paper

 

Carefully read the attached article. 

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
paper
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

Summarize the article in 500 words. I want you to really focus on finding your voice and making sure your writing follows a logical progression and organized thought process. Read it out loud to see if it sounds smooth and makes sense. 

While summarizing answer the following questions: 

What is considered a commons?

As an environmental health scientist, what commons are you primarily concerned with?

 The author discusses the “Freedom to Breed”. How is this a concern with Environmental Health Sciences? Are there ethical issues with this?

How is your responsibility as an Environmental Health Scientist similar or different than the definition the author gives?

Plagiarism free paper.

What Shanl We Mam?

The Tragedy of the Commons

The population problem has no technical solution;
it requires a fundamental extension in morality.

Garrett Hardin

At the end of a thoughtful article on
the future of nuclear war, Wiesner and
York (1) concluded that: “Both sides in
the arms race are … confronted by the
dilemma of steadily increasing military
power and steadily decreasing national
security. It is our considered profes-
sional judgment that this dilemma has
no technical solution. If the great pow-
ers continue to look for solutions in
the area of science and technology only,
the result will be to worsen the situa-
tion.”

I would like to focus your attention
not on the subject of the article (na-
tional security in a nuclear world) but
on the kind of conclusion they reached,
namely that there is no technical solu-
tion to the problem. An implicit and
almost universal assumption of discus-
sions published in professional and
semipopular scientific journals is that
the problem under discussion has a
technical solution. A technical solution
may be defined as one that requires a
change only in. the techniques of the
natural sciences, demanding little or
nothing in the way of change in human
values or ideas of morality.

In our day (though not in earlier
times) technical solutions are always
welcome. Because of previous failures
in prophecy, it takes courage to assert
that a desired technical solution is not
possible. Wiesner and York exhibited
this courage; publishing in a science
journal, they insisted that the solution
to the problem was not to be found in
the natural sciences. They cautiously
qualified their statement with the
phrase, “It is our considered profes-

The author is professor of biology, University
of California, Santa Barbara. This article is
based on a presidential address presented before
the meeting of the Pacific Division of the Ameri-
can Association for the Advancement of Science
at Utah State University, Logan, 25 June 1968.

13 DECEMBER 1968

sional judgment. . . .” Vhether they
were right or not is not the concern of
the present article. Rather, the concern
here is with the important concept of a
class of human problems which can be
called “no technical solution problems,”
and, more specifically, with the identifi-
cation and discussion of one of these.

It is easy to show that the class is not
a null class. Recall the game of tick-
tack-toe. Consider the problem, “How
can I win. the game of tick-tack-toe?”
It is well known that I cannot, if I as-
sume (in keeping with the conventions
of game theory) that my opponent un-
derstands the game perfectly. Put an-
other way, there is no “technical solu-
tion” to the problem. I can win only
by giving a radical meaning to the word
“win.” I can hit my opponent over the
head; or I can drug him; or I can falsify
the records. Every way in which I “win”
involves, in some sense, an abandon-
ment of the game, as we intuitively un-
derstand it. (I can also, of course,
openly abandon the game-refuse to
play it. This is what most adults do.)
The class of “No technical solution

problems” has members. My thesis is
that the “population problem,” as con-
ventionally conceived, is a member of
this class. How it is conventionally con-
ceived needs some comment. It is fair
to say that most people who’ anguish
over the population problem are trying
to find a way to avoid the evils of over-
population without relinquishing any of
the privileges they now enjoy. They
think that farming the seas or develop-
ing new strains of wheat will solve the
problem-technologically. I try to show
here that the solution they seek cannot
be found. The population problem can-
not be solved in a technical way, any
more than can the problem of winning
the game of tick-tack-toe.

Population, as Malthus said, naturally
tends to grow “geometrically,” or, as we
would now say, exponentially. In a
finite world this means that the per
capita share of the world’s goods must
steadily decrease. Is ours a finite world?
A fair defense can be put forward for

the view that the world is infinite; or
that we do not know that it is not. But,
in terms of the practical problems that
we must face in the next few genera-
tions with the foreseeable technology, it
is clear that we will greatly increase
human misery if we do not, during the
immediate future, assume that the world
available to the terrestrial human pop-
ulation is finite. “Space” is no escape
(2).
A finite world can support only a

finite population; therefore, population
growth must eventually equal zero. (The
case of perpetual wide fluctuations
above and below zero is a trivial variant
that need not be discussed.) When this
condition is met, what will be the situa-
tion of mankind? Specifically, can Ben-
tham’s goal of “the greatest good for
the greatest number” be realized?
No-for two reasons, each sufficient

by itself. The first is a theoretical one.
It is not mathematically possible to
maximize for two (or more) variables at
the same time. This was clearly stated
by von Neumann and Morgenstern (3),
but the principle is implicit in the theory
of partial differential equations, dating
back at least to D’Alembert (1717-
1783).
The second reason springs directly

from biological facts. To live, any
organism must have a source of energy
(for example, food). This energy is
utilized for two puposes: mere main-
tenance and work. For man, mainte-
nance of life requires about 1600 kilo-
calories a day (“maintenance calories’).
Anything that he does over and above
merely staying alive will be defined as
work, and is supported by “work cal-
ories” which he takes in. Work calories
are used not only for what we call work
in common speech; they are also re-
quired for all forms of enjoyment, from
swimming and automobile racing to
playing music and writing poetry. If
our goal is to maximize population it is
obvious what we must do: We must
make the work calories per person ap-
proach as close to zero as possible. No
gourmet meals, no vacations, no sports,
no music, no literature, no art. . . . I
think that everyone will grant, without

