This case study describes how a company embarked on improving its image to its customer base. The company formed a community of practice amongst its employees, with the goal of developing a positive image of the company, by highlighting the company’s positive impact on the community and environment. The company also set aside a budget for donations to nominated sustainability charities. Part of this initiative was a social media launch and a campaign to highlight the company’s support for various sustainability charities. This plan had been received very positively by its executive team, because of the projected increased brand exposure. Many employees also expressed their support for the proposals for this social media release, and they even proposed ways of measuring the impact of the social media campaign and potential market gain.
However, some employees within the company had personal reservations about this campaign. Although they were asked to provide their comments, employees were careful not to say anything, as this campaign had gained widespread traction amongst high-level executives. As a consequence, there were internal conflicts. Some employees decided that they had had no opportunity to voice their concerns, and they resigned from the company. Other employees were not so fortunate and could not find other employment. These employees remained quiet but felt they were disempowered and unable to voice their opinions. These employees felt socially isolated.
As it turned out, the company was heavily criticized on social media at the launch of the campaign. Members of the public flooded the company’s social media page with complaints about the company’s instrumental approach toward corporate social responsibility (CSR) and sustainability. They felt the company was being disrespectful towards the charity and accused the company of being hypocritical in their intentions and caring only about the image of the company. The company was accused of using charities to increase its market share. This vitriolic attack came as a surprise, and the company did not have any plan to respond. The company shut down its social media page and withdrew from the campaign.
You have been engaged by the company to do a study on this failed campaign and to write a report. The purpose of this is to enable the company to learn from what occurred, and for its future proposals to avoid this situation.
Prepare a report, for your executives. Your report should be 2500 words maximum, excluding references and appendices, and should cover the following issues and include the following components:
There might be conflicting perspectives amongst the members of the company; and
The backlash from the public against this marketing campaign was predictable.
Hirschheim, R. & Klein, H. K. (1989). Four paradigms of information systems development. Communications of the ACM, Vol. 32(10): 1199-1216. THIS IS YOUR KEY THEORETICAL TEXT AND MUST BE DRAWN ON EXTENSIVELY TO INFORM YOUR WORK.
Burrell, G & Morgan, G 1979, Sociological paradigms and organisational analysis, Routledge, USA. (Part 1, Chapters 1–3, pp. 1–37): Burrell & Morgan, Sociological paradigms and organisational analysis
Cho, C.H., Laine, M., Roberts, R.W., & Rodrigue, M. (2015). Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and sustainability reporting, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 40: 78-94.
Atkins, J., Atkins, B.C., Thomson, I., Maroun, W. (2015). “Good” news from nowhere: Imagining utopian sustainable accounting, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 28(5): 651-670.
StuDocu is not sponsored or endorsed by any college or university
BUSM1094 Assignment 3
Organisational Analysis (RMIT)
StuDocu is not sponsored or endorsed by any college or university
BUSM1094 Assignment 3
Organisational Analysis (RMIT)
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
https://www.studocu.com/en/document/rmit/organisational-analysis/mandatory-assignments/busm1094-assignment-3/5468873/view?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
https://www.studocu.com/en/course/rmit/organisational-analysis/3221964?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
https://www.studocu.com/en/document/rmit/organisational-analysis/mandatory-assignments/busm1094-assignment-3/5468873/view?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
https://www.studocu.com/en/course/rmit/organisational-analysis/3221964?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
RMIT University
School of Management
BUSM1094 – Organisational Analysis
Assignment 3 Submission
Problem Solving Case Study and Proposal Report
Lecturer:
Dr. Keith Toh
Tutor:
Dr. Peter Chomley
Student Name:
Anonymous
Tutorial Session:
Friday 14:30 – 16:30
Submission Due Date:
07:00PM, 7th of June 2019
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
1 | P a g e
Contents
1 Abstract: ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………… 2
2 Introduction: ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….. 2
2.1 Problem statement: ……………………………………………………………………………………………………… 2
2.1.1 Social isolation of the bank: ……………………………………………………………………………….. 2
3 Methodology ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….. 2
3.1 The Neohumanist perspective …………………………………………………………………………………… 3
3.2 The radical structuralist ……………………………………………………………………………………………. 3
3.3 The functionalist perspective …………………………………………………………………………………….. 3
4 Literature review …………………………………………………………………………………………………………….. 3
4.1 Corporate Social responsibility: …………………………………………………………………………………. 3
4.2 Criticism of Corporate social responsibility …………………………………………………………………. 4
