Discussion 1

Carefully read Roger Scrouton’s essay “Scientism in the Arts and Humanities,” and choose a different question from the previous discussion in the research project list and answer it in relation to an issue in philosophy and technology according to theses of these two articles. Please only reference Scrouton’s essay and refrain from personal opinions. Your post should not have any first-person pronouns and as always. any badly written posts (i. e., clearly not proofread) will be downgraded. Also, simply writing the article’s author and the year is not a proper citation. All quotes and paraphrases necessitate FULL citations. Choose one or two from these questions: 

  1. What      is the problem for which this technology is the solution?
  2. Whose      problem is it?
  3. Which      people and what institutions might be most seriously harmed by a      technological solution?
  4. What      new problems might be created because we have solved this problem?
  5. What      sort of people and institutions might acquire special economic and      political power because of technological change?
  6. What      changes in language are being enforced by new technologies, and what is      being gained and lost by such changes?

Carefully read Roger Scrouton’s essay “Scientism in the Arts and Humanities,” and choose a different question from the previous discussion in the research project list and answer it in relation to an issue in philosophy and technology according to theses of these two articles. Please only reference Scrouton’s essay and refrain from personal opinions. Your post should not have any first-person pronouns and as always. any badly written posts (i. e., clearly not proofread) will be downgraded. Also, simply writing the article’s author and the year is not a proper citation. All quotes and paraphrases necessitate FULL citations. 

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
Discussion 1
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

Choose one or two from these questions:

1. What is the problem for which this technology is the solution?

2. Whose problem is it?

3. Which people and what institutions might be most seriously harmed by a technological solution?

4. What new problems might be created because we have solved this problem?

5. What sort of people and institutions might acquire special economic and political power because of technological change?

6. What changes in language are being enforced by new technologies, and what is being gained and lost by such changes?

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 1/21

Scientism in the Arts and Humanities
Why art is more than matter and meme

Roger Scruton

A s the universities expanded in the twentieth century, and as the hard sciences began to retreat to the marginsof an educational system increasingly reluctant to demand too much of its students, the humanities moved
to the center of the curriculum. First among them was English, a subject that established its place as a university

degree in Britain only about mid-century, and largely as a result of the failed attempt by I. A. Richards to treat the

study of literature as a branch of empirical psychology. Art history rose along with English, bringing with it the

Hegelian historical approach that had been developed in the German universities. And the growing prominence

of philosophy (still considered a branch of the “moral sciences” during my undergraduate days in Cambridge) laid

the foundations for the continuing expansion of the curriculum into areas as diverse as classical civilization, film

studies, and creative writing. The simultaneous expansion of the social sciences to encompass anthropology

(coupled to archaeology in the Cambridge of my youth), sociology, economics, political science, and the theory of

education meant that many of the new areas of study fell uneasily between arts and sciences and required

extensive borrowings from both. Take media studies: was it a branch of sociology or a subsection of literary

criticism? The habit very quickly arose during the 1960s and 1970s of throwing together clusters of disciplines

from the social sciences and the humanities in order to generate “studies” that would appeal to the increasingly

unqualified intake of students by conveying a spurious — and usually highly politicized — image of relevance.

In the current university, the impression arises that outside the hard sciences just about anything goes, and that

the humanities have neither a method nor a received body of knowledge, it being up to the professor to decide

what to teach in his class. Occasional attempts to establish a canon of great books are quickly and easily

Roger Scruton

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 2/21

overthrown, while the journals fill with articles devoted to what Jean Bricmont and Alan Sokal have castigated as

“fashionable nonsense.”

An additional problem has been created by the growth of post-graduate schools in the humanities and social

sciences. University departments and the people who teach in them are increasingly assessed — both for status

and for funding — on their output of “research.” The use of this word to describe what might formerly have gone

under the name of “scholarship” naturally suggests an affinity between the humanities and the sciences, implying

that both are engaged in discovering things, whether facts or theories, to be added in the same way to the store of

human knowledge. Pressed to justify their existence, therefore, the humanities begin to look to the sciences to

provide them with “research methods” and the promise of “results.” To suggest that the principal concern of the

humanities is the transmission of “culture” — as has been argued by the followers of the nineteenth-century poet

and critic Matthew Arnold — would be to condemn them to second-class status. If all the humanities have to

offer is “culture,” then they can hardly have the same claim on the public purse as the sciences, which constantly

add to the store of knowledge. Culture has no method, while research proceeds by conjecture and evidence.

Culture means the past, research means the future.