1243

o
n
Ja

n
u
a
ry 1

3
, 2

0
2
0

h
ttp

://scie
n
ce

.scie
n
ce

m
a
g
.o

rg
/

D
o
w

n
lo

a
d
e
d
fro

m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

argument or proof, that maximizing
population does not max2imize goods.
Bentham’s goal is impossible.

In reaching this conclusion I have
made the usual assumption that it is
the acquisition of energy that is the
problem. The appearance of atomic
energy has led some to question this
assumption. However, given an infinite
source of energy, population growth
still produces an inescapable problem.
The problem of the acquisition of en-
ergy is replaced by the problem of its
dissipation, as J. H. Fremlin has so wit-
tily shown (4). The arithmetic signs in
-t-he analysis are, as it were, reversed;
but Bentham’s goal is still unobtainable.
The optimum population is, then, less

than the maximum. The difficulty of
defining the optimum is enormous; so
far as I know, no one has seriously
tackled this problem. Reaching an ac-
ceptable and stable solution will surely
require more than one generation of
hard analytical work-and much per-
suasion.
We want the maximum good per

person; but what is good? To one per-
son it is wilderness, to another it is ski
lodges for thousands. To one it is estu-
aries to nourish ducks for hunters to
shoot; to another it is factory land.
Comparing one good with another is,
we usually say, impossible because
goods are incommensurable. Incommen-
surables cannot be compared.

Theoretically this may be true; but in
real life incommensurables are commen-
surable. Only a criterion of judgment
and a system of weighting are needed.
In nature the criterion is survival. Is it
better for a species to be small and hide-
able, or large and powerful? Natural
selection commensurates the incommen-
surables. The compromise achieved de-
pends on a natural weighting of the
values of the variables.
Man must imitate this process. There

is no doubt that in fact he already does,
but unconsciously. It is when the hidden
decisions are made explicit that the
arguments begin. The problem for the
years ahead is to work out an accept-
able theory of weighting. Synergistic
effects, nonlinear variation, and difficul-
ties in discounting the future make the
intellectual problem difficult, but not
(in principle) insoluble.
Has any cultural group solved this

practical problem at the present time,
even on an intuitive level? One simple
fact proves that none has: there is no
prosperous population in the world to-
day that has, and has had for some

1244

time,-p – rate of zero. Any people
that has intuitively identified its opti-
mum point will soon reach it, after
which its growth rate becomes and re-
mains zero.
Of course, a positive growth rate

might be taken as evidence that a pop-
ulation is below its optimum. However,
by any reasonable standards, the most
rapidly growing populations on earth
today are (in general) the most misera-
ble. This association (which need not be
invariable) casts doubt on the optimistic
assumption that the positive growth rate
of a population is evidence that it has
yet to reach its optimum.
We can make little progress in work-

ing toward optimum poulation size until
we explicitly exorcize the spirit of
Adam Smith in the field of practical
demography. In economic affairs, The
Wealth of Nations (1776) popularized
the “invisible hand,” the idea that an
individual who “intends only his own
gain,” is, as it were, “led by an invisible
hand to promote . .,. the public interest”
(5). Adam Smith did not assert that
this was invariably true, and perhaps
neither did any of his followers. But he
contributed to a dominant tendency of
thought that has ever since interfered
with positive action based on rational
analysis, namely, the tendency to as-
sume that decisions reached individually
will, in fact, be the best decisions for an
entire society. If this assumption is
correct it justifies the continuance of
our present policy of laissez-faire in
reproduction. If it is correct we can as-
sume that men will control their individ-
ual fecundity so as to produce the opti-
mum population. If the assumption is
not correct, we need to reexamine our
individual freedoms to see which ones
are defensible.

Tragedy of Freedom in a Commons

The rebuttal to the invisible hand in
population control is to be found in a
scenario first sketched in a little-known
pamphlet (6) in 1833 by a mathematical
amateur named William Forster Lloyd
(1794-1852). We may well call it “the
tragedy of the commons,” using the
word “tragedy” as the philosopher
Whitehead used it (7): “The essence of
dramatic tragedy is not unhappiness. It
resides in the solemnity of the remorse-
less working of things.” He then’ goes on.
to say, “This inevitableness of destiny
can only be illustrated in terms of hu-
man life by incidents which in fact in-

volve unhappiness. For it is only by
them that the futility of escape can be
made evident in the drama.”
The tragedy of the commons develops

in this way. Picture a pasture open to
all. It is to be expected that each herds-
man will try to keep as many cattle as
possible on the commons. Such an ar-
rangement may work reasonably satis-
factorily for centuries because tribal
wars, poaching, and disease keep the
numbers of both man and beast well
below the carrying capacity of the land.
Finally, however, comes the day of
reckoning, that is, the day when the
long-desired goal of social stability be-
comes a reality. At this point, the in-
herent logic of the commons remorse-
lessly generates tragedy.
As a rational being, each herdsman

seeks to maximize his gain. Explicitly
or implicitly, more or less consciously,
he asks, “What is the utility to me of
adding one more animal to my herd?”
This utility has one negative and one
positive component.