4.3 Consumer perception on corporate social donations …………………………………………………… 4
4.4 Ethical framework for corporate social marketing ……………………………………………………….. 4
5 Risk and Recommendations ……………………………………………………………………………………………… 5
5.1 Risk ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………… 5
5.2 Recommendations …………………………………………………………………………………………………… 5
6 Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………… 5
7. Appendix ……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….. 6
7.1 Critical analysis ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… 6
7.1.1 Corporate Social responsibility model …………………………………………………………………. 6
7.1.2 The criticism of corporate social responsibility …………………………………………………….. 6
7.1.3 The consumer perception on social donations ……………………………………………………… 6
7.1.4 Ethical Framework ……………………………………………………………………………………………. 7
8. References: ……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………. 7
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
2 | P a g e
1 Abstract:
The aim of this report is to analyse the impact on the perception of the bank with the recent issues
faced with the banks misconduct. Through the analysis of concepts relating to corporate social
responsibility and organisational perception this paper hopes to analyse the banks new campaign to
improve brand image. Using three of the four paradigms this paper hopes to clarify and analyse the
different perceptions of the stakeholders of this campaign.
2 Introduction:
Corporate social responsibility was defined by Keith Davis as “decisions and actions taken for
reasons at least partially beyond the firms economic or technical interest. (Carroll 1991)” This
concept shows that a company has responsibilities beyond being a profitable brand. In the
contemporary business environment companies are often held accountable for their actions by
government, activist and media. This increased awareness brought by these entities has made the
perception of corporate social responsibility (CSR) a very important matter for competitiveness of an
organisation. When a corporation has been caught breaching CSR, it can cause a corporation to be
isolated from its stakeholders.
2.1 Problem statement:
The following issue is of a bank that breached corporate social responsibility due to the pursuing of
economic interest. This bank has had its reputation tarnished due to a variety of scandals which
arose of poor conduct involving many parts of the company. The Bank has been caught charging
deceased customers, withholding payments and breaching anti money laundering laws. To reinvent
their image, the bank has decided to run a campaign in which they would promote the current social
movement known as the #MeToo movement. Through the supporting of non-for-profit
organisations that prevent violence against women the bank hopes to show their commitment to
the movement and hence improve their brand perception. Through the running of this campaign the
bank risk further impeding their progress as it could potentially backfire on them as it the public may
not receive it as well.
Social isolation of the bank:
This campaign could have the potential to backfire as it may not be received well by certain
stakeholders of the bank. This could run the risk of the bank further isolating themselves instead of
improving the solidarity between themselves and their target audience.
3 Methodology
This report will use two different ontological positions in order to study the issue of the perception
of corporate social responsibility. These two ontological perceptions are the Neohumanist and
radical structuralist paradigms found in the paper the Four paradigms of information systems
(Hirschheim & Klein 1989). Through the use of these two paradigms this report will study the issues
of CSR using two different perceptions.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
3 | P a g e
3.1 The Neohumanist perspective
The Neohumanist perspective focuses on how individual understand each other and rationalise with
the social world. It uses a subjective viewpoint to improve understanding of an issue where it takes
the perception and interpretations of individuals based on their cultural values and experiences. The
neo humanist perspectives studies the conflicts and barriers which restrict human understanding
tries to emancipate the supressed ideas and interest. This report will use the Neohumanist
perspective when studying the various interpretations of corporate social responsibility through the
studying of literature critical of the issue. In addition, through the literature review on the
perceptions of organisational giving this report will be able to provide an understanding to the client
on the negative perceptions the organisation may face.
3.2 The radical structuralist
The radical structuralist perception is a view of conflict between two players in society. This conflict
is traditionally seen to be between labour and the corporation. This is often seen as a battle
between the different social classes. The radical structuralist acts as a partisan between labour and
management.
This report will study the literature using a radical structuralist perspective. This is as the main issue
between the bank and its stakeholders. Through the radical structuralist paradigm is bank is able to
see the perceptions of the labour partisan and the potential backlash of their campaign.
3.3 The functionalist perspective
The functionalist perspective looks at how different components of social systems interact with each
other. The main goal of the functionalist perspective is to explain how these individual elements
interact. The functionalist system often utilises many models to help with this cause.