Moreover, once the defense of the humanities is made to rest on the “culture” they transmit, they become

vulnerable to deconstruction. One can summon any number of theories — the Marxist theory of “ideology,” or

some feminist, post-structuralist, or Foucauldian descendant of it — in proof of the view that the precious

achievements of our culture owe their status merely to the power that speaks through them, and hence that they

are of no intrinsic worth. In this way the whole idea of culture as an autonomous sphere of moral knowledge, one

that requires learning, scholarship, and immersion to enhance and retain, is cast to the winds. On this view,

instead of transmitting culture, the university exists to deconstruct it, to remove its aura. The university’s purpose

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 3/21

is to leave the student, after three or four years of anxious dissipation, with the view that anything goes and

nothing matters.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 4/21

T
Invading the Humanities

his transformation of the humanities into an anti-cultural force seems to be where we are today — or nearly

so. Increasingly, we can see attempts to rectify the humanities’ difficulties by assimilating their subject

matter to one or another of the sciences.

Take, for instance, art history. Generations of students have been drawn to this subject in the hope of acquiring

knowledge of the masterpieces of the past. Art history had developed in nineteenth-century German universities,

under the influence of the Swiss historians Jacob Burkhardt, Heinrich Wölfflin, and others, to become a paradigm

of objective study in the humanities. The Hegelian theory of the Zeitgeist, put to astute use by Wölfflin, divided

everything into neatly circumscribed periods — Renaissance, Baroque, Rococo, neoclassical, and so on. And the

“comparative” method, in which images were shown side by side and their differences assigned to the

distinguishing mental frameworks of their creators, proved endlessly fertile in critical judgments. Look at the

works of Wittkower, Panofsky, Gombrich, and the other products of this school of thought, many of whom fled to

safety from the Nazi destruction of the German universities, and you will surely conclude that there has never

been a more creative and worthwhile addition to the curriculum in modern times.

Yet the scholars are not satisfied. Is there any more “research” to be done on the art of Michelangelo, or the

architecture of Palladio? Is there anything to be added to the study of the Gothic cathedral after Ruskin, von

Simson, Pevsner, and Sedlmayr? And how do we confront the complaint that this whole subject seems to be

focused on a narrow range of dead white European males, who spoke clearly for their times, but who have no

great relevance to ours? All in all, the subject of art history has been condemned by its own success to a corner of

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 5/21

the academy, there to be starved of funds and graduate students — unless, that is, it can be endowed with some

new field of “research.”

Similar problems have bedeviled musicology and literary studies, and in each case the temptation has arisen to

look for some branch of the natural sciences that could be applied to their subject matter, so as to rescue it from

its methodless sterility. Two sciences in particular seem to fit the bill: evolutionary psychology and neuroscience.

Both are sciences of the mind, and since culture is a mental arena, both sciences ought to be capable of making

sense of it. Evolutionary psychology treats mental states as adaptations, and explains them in terms of the

reproductive advantages they conferred on our ancestors; neuroscience treats them as aspects of the nervous

system, and explains them in terms of their cognitive function.

Over the last several decades, therefore, we have witnessed a steady invasion of the humanities by scientific

methodology. This invasion provides us with a useful illustration of the distinction between scientific and

scientistic ways of thinking. The scientific thinker has a clear question, a body of data, and a theoretical answer to

the question that can be tested against that data. The scientistic thinker borrows the apparatus of science, not in

order to explain the phenomenon before him, but in order to create the appearance of a scientific question, the

appearance of data, and the appearance of a method that will arrive at an answer.

Structuralism in literary criticism, as exemplified by Roland Barthes in his 1970 book S/Z, was scientistic in this

sense. It raised questions that had the appearance of science, and addressed them with theories that could not be

refuted since they failed to make predictions. Barthes’s flamboyant analysis of Balzac’s short story “Sarrasine,”

casting about the technicalities of Saussurian linguistics, created a certain stir in its day, and was immediately

taken up by literary critics hungry for a “method” that would deliver results. The results never came, and that

particular episode is now more or less forgotten.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 6/21

A similar case today can be found in the new “science” of “neuroaesthetics,” introduced and championed by V. S.

Ramachandran, Semir Zeki, and William Hirstein, which promises to produce its own journal and already has a

growing pile of publications devoted to its results. And the art historian John Onians has followed this example by

attempting to recast his discipline as the science of (as the title of his 2008 book calls it) Neuroarthistory.

Philosophers and critics have, over the centuries, asked themselves questions about the meaning of art, why it is

so special, and why it affects us as it does. Their speculations have been subtle, difficult, and alert at every point to

the human significance of the subject — what the work of art means to us, who interpret it and take it to heart.