1) The positive component is a func-
tion of the increment of one animal.
Since the herdsman receives all the
proceeds from the sale of the additional
animal, the positive utility is nearly +1.

2) The negative component is a func-
tion of the additional overgrazing
created by one more animal. Since,
however, the effects of overgrazing are
shared by all the herdsmen, the negative
utility for any particular decision-
making herdsman is only a fraction of
-1.
Adding together the component par-

tial utilities, the rational herdsman
concludes that the only sensible course
for him to pursue is to add another
animal to his herd. And another; and
another…. But this is the conclusion
reached by each and every rational
herdsman sharing a commons. Therein
is the tragedy. Each man is locked into
a system that compels him to increase
his herd without limit-in a world that
is limited. Ruin is the destination to-
ward which all men rush, each pursuing
his own best interest in a society that
believes in the freedom of the com-
mons. Freedom in a commons brings
ruin to all.
Some would say that this is a plati-

tude. Would that it were! In a sense, it
was learned thousands of years ago, but
natural selection favors the forces of
psychological denial (8). The individual
benefits as an individual from his ability
to deny the truth even though society as
a whole, of which he is a part, suffers.

SCIENCE, VOL. 162

o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

Education can counteract the natural
tendency to do the wrong thing, but the
inexorable succession of generations
requires that the basis for this knowl-
edge be constantly refreshed.
A simple incident that occurred a few

years ago in Leominster, Massachusetts,
shows how perishable the knowledge is.
During the Christmas shopping season
the parking meters downtown were
covered with plastic bags that bore tags
reading: “Do not open until after Christ-
mas. Free parking courtesy of the
mayor and city council.” In other words,
facing the prospect of an increased de-
mand for already scarce space, the city
fathers reinstituted the system of the
commons. (Cynically, we suspect that
they gained more votes than they lost
by this retrogressive act.)

In an approximate way, the logic of
the commons has been understood for
a long time, perhaps since the dis-
covery of agriculture or the invention
of private property in real estate. But
it is understood mostly only in special
cases which are not sufficiently general-
ized. Even at this late date, cattlemen
leasing national land on the western
ranges demonstrate no more than an
ambivalent understanding, in constantly
pressuring federal authorities to increase
the head count to the point where over-
grazing produces erosion and weed-
dominance. Likewise, the oceans of the
world continue to suffer from the sur-
vival of the philosophy of the commons.
Maritime nations still respond automat-
ically to the shibboleth of the “freedom
of the seas.” Professing to believe in
the “inexhaustible resources of the
oceans,” they bring species after species
of fish and whales closer to extinction
(9).
The National Parks present another

instance of the working out of the
tragedy of the commons. At present,
they are open to all, without limit. The
parks themselves are limited in extent-
there is only one Yosemite Valley-
whereas population seems to grow with-
out limit. The values that visitors seek
in the parks are steadily eroded. Plainly,
we must soon cease to treat the parks
as commons or they will be of no value
to anyone.
What shall we do? We have several

options. We might sell them off as pri-
vate property. We might keep them as
public property, but allocate the right
to enter them. The allocation might be
on the basis of wealth, by the use of an
auction system. It might be on the basis
of merit, as defined by some agreed-
13 DECEMBER 1968

upon standards. It might be by lottery.
Or it might be on a first-come, first-
served basis, administered to long
queues. These, I think, are all the
reasonable possibilities. They are all
objectionable. But we must choose-or
acquiesce in the destruction of the com-
mons that we call our National Parks.

Pollution

In a reverse way, the tragedy of
the commons reappears in problems of
pollution. Here it is not a question of
taking something out of the commons,
but of putting something in-sewage,
or chemical, radioactive, and heat
wastes into water; noxious and danger-
ous fumes into the air; and distracting
and unpleasant advertising signs into
the line of sight. The calculations of
utility are much the same as before.
The rational man finds that his share of
the cost of the wastes he discharges into
the commons is less than the cost of
purifying his wastes before releasing
them. Since this is true for everyone, we
are locked into a system of “fouling our
own nest,” so long as we behave only
as independent, rational, free-enter-
prisers.
The tragedy of the commons as a

