does this relate to
    the existing social classes? How is this different
    from previous class struggles in recorded history?

    ■ Has any country achieved the 10-point program
    offered by Marx and Engels?

    ■ What role does “morality” play in the theories of
    Marx and Engels?

    ■ Why do Marx and Engels reject the possibility that
    existing social and political systems can be
    reformed?

    ■ Why do Marx and Engels claim that the bourgeoisie
    inevitably produces its own gravediggers?

    What Will You Get?

    We provide professional writing services to help you score straight A’s by submitting custom written assignments that mirror your guidelines.

    Premium Quality

    Get result-oriented writing and never worry about grades anymore. We follow the highest quality standards to make sure that you get perfect assignments.

    Experienced Writers

    Our writers have experience in dealing with papers of every educational level. You can surely rely on the expertise of our qualified professionals.

    On-Time Delivery

    Your deadline is our threshold for success and we take it very seriously. We make sure you receive your papers before your predefined time.

    24/7 Customer Support

    Someone from our customer support team is always here to respond to your questions. So, hit us up if you have got any ambiguity or concern.

    Complete Confidentiality

    Sit back and relax while we help you out with writing your papers. We have an ultimate policy for keeping your personal and order-related details a secret.

    Authentic Sources

    We assure you that your document will be thoroughly checked for plagiarism and grammatical errors as we use highly authentic and licit sources.

    Moneyback Guarantee

    Still reluctant about placing an order? Our 100% Moneyback Guarantee backs you up on rare occasions where you aren’t satisfied with the writing.

    Order Tracking

    You don’t have to wait for an update for hours; you can track the progress of your order any time you want. We share the status after each step.

    image

    Areas of Expertise

    Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

    Areas of Expertise

    Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

    image

    Trusted Partner of 9650+ Students for Writing

    From brainstorming your paper's outline to perfecting its grammar, we perform every step carefully to make your paper worthy of A grade.

    Preferred Writer

    Hire your preferred writer anytime. Simply specify if you want your preferred expert to write your paper and we’ll make that happen.

    Grammar Check Report

    Get an elaborate and authentic grammar check report with your work to have the grammar goodness sealed in your document.

    One Page Summary

    You can purchase this feature if you want our writers to sum up your paper in the form of a concise and well-articulated summary.

    Plagiarism Report

    You don’t have to worry about plagiarism anymore. Get a plagiarism report to certify the uniqueness of your work.

    Free Features $66FREE

    • Most Qualified Writer $10FREE
    • Plagiarism Scan Report $10FREE
    • Unlimited Revisions $08FREE
    • Paper Formatting $05FREE
    • Cover Page $05FREE
    • Referencing & Bibliography $10FREE
    • Dedicated User Area $08FREE
    • 24/7 Order Tracking $05FREE
    • Periodic Email Alerts $05FREE
    image

    Our Services

    Join us for the best experience while seeking writing assistance in your college life. A good grade is all you need to boost up your academic excellence and we are all about it.

    • On-time Delivery
    • 24/7 Order Tracking
    • Access to Authentic Sources
    Academic Writing

    We create perfect papers according to the guidelines.

    Professional Editing

    We seamlessly edit out errors from your papers.

    Thorough Proofreading

    We thoroughly read your final draft to identify errors.

    image

    Delegate Your Challenging Writing Tasks to Experienced Professionals

    Work with ultimate peace of mind because we ensure that your academic work is our responsibility and your grades are a top concern for us!

    Check Out Our Sample Work

    Dedication. Quality. Commitment. Punctuality

    Categories
    All samples
    Essay (any type)
    Essay (any type)
    The Value of a Nursing Degree
    Undergrad. (yrs 3-4)
    Nursing
    2
    View this sample

    It May Not Be Much, but It’s Honest Work!

    Here is what we have achieved so far. These numbers are evidence that we go the extra mile to make your college journey successful.

    0+

    Happy Clients

    0+

    Words Written This Week

    0+

    Ongoing Orders

    0%

    Customer Satisfaction Rate
    image

    Process as Fine as Brewed Coffee

    We have the most intuitive and minimalistic process so that you can easily place an order. Just follow a few steps to unlock success.

    See How We Helped 9000+ Students Achieve Success

    image

    We Analyze Your Problem and Offer Customized Writing

    We understand your guidelines first before delivering any writing service. You can discuss your writing needs and we will have them evaluated by our dedicated team.

    • Clear elicitation of your requirements.
    • Customized writing as per your needs.

    We Mirror Your Guidelines to Deliver Quality Services

    We write your papers in a standardized way. We complete your work in such a way that it turns out to be a perfect description of your guidelines.

    • Proactive analysis of your writing.
    • Active communication to understand requirements.
    image
    image

    We Handle Your Writing Tasks to Ensure Excellent Grades

    We promise you excellent grades and academic excellence that you always longed for. Our writers stay in touch with you via email.

    • Thorough research and analysis for every order.
    • Deliverance of reliable writing service to improve your grades.
    Place an Order Start Chat Now
    image

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code Happy