This human significance is a cultural phenomenon — the kind of thing that the humanities emerged in order to

study. And so the first move of Ramachandran and Hirstein, in the 1999 paper in which they laid out their theory,

is to present art as already dressed in the science they propose to apply to it:

The purpose of art, surely, is not merely to depict or represent reality — for that can be accomplished very

easily with a camera — but to enhance, transcend, or indeed even to distort reality…. [W]hat the artist tries

to do (either consciously or unconsciously) is to not only capture the essence of something but also to

amplify it in order to more powerfully activate the same neural mechanisms that would be activated by the

original object.

Having thus reduced the effect of art to one of perceptual distortion, and dazzled the reader with a reference to

“neural mechanisms,” Ramachandran and Hirstein summon a psychological principle — the “peak shift” effect, by

which an animal that has learned to respond to a stimulus responds more strongly to an exaggeration of that

stimulus — to give a general explanation of “what art really is.” The ensuing mishmash of abridged and

misapplied theories has been explored and exploded by the British professor of philosophy and aesthetics John

Hyman. In his 2010 article “Art and Neuroscience,” Hyman shows that the neuroaestheticians misunderstand the

http://neuroesthetics.org/journal_of_neuroesthetics.php

http://www.imprint.co.uk/rama/art

http://www.queens.ox.ac.uk/academics/hyman/files/art_and_neuroscience

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 7/21

peak shift effect, that they are woefully ignorant of art, and that their theories really have nothing to say about art

as distinct from non-art. For our present purposes, it is also worth noting the way in which science intrudes into

Ramachandran’s description of the subject. Instead of a careful and circumspect attempt to define a problem,

there is a perfunctory description of a few artistic phenomena, an unwarranted reference to a preferred

explanation (“neural mechanisms”), and an anticipation of the result of applying it. This is the sure sign of

scientism — that the science precedes the question, and is used to redefine it as a question that the science can

solve. But the difficulty of understanding art arises precisely because questions about the nature and meaning of

art are not asking for an explanation of something, but for a description.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 8/21

W
Science and the Subjective

hy should there be such questions, and why is it that they lie beyond the reach of the empirical sciences?

The simple answer is that they are questions that deal with the “spirit,” with Geist, and therefore with

phenomena that lie outside the purview of experimental methods. But this is not an answer that would satisfy

people today; putting it that way is likely to prompt a wry, skeptical smile. The “spirit” vanished with Kant’s

demolition of the Cartesian theory of the subject. Or if it didn’t vanish, then how could it have survived the

advances in cognitive science, genetics, and evolutionary psychology that have abolished the illusions through

which religion governed our world? All that Ramachandran and company are doing, it might be said, is to replace

the vague language in which the dispute between science and the Geisteswissenschaften — “spirit or mind studies,”

in some ways a more helpful term than our “liberal arts” — was originally formulated with something more in

keeping with our modern view of what we are. The problem is that there is no agreed-upon “modern view of what

we are,” in no small part because we are unsure of the relation between “we” and “I,” being unsure of the place of

the self-conscious individual in the science of the species.

As a conscious subject, I have a point of view on the world. The world seems a certain way to me, and this

“seeming” defines my unique perspective. Every self-conscious being has such a perspective; this is what it means

to be a subject rather than an object. When I give a scientific account of the world, however, I am describing only

objects. I am describing the way things are, and the causal laws that explain the way things are. This description is

given from no particular perspective. It does not contain words like “here,” “now,” and “I”; and while it is meant to

explain the way things seem, it does so by giving a theory of how they are. In short, the subject is in principle

unobservable to science — not because it exists in another realm but because it is not part of the empirical world.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 9/21

It lies on the edge of things, like a horizon, and could never be grasped “from the other side,” the side of

subjectivity itself.

Is the subject a real part of the real world? In one sense not. For if I look for it in the world of objects I shall never

find it. But without my nature as a subject, nothing for me is real. If I am to care for my world, then I must first

care for this thing, the subject, without which I have no perspective from which to see the world, and so have no

world. This attention to the subject is the purpose of art, or at least of the art that matters. And that is one reason

why those humanities that have art and culture as their theme will never be reducible to natural sciences.

We understand others through the attitudes that Martin Buber summarized as relations between Ich and Du (I

and You) but which would perhaps better be described as relations between I and I. We see each other I to I, and

from this relation all judgment, all responsibility, all shame, pride, and fulfillment arise. This momentous fact

about the human condition might be summarized in the word bequeathed to us by Roman law, and taken up by

Boethius and Aquinas: “person.” We are persons, and personality is of our essence.