food basket is averted by private prop-
erty, or something formally like it. But
the air and waters surrounding us can-
not readily be fenced, and so the trag-
edy of the commons as a cesspool must
be prevented by different means, by co-
ercive laws or taxing devices that make
it cheaper for the polluter to treat his
pollutants than to discharge them un-
treated. We have not progressed as far
with the solution of this problem as we
have with the first. Indeed, our particu-
lar concept of private property, which
deters us from exhausting the positive
resources of the earth, favors pollution.
The owner of a factory on the bank of
a stream-whose property extends to
the middle of the stream-often has
difficulty seeing why it is not his natural
right to muddy the waters flowing past
his door. The law, always behind the
times, requires elaborate stitching and
fitting to adapt it to this newly perceived
aspect of the commons.
The pollution problem is a con-

sequence of population. It did not much
matter how a lonely American frontiers-
man disposed of his waste. “Flowing
water purifies itself every 10 miles,” my
grandfather used to say, and the myth
was near enough to the truth when he

was a boy, for there were not too many
people. But as population became denser,
the natural chemical and biological re-
cycling processes became overloaded,
calling for a redefinition of property
rights.

How To Legislate Temperance?

Analysis of the pollution problem as
a function of population density un-
covers a not generally recognized prin-
ciple of morality, namely: the morality
of an act is a function of the state of
the system at the time it is performed
(10). Using the commons as a cesspool
does not harm the general public under
frontier conditions, because there is no
public; the same behavior in a metropo-
lis is unbearable. A hundred and fifty
years ago a plainsman could kill an
American bison, cut out only the tongue
for his dinner, and discard the rest of
the animal. He was not in any impor-
tant sense being wasteful. Today, with
only a few thousand bison left, we
would be appalled at such behavior.

In passing, it is worth noting that the
morality of an act cannot be determined
from a photograph. One does not know
whether a man killing an elephant or
setting flre to the grassland is harming
others until one knows the total system
in which his act appears. “One picture
is worth a thousand words,” said an
ancient Chinese; but it may take 10,000
words to validate it. It is as tempting to
ecologists as it is to reformers in general
to try to persuade others by way of the
photographic shortcut. But the essense
of an argument cannot be photo-
graphed: it must be presented rationally
-in words.

That morality is system-sensitive
escaped the attention of most codifiers
of ethics in the past. “Thou shalt
not . . .” is the form of traditional
ethical directives which make no allow-
ance for particular circumstances. The
laws of our society follow the pattern of
ancient ethics, and therefore are poorly
suited to governing a complex, crowded,
changeable world. Our epicyclic solu-
tion is to augment statutory law with
administrative law. Since it is practically
impossible to spell out all the conditions
under which it is safe to burn trash in
the back yard or to run an automobile
without smog-control, by law we dele-
gate the details to bureaus. The result
is administrative law, which is rightly
feared for an ancient reason-Quis
custodiet ipsos custodes?-“Who shall

1245

-A

o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

watch the watchers themselves?” John
Adams said that we must have “a gov-
ernment of laws and not men.” Bureau
administrators, trying to evaluate the
morality of acts in the total system, are
singularly liable to corruption, produc-
ing a government by men, not laws.

Prohibition is easy to legislate
(though not necessarily to enforce); but
how do we legislate temperance? Ex-
perience indicates that it can be ac-
complished best through the mediation
of administrative law. We limit possi-
bilities unnecessarily if we suppose that
the sentiment of Quis custodiet denies
us the use of administrative law. We
should rather retain the phrase as a
perpetual reminder of fearful dangers
we cannot avoid. The great challenge
facing us now is to invent the corrective
feedbacks that are needed to keep cus-
todians honest. We must find ways to
legitimate the needed authority of both
the custodians and the corrective feed-
backs.

Freedom To Breed Is Intolerable

The tragedy of the commons is in-
volved in population problems in an-
other way. In a world governed solely
by the principle of “dog eat dog”-if
indeed there ever was such a world-
how many children a family had would
not be a matter of public concern.
Parents who bred too exuberantly would
leave fewer descendants, not more, be-
cause they would be unable to care
adequately for their children. David
Lack and others have found that such a
negative feedback demonstrably con-
trols the fecundity of birds (11). But
men are not birds, and have not acted
like them for millenniums, at least.

If each human family were depen-
dent only on its own resources; if the
children of improvident parents starved
to death; if, thus, overbreeding brought
its own “punishment” to the germ line-
then there would be no public interest
in controlling the breeding of families.
But our society is deeply committed to
the welfare state (12), and hence is
confronted with another aspect of the
tragedy of the commons.

In a welfare state, how shall we deal
with the family, the religion, the race,
or the class (or indeed any distinguish-
able and cohesive group) that adopts
overbreeding as a policy to secure its
own aggrandizement (13)? To couple
the concept of freedom to breed with
the belief that everyone born has an

1246

equal right to the commons is to lock
the world into a tragic course of action.

Unfortunately this is just the course
of action that is being pursued by the
United Nations. In late 1967, some 30
nations agreed to the following (14):
The Universal Declaration of Human

Rights describes the family as the natural
and fundamental unit of society. It fol-
lows that any choice and decision with
regard to the size of the family must irte-
vocably rest with the family itself, and
cannot be made by anyone else.