This report will briefly utilise a functionalist diagram to help the client understand corporate social
responsibility and its many components.
4 Literature review
4.1 Corporate Social responsibility:
Corporate social responsibility is seen as an obligation of the company which include factors outside
their economic and technical gains. In previous generations corporate social responsibility was
viewed solely in economic terms. This meant companies mainly focused on shareholder money
return and fiscal responsibility. There is a new perception on corporate social responsibility with four
components which include (Economic, Legal, Social and Philanthropic). This can been seen by the
hierarchical pyramid (Fig.1) developed by (Carroll 1991) . This pyramid depicts the different levels of
CSR within an organisation. This shows that’s economic is still the main goal of a corporation as it is
still important that a corporation achieves this to stay in operation. In order to achieve corporate
responsibility companies are said to have to achieve the triple bottom line (Carroll 1991). This means
companies have to maintain Economic, Legal and Social components of CSR. The Philanthropic
component is seen as a bonus for a company and can be used to boost brand image (Carroll 1991).
Companies have been criticised in failing to maintain the triple bottom line as they still mainly focus
on the shareholder and ignore the wider stakeholders which are impacted by the organisation’s
operations. When companies have poor social responsibility management this can have large
negative impacts to the organisation. These impacts can ruin the reputation of the organisation
which can have negative financial impacts to the corporation.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
4 | P a g e
4.2 Criticism of Corporate social responsibility
Corporate social responsibility is criticised as it can be used as a scape goat or a buzz word by
organisations as excuses for deceptive behaviour (Carson 2003). This can be seen as Enron increased
their stock prices through creative accounting which was said by the company to be a method to
please shareholders of the organisation. Executives of these companies are said to use this as an
excuse to commit fraudulent behaviour and to deceive the public (Carson 2003). This false initiative
is an act of self interest which is used to ignore the moral obligations of the stakeholders. This
deception through corporate social responsibility can be further seen in companies using corporate
social responsibility initiatives to manage impressions of their corporations other than actually care
about the issue (Coelho, McClure & Spry 2003). Companies are said to use the façade of corporate
social responsibility to highlight the positive outcomes of a corporation and to mask the negative
actions that the corporation does (Coelho, McClure & Spry 2003). This can be use by companies to
draw attention away from the negative.
4.3 Consumer perception on corporate social donations
Normally the perception of philanthropic corporate social responsibility initiatives by companies are
viewed in a positive light. This is often inferred to be altruistic in nature. This can change however for
companies which have poor reputations (Dean 2003). When these companies make philanthropic
contributions, their actions are viewed to be self-interested in nature. According to an attribution
theory consumers often make inferences in order to make sense of their environment. This
characteristic can often backfire on companies with bad publicity (Bae & Cameron 2006). When
these companies make philanthropic efforts it is often viewed to have poor motives and is often
viewed as a knee jerk response by the company (Bae & Cameron 2006).
4.4 Ethical framework for corporate social marketing
Corporate social marketing can be viewed positively and is a good way for companies to show their
CSR. This can also be negative as companies which openly advertise their corporate social initiatives
can be viewed as a having self-interested and ulterior motives (Bae & Cameron 2006). The ethical
framework suggest that corporations do not publicly tout or campaign their social initiatives and let
others talk about them instead. By applying deontological ethics, it is said that an action can only be
virtuous if it is performed without alter motives (van de Ven 2008). One company which applied this
framework was TNT. Which in their corporate social initiative used the policy that silence speaks
louder than words. In their partnership with the united nations world food program. TNT stayed
away from any external marketing or communications. This was used by TNT as a strategic goal to
utilise free publicity to spread the word of the corporation’s actions. This was a successful campaign
as TNT received press exposure and they improved their brand perception according to an
independent corporation ranking system. This perception is paradoxical and wouldn’t make sense to
an organisation which is trying to improve their brand image through a campaign. This would be a
waste of money as corporations would have no guarantee of reaping the rewards. This report
suggest companies should instead focus on campaigns which build a corporate brand. This would
mean companies would have to implement a certain social cause into the brand identity instead of a
one off campaign (van de Ven 2008). This would show the company to be more dedicated and
authentic when it comes to that cause. In order to assist them companies should avoid using
marketing communication instruments to communicate this to the external world. The firm should
restrict it to their social and environmental reporting on their website which would illicit a more
positive response.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
5 | P a g e
5 Risk and Recommendations
5.1 Risk
As the bank has made mistakes in maintaining its corporate social responsibility by not addressing
the social and legal aspects of CSR. The use of a philanthropic donation would most likely be viewed
favourably by the public. This donation in the light of bad press for the bank may arouse suspicion on
the motives of the bank when making this donation. This could be viewed by certain stakeholders as
an attempt by the bank to draw negative attention away from their mishaps through a public
donation. Some may also discount the goodwill of the banks actions when making this donation as it
may be viewed to have ulterior motives to donate after bad press.