Flowing from personality, there are concepts that play an organizing role in our experience — concepts like

ornament, melody, duty, and freedom — but belong to no scientific theory because they divide up the world in a

way that no natural science could countenance. Science tells us a lot about the ordered sequences of pitched

sounds; but it tells us nothing about melodies. A melody is not an acoustical but a musical object. And musical

objects belong to the purely intentional realm: they are about something else; they are imbued with meaning; they

are sounds as we self-conscious beings experience and relate to them. The concept of the person is like the

concept of a melody. It features in our way of perceiving and relating to each other, but it does not “carry over”

into the science of what we are. The fact that the person does not carry over into science does not mean that there

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 10/21

are no persons, but only that a scientific theory of persons will classify them with other things — for example,

with apes or other mammals.

In other words, the kind of thing we are is defined through a concept that does not feature in the science of our

nature. Science sees us as objects rather than as subjects, and its descriptions of our responses are not descriptions

of what we feel. When we refer to the soul, we generally do not refer to some Cartesian substance floating in the

inner nowhere. We refer to the organizing principle of first-person awareness: the capacities for self-attribution,

self-knowledge, and inter-subjective response that seem to distinguish ours from every other species, and that

make the life of a person into a thing worthwhile. This organizing principle is what Aristotle and Aquinas meant

by describing the soul as the form and the body as the matter of the human being; all that I have added to their

account is to define the form in terms of the organization exhibited by the first-person singular — that is, in

terms of a person.

Our behavior towards each other is founded on the belief in freedom, in selfhood, in the knowledge that I am I

and you are you and that each of us is a center of free and responsible thought and action. Out of these beliefs

arises the whole world of interpersonal responses, and it is from the relations established between us that our

own self-conception derives. It would seem to follow that we have an existential need to clarify the concepts of

the self, of free choice, of responsibility and the rest if we are to have a clear conception of what we are, and that

no amount of neuroscience is going to help us to clarify those concepts. We live on the surface, and what matters

to us are not the invisible nervous systems that explain how people work but the visible appearances to which we

respond when we respond to people as people. It is these appearances that we interpret; and it is upon these

interpretations that we craft responses that will in turn be interpreted; and so on. It is because culture is built

upon these interpersonal and inter-subjective relations that it is a distinct realm of human inquiry, one which

cannot be replaced by a natural science.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 11/21

T
What Pictures Are About

his returns us to the history of art and the study of pictures. What are pictures — scientifically speaking, in

contrast to what they mean? It is fairly obvious that Titian’s famous painting of the Venus of Urbino (1538)

consists of a canvas on which are distributed pigments (see below). We could describe this distribution using

geometrical coordinates in two-dimensional space, and so pixelize Titian’s picture in a digital formula that

enables a machine to reproduce it. This formula makes no mention of the woman, her servant, or the eyes that

challenge and the hand that hides. Yet it contains all the information necessary to produce the image, in which

those things are seen by someone who has the capacity to understand pictures. We could imagine animals who

were adept at recognizing the distribution of pixels, and could selectively respond to every difference between

patterns of pigments that we see as pictures, but who could not see pictures. And of course, we are familiar with

the digital programs that record, transmit, and present pixelated images in machines that see nothing at all.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Tiziano_-_Venere_di_Urbino_-_Google_Art_Project

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 12/21

Titian, Venus of Urbino (1538), Galleria delli Uffizi, Florence
Wikimedia

https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Tiziano_-_Venere_di_Urbino_-_Google_Art_Project

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 13/21

The normal response to that kind of example is to say that pictorial images are emergent features of the physical

objects in which they are contained. The picture of the young lady of Urbino is not something over and above the

colored patches in which we see it, but neither is the picture reducible to these patches: though the right

distribution of colored patches can produce the picture, what it is is a feature of the painting that emerges for

those with the imaginative powers required to perceive it. Indeed, someone might be an expert in producing

copies of the Venus of Urbino even though he is blind to its subject matter, and sees it only as a distribution of

pigments on a canvas.

It is certain that there is much to be said about Titian’s painting in terms of the disposition of pigments on a two-

dimensional matrix. But it will not amount to an interpretation of the painting and will tell us nothing about its

significance or value. For it will not mention the most important fact about the painting, which is what it is about.

The word “about” is notorious: it is the very same word that causes all those difficulties in understanding mental

states that were once thought to present an immovable obstacle to any simple physical analysis of the mind.

Pictures have intentionality just like beliefs and desires. And they can be compared in this respect not only with

other paintings but with works of literature and music. It is a question of interpretation whether Titian’s painting

is to be understood as the expression of a domestic and nuptial sexuality, or whether the young lady is to be seen

more as a courtesan than a wife. One can compare the painting with another that explicitly refers to Titian’s, the

famous Olympia by Manet (1863, see below), in which the rough trade of the Boulevard is put in ironical relation

to the soft downy embraces of Renaissance Venice. Interpretation starts here, in comparative judgment, and it is

hard to see what neuroscience can contribute to the result. Pictures are understood by finding their meaning, and

by assessing the place of that meaning in the life of the observer, and what it conveys about the human condition.