It is painful to have to deny categor-
ically the validity of this right; denying
it, one feels as uncomfortable as a resi-
dent of Salem, Massachusetts, who
denied the reality of witches in the 17th
century. At the present time, in liberal
quarters, something like a taboo acts to
inhibit criticism of the United Nations.
There is a feeling that the United
Nations is “our last and best hope,”
that we shouldn’t find fault with it; we
shouldn’t play into the hands of the
archconservatives. However, let us not
forget what Robert Louis Stevenson
said: “The truth that is suppressed by
friends is the readiest weapon of the
enemy.” If we love the truth we must
openly deny the validity of the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights, even
though it is promoted by the United
Nations. We should also join with
Kingsley Davis (15) in attempting to
get Planned Parenthood-World Popula-
tion to see the error of its ways in em-
bracing the same tragic ideal.

Conscience Is Self-Eliminating

It is a mistake to think that we can
control the breeding of mankind in the
long run by an appeal to conscience.
Charles Galton Darwin made this point
when he spoke on the centennial of the
publication of his grandfather’s great
book. The argument is straightforward
and Darwinian.

People vary. Confronted with appeals
to limit breeding, some people will un-
doubtedly respond to the plea more
than others. Those who have more
children will produce a larger fraction
of the next generation than those with
more susceptible consciences. The dif-
ference will be accentuated, generation
by generation.

In C. G. Darwin’s words: “It may
well be that it would take hundreds of
generations for the progenitive instinct
to develop in this way, but if it should
do so, nature would have taken her
revenge, and the variety Homo contra-

cipiens would become extinct and
would be replaced by the variety Homo
progenitivus” (16).
The argument assumes that con-

science or the desire for children (no
matter which) is hereditary-but heredi-
tary only in the most general formal
sense. The result will be the same
whether the attitude is transmitted
through germ cells, or exosomatically,
to use A. J. Lotka’s term. (If one denies
the latter possibility as well as the
former, then what’s the point of educa-
tion?) The argument has here been
stated in the context of the population
problem, but it applies equally well to
any instance in which society appeals
to an individual exploiting a commons
to restrain himself for the general
good-by means of his conscience. To
make such an appeal is to set up a
selective system that works toward the
elimination of conscience from the race.

Pathogenic Effects of Conscience

The long-term disadvantage of an
appeal to conscience should be enough
to condemn it; but has serious short-
term disadvantages as well. If we ask
a man who is exploiting a commons to
desist “in the name of conscience,”
what are we saying to him? What does
he hear?-not only at the moment but
also in the wee small hours of the
night when, half asleep, he remembers
not merely the words we used but also
the nonverbal communication cues we
gave him unawares? Sooner or later,
consciously or subconsciously, he senses
that he has received two communica-
tions, and that they are contradictory:
(i) (intended communication) “If you
don’t do as we ask, we will openly con-
demn you for not acting like a respon-
sible citizen”; (ii) (the unintended
communication) “If you do behave as
we ask, we will secretly condemr. you
for a simpleton who can be shamed
into standing aside while the rest of us
exploit the commons.”

Everyman then is caught in what
Bateson has called a “double bind.”
Bateson and his co-workers have made
a plausible case for viewing the double
bind as an important causative factor in
the genesis of schizophrenia (17). The
double bind may not always be so
damaging, but it always endangers the
mental health of anyone to whom it is
applied. “A bad conscience,” said
Nietzsche, “is a kind of illness.”
To conjure up a conscience in others

SCIENCE, VOL. 162
o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

is tempting to anyone who wishes to
extend his control beyond the legal
limits. Leaders at the highest level
succumb to this temptation. Has any
President during the past generation
failed to call on labor unions to moder-
ate voluntarily their demands for higher
wages, or to steel companies to honor
voluntary guidelines on prices? I can
recall none. The rhetoric used on such
occasions is designed to produce feel-
ings of guilt in noncooperators.
For centuries it was assumed without

proof that guilt was a valuable, perhaps
even an indispensable, ingredient of the
civilized life. Now, in this post-Freudian
world, we doubt it.

Paul Goodman speaks from the
modern point of view when he says:
“No good has ever come from feeling
guilty, neither intelligence, policy, nor
compassion. The guilty do not pay
attention to the object but only to them-
selves, and not even to their own in-
terests, which might make sense, but to
their anxieties” (18).
One does not have to be a profes-

sional psychiatrist to see the conse-
quences of anxiety. We in the Western
world are just emerging from a dreadful
two-centuries-long Dark Ages of Eros
that was sustained partly by prohibi-
tion laws, but perhaps more effectively
by the anxiety-generating mechanisms
of education. Alex Comfort has told the
story well in The Anxiety Makers (19);
it is not a pretty one.