5.2 Recommendations
The Bank can continue with this campaign and expect a good response from the general public. This
campaign will however not please everyone and the bank would have to accept this fact when
running this campaign. Another approach that does have the potential to have greater benefits is
through the utilisation of a campaign that appears more ethical and with less ulterior motive as
suggested by (van de Ven 2008). Through this campaign the bank would have to contribute to this
cause in a less overt manner. This may run against the whole initial idea of the campaign to improve
the banks image from marketing of this philanthropic act. This would make the bank appear less
insincere and make the campaign seem more genuine. For this approach to work the bank would
have to rely on positive press coverage of this campaign to reap the rewards.
6 Conclusion
With the issue of the social perception of the bank and the campaign to improve it we can see it is
quite a complex scenario. With the different perceptions on Corporations and their responsibilities it
was difficult for the bank to please everyone with the campaign. Through the study of the literature
it is evident that there is perceptions held by the public which mirror the radical structuralist
perspective. The Bank was seen in conflict with certain stakeholders and the campaign could be an
attempt by the bank to deceive the said stakeholders. This campaign could backfire on the bank as it
could further isolate the bank from its target audience due to these negative perceptions held.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
6 | P a g e
7. Appendix
7.1 Critical analysis
7.1.1 Corporate Social responsibility model
Figure 1: Corporate social responsibility pyramid
The corporate social responsibility model uses a functional framework to integrate the knowledge of
corporate social responsibility. This shows how the individual elements of corporate social
responsibility interact and are co dependent to form the perception of corporate social responsibility
in an organisation. Through the utilisation of this model the client can better understand the
different components of CSR and its hierarchical nature.
7.1.2 The criticism of corporate social responsibility
Corporate social responsibility initiatives are perceived by certain individuals as tools that can be
used by organisations to gain power over certain stakeholders and to deceive them. This is reflective
of the radical structuralist paradigm which discuss the conflict between the labour and management.
Through the using of the perspective of a labour partisan companies can be seen to use these
deceptions to gain economic power over the stakeholders. Through the use of impression
management companies and using CSR as an excuse companies can deceive the stakeholders and
gain power over them.
7.1.3 The consumer perception on social donations
Through the analysis of the literature it is also evident that companies can use social donations to
maintain their corporate façade. This can be linked back to the radical structuralist paradigm which
addresses the conflict between corporations and stakeholders. Through the use of philanthropic
means the organisations can be seen to mislead the stakeholders through this act.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
https://www.studocu.com/en?utm_campaign=shared-document&utm_source=studocu-document&utm_medium=social_sharing&utm_content=busm1094-assignment-3
7 | P a g e
7.1.4 Ethical Framework
This framework suggests a less overt method for a corporation to change its image. Through this
method the company will seem less deceptive to stakeholders. Through the use of more covert
measures and less indirect advertising methods companies can be perceived to be more genuine
and less immoral.
8. References:
Bae, J & Cameron, GT 2006, ‘Conditioning effect of prior reputation on perception of corporate
giving’, Public Relations Review, vol. 32, no. 2, pp. 144-150.
Carroll, AB 1991, ‘The pyramid of corporate social responsibility: Toward the moral management of
organizational stakeholders’, Business horizons, vol. 34, no. 4, pp. 39-48.
Carson, TL 2003, ‘Self–Interest and Business Ethics: Some Lessons of the Recent Corporate Scandals’,
Journal of Business Ethics, vol. 43, no. 4, pp. 389-394.
Coelho, PRP, McClure, JE & Spry, JA 2003, ‘The Social Responsibility of Corporate Management: A
Classical Critique’, American Journal of Business, vol. 18, no. 1, pp. 15-24.