You are likely to gain insight into Manet’s painting if you set it side by side with two novels: Daudet’s Sappho

(1884) and Zola’s Nana (1880). You understand what Manet is saying better if you see Titian’s world ironically

reflected in the forms and props that surround this hard-bitten boulevardienne.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Edouard_Manet_-_Olympia_-_Google_Art_Project_3

https://archive.org/stream/sapphoparisianma00daud#page/n7/mode/2up

https://archive.org/stream/nananana00zolarich#page/n7/mode/2up

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 14/21

Édouard Manet, Olympia (1863), Musée d’Orsay, Paris
Wikimedia

https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Edouard_Manet_-_Olympia_-_Google_Art_Project_4

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 15/21

Art critics have a discipline, and it is one that involves reasoning and judgment. It is not a science, and what it

describes forms no part of the physical world, which does not contain Olympia or anything else you see in

Manet’s painting. Yet someone who thought that art criticism is therefore deficient and ought to be replaced by

the study of pigments would surely be missing the point. There are forms of human understanding that can be

neither reduced to science nor enhanced by it.

Here is where the neurothugs step in, to declare that, of course, the science of pixels won’t explain pictures, since

pictures are in the eye of the beholder. But there is also such a thing as the fMRI of the beholder, and this does

contain the secret of the image in the frame. Since understanding a picture is a matter of seeing it in a certain way

— in such a way as to grasp its visual aspect, and the meaning which that aspect has for beings like us — then we

should be examining the neural pathways involved in seeing aspects, and the connections that link those

pathways to judgments of meaning.

But what, exactly, would such a study show? Suppose we have achieved a perfect decipherment of the pathways

involved in seeing an aspect and in stabilizing it in the mind of the observer. This is not a judgment of criticism,

and while it might enable us to predict that the normal observer will, on confronting Titian’s picture, see a naked

woman lying on a couch and looking at him, it will say nothing in answer to the critic who says: Yes, but that is

not all that there is, and indeed you must see that this woman is not naked at all, but rather unclothed, that her

body, as Anne Hollander shows so convincingly in Seeing Through Clothes, has the texture and the movement of

the clothes she has removed, and that those eyes do not look at you but look through you, dreaming of someone

you are not. Critics don’t tell us how we do, with normal equipment, see things, but how we ought to see them,

and their account of the meaning of a picture is also a recommendation, which we obey by making a free choice of

our own. Neuroscience, then, remains only a science: it cannot rise to the level of intentional understanding,

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 16/21

where meaning is created through our own voluntary acts. Hence we should not be surprised at the dreariness of

neuroaesthetics, and its inability to cast light on the nature or meaning of works of art.

Just as there is an understanding of art, which forms the domain of criticism, and which is a rational exercise with

its own standards of validity, so there is an understanding of people, which forms the domain of interpersonal

relations, and which is a rational exercise obedient to norms of its own. And just as it is an error to think you can

replace art criticism with the neuroscience that allegedly explains the experience of art, so too is it an error to

think you can replace interpersonal understanding with the neuroscience that allegedly explains our behavior.

This shift requires describing human behavior in terms that remove it from the context that gives it sense; it

requires becoming a reductionist, someone who fails to see that the most important features of the human

condition are emergent features, ones that inhabit the surface of the world and are invisible to those whose eyes

are fixed on the depths.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 17/21

H
The Meme Delusion

uman cultures are reflections on and in the surface of life, ways in which we understand the world of

persons, and the moral framework within which persons live. But this exalted idea of culture has in recent

decades undergone another scientistic assault, this time from Richard Dawkins and his concept of the “meme,”

first spelled out in The Selfish Gene (1976). Natural selection can account for all the difficult facts presented by

human culture, Dawkins suggests, once we see culture as evolving according to the same Darwinian principles

that drive biological evolution. Just as any organism is a “survival machine” that exists to serve self-replicating

genes, human beings are also “survival machines” for self-replicating “memes” — mental entities that use the

energies of human brains to multiply, in the way that viruses use the energies of cells. Like genes, memes need a

place to inhabit, and their success depends upon finding the ecological niche that enables them to generate more

examples of their kind. That niche is the human brain.