Since proof is difficult, we may even
concede that the results of anxiety may
sometimes, from certain points of view,
be desirable. The larger question we
should ask is whether, as a matter of
policy, we should ever encourage the
use of a technique the tendency (if not
the intention) of which is psycholog-
ically pathogenic. We hear much talk
these days of responsible parenthood;
the coupled words are incorporated
into the titles of some organizations de-
voted to birth control. Some people
have proposed massive propaganda
campaigns to instill responsibility into
the nation’s (or the world’s) breeders.
But what is the meaning of the word
responsibility in this context? Is it not
merely a synonym for the word con-
science? When we use the word re-
sponsibility in the absence of substantial
sanctions are we not trying to browbeat
a free man in a commons into acting
against his own interest? Responsibility
is a verbal counterfeit for a substantial
quid pro quo. It is an attempt to get
something for nothing.
13 DECEMBER 1968

If the word responsibility is to be
used at all, I suggest that it be in the
sense Charles Frankel uses it (20).
“Responsibility,” says this philosopher,
“is the product of definite social ar-
rangements.” Notice that Frankel calls
for social arrangements-not propa-
ganda.

Mutual Coercion

Mutually Agreed upon

The social arrangements that produce
responsibility are arrangements that
create coercion, of some sort. Consid-
er bank-robbing. The man who takes
money from a bank acts as if the bank
were a commons. How do we prevent
such action? Certainly not by trying to
control his behavior solely by a verbal
appeal to his sense of responsibility.
Rather than rely on propaganda we
follow Frankel’s lead and insist that a
bank is not a commons; we seek the
definite social arrangements that will
keep it from becoming a commons.
That we thereby infringe on the free-
dom of would-be robbers we neither
deny nor regret.
The morality of bank-robbing is

particularly easy to understand because
we accept complete prohibition of this
activity. We are willing to say “Thou
shalt not rob banks,” without providing
for exceptions. But temperance also can
be created by coercion. Taxing is a good
coercive device. To keep downtown
shoppers temperate in their use of
parking space we introduce parking
meters for short periods, and traffic
fines for longer ones. We need not
actually forbid a citizen to park as long
as he wants to; we need merely make it
increasingly expensive for him to do so.
Not prohibition, but carefully biased
options are what we offer him. A Madi-
son Avenue man might call this per-
suasion; I prefer the greater candor of
the word coercion.

Coercion is a dirty word to most
liberals now, but it need not forever be
so. As with the four-letter words, its
dirtiness can be cleansed away by ex-
posure to the light, by saying it over and
over without apology or embarrassment.
To many, the word coercion implies
arbitrary decisions of distant and irre-
sponsible bureaucrats; but this is not a
necessary part of its meaning. The only
kind of coercion I recommend is mutual
coercion, mutually agreed upon by the
majority of the people affected.
To say that we mutually agree to

coercion is not to say that we are re-
quired to enjoy it, or even to pretend
we enjoy it. Who enjoys taxes? We all
grumble about them. But we accept
compulsory taxes because we recognize
that voluntary taxes would favor the
conscienceless. We institute and (grum-
blingly) support taxes and other coercive
devices to escape the horror of the
commons.
An alternative to the commons need

not be perfectly just to be preferable.
With real estate and other material
goods, the alternative we have chosen
is the institution of private property
coupled with legal inheritance. Is this
system perfectly just? As a genetically
trained biologist I deny that it is. It
seems to me that, if there are to be dif-
ferences in individual inheritance, legal
possession should be perfectly cor-
related with biological inheritance-that
those who are biologically more fit to
be the custodians of property and power
should legally inherit more. But genetic
recombination continually makes a
mockery of the doctrine of “like father,
like son” implicit in our laws of legal in-
heritance. An idiot can inherit millions,
and a trust fund can keep his estate
intact. We must admit that our legal
system of private property plus inheri-
tance is unjust-but we put up with it
because we are not convinced, at the
moment, that anyone has invented a
better system. The alternative of the
commons is too horrifying to contem-
plate. Injustice is preferable to total
ruin.

It is one of the peculiarities of the
warfare between reform and the status
quo that it is thoughtlessly governed
by a double standard. Whenever a re-
form measure is proposed it is often
defeated when its opponents trium-
phantly discover a flaw in it. As Kings-
ley Davis has pointed out (21), worship-
pers of the status quo sometimes imply
that no reform is possible without unan-
imous agreement, an implication con-
trary to historical fact. As nearly as I
can make out, automatic rejection of
proposed reforms is based on one of
two unconscious assumptions: (i) that
the status quo is perfect; or (ii) that the
choice we face is between reform and
no action; if the proposed reform is
imperfect, we presumably should take
no action at all, while we wait for a
perfect proposal.

But we can never do nothing. That
which we have done for thousands of
years is also action. It also produces
evils. Once we are aware that the

1247

o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

status quo is action, we can then com-
pare its discoverable advantages and
disadvantages with the predicted ad-
vantages and disadvantages of the pro-
posed reform, discounting as best we
can for our lack of experience. On the
basis of such a comparison, we can
make a rational decision which will not
involve the unworkable assumption that
only perfect systems are tolerable.

Recognition of Necessity

Perhaps the simplest summary of this
analysis of man’s population problems
is this: the commons, if justifiable at
all, is justifiable only under conditions
of low-population density. As the hu-
man population has increased, the
commons has had to be abandoned in
one aspect after another.