A meme is a self-replicating cultural entity that, lodging in the brain of a human being, uses that brain to

reproduce itself — just in the way that a catchy tune reproduces itself in hums and whistles, spreading like an

epidemic through a human community, like “La donna è mobile” the morning after the first performance of

Verdi’s Rigoletto. Dawkins argues that ideas, beliefs, and attitudes are the conscious forms taken by these self-

replicating entities, which propagate themselves as diseases propagate themselves, by using the energies of their

hosts: “Just as genes propagate themselves in the gene pool by leaping from body to body via sperm or eggs, so

memes propagate themselves in the meme pool by leaping from brain to brain via a process which, in the broad

sense, can be called imitation.” Daniel Dennett, in such books as Freedom Evolves (2003) and Breaking the Spell:

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 18/21

Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (2006), adds that this process can be variously harmful or beneficial to the host

— parasitic or symbiotic.

The theory of the “meme” threatens to debunk the whole realm of high culture by making culture into a thing

that survives in the human brain by its own efforts, as it were, and which has no more intrinsic significance than

any other network of adaptations. To make the theory remotely plausible, however, Dawkins has to distinguish

memes that belong to science from memes that are merely “cultural.” Scientific memes are subject to effective

policing by the brains that harbor them, which accept ideas and theories only as part of science’s own truth-

directed method. Merely cultural memes are outside the purview of scientific inference and can run riot, causing

all kinds of cognitive and emotional disorders. They are subject to no external discipline, such as that contained in

the concept of truth, but follow their own reproductive path, indifferent to the aims of the organism they have

invaded.

The meme idea is appealing at the level of metaphor, but what does it amount to in fact? From the point of view

of memetics, absurd ideas have the same start in life as true theories, and assent is a retrospective honor bestowed

on the ones that succeed in reproducing. The only significant distinction to be made, when accounting for this

success, is between memes that enhance the life of their hosts, and memes that either destroy that life or coexist

commensally with it.

One of the distinguishing characteristics of human beings, however, is that they can distinguish a concept from

the reality it describes, can entertain propositions from which they withhold their assent, and so can move judge-

like in the realm of ideas, calling each before the bar of rational argument, accepting them and rejecting them

regardless of the reproductive cost. And it is not only in science that this attitude of critical reflection is

maintained. Matthew Arnold, in his classic collection of essays Culture and Anarchy (1869), famously described

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 19/21

culture as “a pursuit of our total perfection by means of getting to know, on all the matters which most concern

us, the best which has been thought and said in the world, and, through this knowledge, turning a stream of fresh

and free thought upon our stock notions and habits.”

Like so many people wedded to a nineteenth-century view of science, which promised scientific explanations for

social and cultural phenomena, Dawkins overlooks the nineteenth-century reaction that said: Wait a minute;

science is not the only way to pursue knowledge. There is moral knowledge too, which is the province of practical

reason; there is emotional knowledge, which is the province of art, literature, and music. And just possibly there is

transcendental knowledge, which is the province of religion. Why privilege science, just because it sets out to

explain the world? Why not give weight to the disciplines that interpret the world, and so help us to be at home in

it?

That reaction has lost none of its appeal. And it points to a fundamental weakness in “memetics.” Even if there are

units of memetic information propagated from brain to brain, it is not these units that come before the mind in

conscious thinking. Memes stand to ideas as genes stand to organisms: if they exist at all (and no evidence has

been given by Dawkins or anyone else that they do) then their ceaseless and purposeless reproduction is of no

concern to culture. Ideas, by contrast, form part of the conscious network of critical thinking. We assess them for

their truth, their validity, their moral propriety, their elegance, completeness, and charm. We take them up and

discard them, sometimes in the course of our search for truth and explanation, sometimes in our search for

meaning and value. And both activities are essential to us. Although culture isn’t science, it is just as much a

conscious activity of the critical mind. Culture — both the high culture of art and music, and the wider culture

embodied in a moral and religious tradition — sorts ideas by their intrinsic qualities, helps us to feel at home in

the world and to resonate to its personal significance.

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 20/21

It is true that the theory of the meme does not deny the role of culture, nor does it undermine the nineteenth-

century view that culture properly understood is as much an activity of the rational mind as is science. But the

concept of the meme belongs with other subversive concepts — Marx’s “ideology,” Freud’s unconscious,

Foucault’s “discourse” — in being aimed at discrediting common prejudice. It seeks to expose illusions and to

explain away our dreams. But the meme is itself a dream, a piece of ideology, accepted not for its truth but for the

illusory power that it confers on the one who conjures with it. It has produced some striking arguments, not least

those given by Daniel Dennett in Breaking the Spell, in which he explains away religion as a particularly successful

but dangerous meme.

But memetics possesses the very fault for which it purports to be a remedy: it is a spell with which the scientistic

mind seeks to conjure away the things that pose a threat to it — which is also how we should view scientism in

general. Scientism involves the use of scientific forms and categories in order to give the appearance of science to

unscientific ways of thinking. It is a form of magic, a bid to reassemble the complex matter of human life, at the

magician’s command, in a shape over which he can exert control. It is an attempt to subdue what it does not

understand.

Surely human beings can do better than this — by the pursuit of genuine scientific explanation on the one hand,

and by the study of high culture on the other. A culture does not comprise works of art only, nor is it directed

solely to aesthetic interests. It is the sphere of intrinsically interesting artifacts, linked by the faculty of judgment

to our aspirations and ideals. We appreciate works of art, arguments, works of history and literature, manners,

dress, jokes, and forms of behavior. And all these things are shaped through judgment. But what kind of

judgment, and to what does that judgment lead?

3/16/2021 Scientism in the Arts and Humanities — The New Atlantis

https://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/scientism-in-the-arts-and-humanities 21/21

It is my belief that culture in this sense, which stems from the “I” perspective that is the root of the human

condition, points always towards the transcendental — the point on the edge of space and time, which is the

subjectivity of the world. And when we lose our sense of that thing, and of its eternal, tranquil watchfulness, all

human life is cast into shadow. We approach the point at which even the St. Matthew Passion and the Rondanini

Pietà have nothing more to say to us than a shark in formaldehyde. That is the direction we have taken. But it is a

direction of drift, a refusal to adopt the posture that is inherent in the human condition, in which we strive to see

events from outside and as a whole, as they are in the eyes of God.

Roger Scruton, a New Atlantis contributing editor, is a visiting professor of philosophy at Oxford University and a
senior fellow at the Ethics and Public Policy Center. His latest books are The Soul of the World (Princeton, April 2014)
and the novel Notes from Underground (Beaufort, March 2014). A longer version of this essay will appear in
Scientism: The New Orthodoxy, edited by Daniel N. Robinson and Richard Williams (Bloomsbury, November 2014).

Roger Scruton, “Scientism in the Arts and Humanities,” The New Atlantis, Number 40, Fall 2013, pp. 33-46.

Header image via Shutterstock

Roger Scruton

http://www.shutterstock.com/pic-153307175/stock-vector-woman-meditating-and-inducing-calmness-physical-relaxation-improving-the-cogs-of-psychological.html

Running

Head: DISCUSSION

1

DISCUSSION 2

Discussion

Student’s name

Institutional affiliation

Technology represents the art of applying scientific processes and ideologies in the production of goods and services. Technological advancement represents the most significant invention and progress in human history. Technology invention is credited for enhancing convenience, improving the production capacity, reducing the production time while improving the lead time. Most organizations and individuals focus on technology due to improving the quality of products and services they produce. The impact of technology can therefore be not overlooked as the world has been tremendously been changed the technology. Technology has the ability to impact the lives of individuals in a negative manner and through Roger Scruton’s essay, it is easier to pinpoint the negative effect that technology can have on individuals through tinkering with their daily life activities. In the article, we will seek to answer the question about describing the kind of people and institutions that are most likely to be affected by the technological intervention and the kind of people or institutions that are most likely to benefit from a technological intervention as described by Roger Scruton in his essay, “Scientism in the art and humanity.”

With each technological intervention, there are those people and organizations that or whom are most primed to maximumly benefit and there are those whose livelihood and way of life is mostly going to be cut shot. As described by Scruton in his essay some of the people who are at the forefront of being affected by technology are artists. Artists especially those who draw paints write and sing and produce songs are mostly going to be negatively affected by technological interventions since they rely on their logical and mental abilities to produce what they can (Scruton, 2020). Most technological advancements lack the mental abilities to develop or invent ideas from scratch and what they mostly do is increase the speed and accuracy of reproducing already invented ideas and most of the time they lack the authenticity or the logic of seeking reproduction authority from the original creators of the content. Take, for example, the illustration that Scruton used in his essay regarding Titian, Venus of Urbino paint created in 1538, he illustrated that technological intervention with the capabilities to reproduce the exact authentic pictures using pixels and copying it to the digital world have been invented by those who lack the idea of what is inscribed or illustrated by the ink in those paints. the inventors of these technologies lack the mental capabilities to comprehend what is hidden in the pictures or art that their technologies can produce with precision, speed, and accuracy. The original creators of art affect negatively since many people access their art without their involvement hence negatively affecting their financial status.

As described through the article, those individuals and organizations that are bound to benefit through technological invention are those who do not or lack the mental capabilities to produce original contents or those who lack the time and moral standards to look for original and authentic products and only rely or buy what they can see as they want to reduce on cost and save money. Others who would benefit are those who lack the moral standards and self-discipline to desist from illegally reproducing other people’s original content.