First we abandoned the commons in
food gathering, enclosing farm land
and restricting pastures and hunting
and fishing areas. These restrictions
are still not complete throughout the
world.
Somewhat later we saw that the com-

mons as a place for waste disposal
would also have to be abandoned. Re-
strictions on the disposal of domestic
sewage are widely accepted in the
Western world; we are still struggling
to close the commons to pollution by
automobiles, factories, insecticide
sprayers, fertilizing operations, and
atomic energy installations.

In a still more embryonic state is our
recognition of the evils of the commons
in matters of pleasure. There is almost
no restriction on the propagation of
sound waves in the public medium. The
shopping public is assaulted with mind-
less music, without its consent. Our

government is paying out billions of
dollars to create supersonic transport
which will disturb 50,000 people for
every one person who is whisked from
coast to coast 3 hours faster. Adver-
tisers muddy the airwaves of radio and
television and pollute the view of
travelers. We are a long way from out-
lawing the commons in matters of
pleasure. Is this because our Puritan
inheritance makes us view pleasure as
something of a sin, and pain (that is,
the pollution of advertising) as the sign
of virtue?

Every new enclosure of the com-
mons involves the infringement of
somebody’s personal liberty. Infringe-
ments made in the distant past are ac-
cepted because no contemporary com-
plains of a loss. It is the newly pro-
posed infringements that we vigorously
oppose; cries of “rights” and “freedom”
fill the air. But what does “freedom”
mean? When men mutually agreed to
pass laws against robbing, mankind be-
came more free, not less so. Individuals
locked into the logic of the commons
are free only to bring on universal ruin;
once they see the necessity of mutual
coercion, they become free to pursue
other goals. I believe it was Hegel who
said, “Freedom is the recognition of
necessity.”
The most important aspect of neces-

sity that we must now recognize, is the
necessity of abandoning the commons
in breeding. No technical solution can
rescue us from the misery of overpopu-
lation. Freedom to breed will bring
ruin to all. At the moment, to avoid
hard decisions many of us are tempted
to propagandize for conscience and
responsible parenthood. The tempta-
tion must be resisted, because an ap-
peal to independently acting con-

sciences selects for the disappearance
of all conscience in the long run, and
anin,crease in anxiety in the short.
The only way we can preserve and

nurture other and more precious free-
doms is by relinquishing the freedom
to breed, and that very soon. “Freedom
is the recognition of necessity”-and it
is the role of education to reveal to all
the necessity of abandoning the free-
dom to breed. Only so, can we put an
end to this aspect of the tragedy of the
commons.

References

1. J. B. Wiesner and H. F. York, Sci. Amer.
211 (No. 4), 27 (1964).

2. G. Hardin, J. Hered. 50, 68 (1959); S. von
Hoernor, Science 137, 18 (1962).

3. J. von Neumann and 0. Morgenstern, Theory
of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton
Univ. Press, Princeton, N.J., 1947), p. 11.

4. J. H. Fremlin, New Sci., No. 415 (1964), p. 285.
5. A. Smith, The Wealth of Nations (Modem

Library, New York, 1937), p. 423.
6. W. F. Lloyd, Two Lectures on the Checks to

Population (Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford, Eng-
land, 1833), reprinted (in part> in Population,
Evolution, and Birth Control, G. Hardin,
Ed. (Freeman, San Francisco, 1964), p. 37.

7. A. N. Whitehead, Science and the Modern
World (Mentor, New York, 1948), p. 17.

8. G. Hardin, Ed. Population, Evolution, and
Birth Control (Freeman, San Francisco, 1964),
p. 56.

9. S. McVay, Sci. Amer. 216 (No. 8>, 13 (1966).
10. J. Fletcher, Situation Ethics (Westminster,

Philadelphia, 1966).
11. D. Lack, The Natural Regulation of Animal

Nuimbers (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1954).
12. H. Girvetz, From Wealth to Welfare (Stan-

ford Univ. Press, Stanford, Calif., 1950).
13. G. Hardin, Perspec. Biol. Med. 6, 366 (1963).
14. U. Thant, Int. Planned Parenthood News, No.

168 (February 1968>, p. 3.
15. K. Davis, Science 158, 730 (1967).
16. S. Tax, Ed., Evolution after Darwin (Univ.

of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1960), vol. 2, p.
469.

17. G. Bateson, D. D. Jackson, J. Haley, J. Weak-
land, Behav. Scd. 1, 251 (1956).

18. P. Goodman, New York Rev. Books 10(8),
22 (23 May 1968).

19. A. Comfort, The Anxiety Makers (Nelson,
London, 1967).

20. C. Frankel, The Case for Modern Man (Har-
per, New York, 1955), p. 203.

21. J. D. Roslansky, Genetics and the Future of
Man (Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York,
1966), p. 177.

SCIENCE, VOL. 1621248

o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/

The Tragedy of the Commons
Garrett Hardin

DOI: 10.1126/science.162.3859.1243
(3859), 1243-1248.162Science

ARTICLE TOOLS http://science.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243

REFERENCES

http://science.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243#BIBL
This article cites 11 articles, 2 of which you can access for free

PERMISSIONS http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions

Terms of ServiceUse of this article is subject to the

trademark of AAAS.
is a registeredScienceAdvancement of Science, 1200 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005. The title

(print ISSN 0036-8075; online ISSN 1095-9203) is published by the American Association for theScience

of Science. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.
Copyright © 1968 The Authors, some rights reserved; exclusive licensee American Association for the Advancement

o
n
Ja
n
u
a
ry 1
3
, 2
0
2
0

h
ttp
://scie
n
ce
.scie
n
ce
m
a
g
.o
rg
/
D
o
w
n
lo
a
d
e
d
fro
m

http://science.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243

http://science.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243#BIBL

http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions

http://www.sciencemag.org/about/terms-service

http://science.sciencemag.org/

What Will You Get?

We provide professional writing services to help you score straight A’s by submitting custom written assignments that mirror your guidelines.

Premium Quality

Get result-oriented writing and never worry about grades anymore. We follow the highest quality standards to make sure that you get perfect assignments.

Experienced Writers

Our writers have experience in dealing with papers of every educational level. You can surely rely on the expertise of our qualified professionals.

On-Time Delivery

Your deadline is our threshold for success and we take it very seriously. We make sure you receive your papers before your predefined time.

24/7 Customer Support

Someone from our customer support team is always here to respond to your questions. So, hit us up if you have got any ambiguity or concern.

Complete Confidentiality

Sit back and relax while we help you out with writing your papers. We have an ultimate policy for keeping your personal and order-related details a secret.

Authentic Sources

We assure you that your document will be thoroughly checked for plagiarism and grammatical errors as we use highly authentic and licit sources.

Moneyback Guarantee

Still reluctant about placing an order? Our 100% Moneyback Guarantee backs you up on rare occasions where you aren’t satisfied with the writing.

Order Tracking

You don’t have to wait for an update for hours; you can track the progress of your order any time you want. We share the status after each step.

image

Areas of Expertise

Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

Areas of Expertise

Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

image

Trusted Partner of 9650+ Students for Writing

From brainstorming your paper's outline to perfecting its grammar, we perform every step carefully to make your paper worthy of A grade.

Preferred Writer

Hire your preferred writer anytime. Simply specify if you want your preferred expert to write your paper and we’ll make that happen.

Grammar Check Report

Get an elaborate and authentic grammar check report with your work to have the grammar goodness sealed in your document.

One Page Summary

You can purchase this feature if you want our writers to sum up your paper in the form of a concise and well-articulated summary.

Plagiarism Report

You don’t have to worry about plagiarism anymore. Get a plagiarism report to certify the uniqueness of your work.

Free Features $66FREE

  • Most Qualified Writer $10FREE
  • Plagiarism Scan Report $10FREE
  • Unlimited Revisions $08FREE
  • Paper Formatting $05FREE
  • Cover Page $05FREE
  • Referencing & Bibliography $10FREE
  • Dedicated User Area $08FREE
  • 24/7 Order Tracking $05FREE
  • Periodic Email Alerts $05FREE
image

Our Services

Join us for the best experience while seeking writing assistance in your college life. A good grade is all you need to boost up your academic excellence and we are all about it.

  • On-time Delivery
  • 24/7 Order Tracking
  • Access to Authentic Sources
Academic Writing

We create perfect papers according to the guidelines.

Professional Editing

We seamlessly edit out errors from your papers.

Thorough Proofreading

We thoroughly read your final draft to identify errors.

image

Delegate Your Challenging Writing Tasks to Experienced Professionals

Work with ultimate peace of mind because we ensure that your academic work is our responsibility and your grades are a top concern for us!

Check Out Our Sample Work

Dedication. Quality. Commitment. Punctuality

Categories
All samples
Essay (any type)
Essay (any type)
The Value of a Nursing Degree
Undergrad. (yrs 3-4)
Nursing
2
View this sample

It May Not Be Much, but It’s Honest Work!

Here is what we have achieved so far. These numbers are evidence that we go the extra mile to make your college journey successful.

0+

Happy Clients

0+

Words Written This Week

0+

Ongoing Orders

0%

Customer Satisfaction Rate
image

Process as Fine as Brewed Coffee

We have the most intuitive and minimalistic process so that you can easily place an order. Just follow a few steps to unlock success.

See How We Helped 9000+ Students Achieve Success

image

We Analyze Your Problem and Offer Customized Writing

We understand your guidelines first before delivering any writing service. You can discuss your writing needs and we will have them evaluated by our dedicated team.

  • Clear elicitation of your requirements.
  • Customized writing as per your needs.

We Mirror Your Guidelines to Deliver Quality Services

We write your papers in a standardized way. We complete your work in such a way that it turns out to be a perfect description of your guidelines.

  • Proactive analysis of your writing.
  • Active communication to understand requirements.
image
image

We Handle Your Writing Tasks to Ensure Excellent Grades

We promise you excellent grades and academic excellence that you always longed for. Our writers stay in touch with you via email.

  • Thorough research and analysis for every order.
  • Deliverance of reliable writing service to improve your grades.
Place an Order Start Chat Now
image

Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code Happy