References

Scruton, R. (2020, September 26). Scientism in the Arts and Humanities. The New Atlantis. Retrieved from

Scientism in the Arts and Humanities

Running Head: DISCUSSION

1

Discussion

Student’s name

Institutional affiliation

Running Head: DISCUSSION 1

Discussion

Student’s name

Institutional affiliation

What Will You Get?

We provide professional writing services to help you score straight A’s by submitting custom written assignments that mirror your guidelines.

Premium Quality

Get result-oriented writing and never worry about grades anymore. We follow the highest quality standards to make sure that you get perfect assignments.

Experienced Writers

Our writers have experience in dealing with papers of every educational level. You can surely rely on the expertise of our qualified professionals.

On-Time Delivery

Your deadline is our threshold for success and we take it very seriously. We make sure you receive your papers before your predefined time.

24/7 Customer Support

Someone from our customer support team is always here to respond to your questions. So, hit us up if you have got any ambiguity or concern.

Complete Confidentiality

Sit back and relax while we help you out with writing your papers. We have an ultimate policy for keeping your personal and order-related details a secret.

Authentic Sources

We assure you that your document will be thoroughly checked for plagiarism and grammatical errors as we use highly authentic and licit sources.

Moneyback Guarantee

Still reluctant about placing an order? Our 100% Moneyback Guarantee backs you up on rare occasions where you aren’t satisfied with the writing.

Order Tracking

You don’t have to wait for an update for hours; you can track the progress of your order any time you want. We share the status after each step.

image

Areas of Expertise

Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

Areas of Expertise

Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

image

Trusted Partner of 9650+ Students for Writing

From brainstorming your paper's outline to perfecting its grammar, we perform every step carefully to make your paper worthy of A grade.

Preferred Writer

Hire your preferred writer anytime. Simply specify if you want your preferred expert to write your paper and we’ll make that happen.

Grammar Check Report

Get an elaborate and authentic grammar check report with your work to have the grammar goodness sealed in your document.

One Page Summary

You can purchase this feature if you want our writers to sum up your paper in the form of a concise and well-articulated summary.

Plagiarism Report

You don’t have to worry about plagiarism anymore. Get a plagiarism report to certify the uniqueness of your work.

Free Features $66FREE

  • Most Qualified Writer $10FREE
  • Plagiarism Scan Report $10FREE
  • Unlimited Revisions $08FREE
  • Paper Formatting $05FREE
  • Cover Page $05FREE
  • Referencing & Bibliography $10FREE
  • Dedicated User Area $08FREE
  • 24/7 Order Tracking $05FREE
  • Periodic Email Alerts $05FREE
image

Our Services

Join us for the best experience while seeking writing assistance in your college life. A good grade is all you need to boost up your academic excellence and we are all about it.

  • On-time Delivery
  • 24/7 Order Tracking
  • Access to Authentic Sources
Academic Writing

We create perfect papers according to the guidelines.

Professional Editing

We seamlessly edit out errors from your papers.

Thorough Proofreading

We thoroughly read your final draft to identify errors.

image

Delegate Your Challenging Writing Tasks to Experienced Professionals

Work with ultimate peace of mind because we ensure that your academic work is our responsibility and your grades are a top concern for us!

Check Out Our Sample Work

Dedication. Quality. Commitment. Punctuality

Categories
All samples
Essay (any type)
Essay (any type)
The Value of a Nursing Degree
Undergrad. (yrs 3-4)
Nursing
2
View this sample

It May Not Be Much, but It’s Honest Work!

Here is what we have achieved so far. These numbers are evidence that we go the extra mile to make your college journey successful.

0+

Happy Clients

0+

Words Written This Week

0+

Ongoing Orders

0%

Customer Satisfaction Rate
image

Process as Fine as Brewed Coffee

We have the most intuitive and minimalistic process so that you can easily place an order. Just follow a few steps to unlock success.

See How We Helped 9000+ Students Achieve Success

image

We Analyze Your Problem and Offer Customized Writing

We understand your guidelines first before delivering any writing service. You can discuss your writing needs and we will have them evaluated by our dedicated team.

  • Clear elicitation of your requirements.
  • Customized writing as per your needs.

We Mirror Your Guidelines to Deliver Quality Services

We write your papers in a standardized way. We complete your work in such a way that it turns out to be a perfect description of your guidelines.

  • Proactive analysis of your writing.
  • Active communication to understand requirements.
image
image

We Handle Your Writing Tasks to Ensure Excellent Grades

We promise you excellent grades and academic excellence that you always longed for. Our writers stay in touch with you via email.

  • Thorough research and analysis for every order.
  • Deliverance of reliable writing service to improve your grades.
Place an Order Start Chat Now
image

Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code Happy