Dean, DH 2003, ‘CONSUMER PERCEPTION OF CORPORATE DONATIONS Effects of Company
Reputation for Social Responsibility and Type of Donation’, Journal of Advertising, vol. 32, no. 4, pp.
91-102.
Hirschheim, R & Klein, HK 1989, ‘Four paradigms of information systems development’, Commun.
ACM, vol. 32, no. 10, pp. 1199-1216.
van de Ven, B 2008, ‘An Ethical Framework for the Marketing of Corporate Social Responsibility’,
Journal of Business Ethics, vol. 82, no. 2, pp. 339-352.
Downloaded by YUANRONG AU (auyuanrong123@gmail.com)
lOMoARcPSD|2369160
Tableof Contents
1
.
Introduction 4
1.1Problem Statement 4
2. Methodology 5
2.1 Neo-humanist perspective 5
2.2 Radical Structuralism 6
3.Risk Management framework 7
8
4.1. Lack of Awareness 8
4.2. Not learning from mistakes 8
4.3. Poor performance from Management and employees 9
10
4.5 The rising of social risk 10
5.Functional Design 11
5.1Current Data Model 11
5.2Modified data Model 12
13
6.1 Ethical Leadership 13
6.2 Corporate social responsibility 14
14
16
8Appendix 17
17
Risk Management framework 17
4.Problem Analysis (Risk management in corporation) 18
4.1. Lack of Awareness 18
4.2. Not learning from mistakes 18
4.3. Poor performance from Management and employees 19
4.4. Understanding traditional risk 20
4.5 The rising of social risk 20
Solution of the proposal: Incorporation of ethical leadership ,corporate social responsibility and risk Matrix tool 20
6.1 Ethical Leadership 21
6.2 Corporate social responsibility 21
6.3 Using Risk Matrix 22
8.2Interview Questions 24
26
This report is written by an external consultant who is tasked by the organizations to resolve the negative image by enhancing its culture of ethical leadership, accountability towards the leader’s followers and to appraise the organizations in terms of how environment responsibilities are being managed based on the two paradigms. Often, communication breakdown, shifting of blame when situations goes wrong and poor working culture are the root cause of the organization failure system.
Next, the management system is curate to resolve the organization internal and external conflict. Therefore, the system is designed to enhance on ethical leadership and environment accountability within the organization. The report will be further developed based on the present situation, implementation, and challenges of the risk management thesis.
Currently, there is an accusation of the organizations which do not have the intention to make a formal explanation in terms of misusing the charity events as a platform to gain a market share. Consequently, the organizations wind down the social media platform to prevent their external stakeholders ,mainly customers and reporters from further questioning on issues such as sudden resignation rate from employees, being unethical by misusing the charity as a platform to achieve the desired goals the management has set previously.
Two paradigms will be incorporated through the operations based on the internal conflict being faced by the internal stake holders ,mainly employees in an organization. The Neo-humanist and radical approach will be integrated to lower the resistance to changes when creating to apply the risk management concept. To address the employees issues , flooded with negative remarks about the organization unethical behaviors, I have propose Risk management System framework that was created based on both quantitative and qualitative research thesis . Quantitively research is when the usage of literature articles and data remains crucial because it will definitely offer the appropriate justifications to our current approaches. The main objective of qualitative research is to secure perspective and thought from individuals in regards to the marketing product campaign.
The Neo-humanist perspective is concentrating on how a human understand one another and rationalize to the social environments. Furthermore, subjective opinions are involved to enhance understanding of a problem where it leads the perception and interpretation based on their culture values and experiences (Hirschheim& Klein 1989).Next, the Neo- humanist perspective examines the conflict and barriers which restrict human understanding try to emaciate the suppressed ideas and interest. For example, there is an internal dispute being involved when employees are unable to voice out their concerns which results in further isolations and have personal reservation in this charity campaign.
Consequently, the employees have to suffer in silence because if they provide the feedback to the higher management in the current organization proposal, the affected employees will lose their job. Hence, there is a serious consideration and reservations from employees despite the management team request their employees to provide constructive feedback.
According to (Hirschheim & Klein 1989) thesis concept, radical structuralism perspective is concentrating on the rising belief in conscience and conscious through organizational political act, adaption of tools and techniques in different social classes. Moreover, this dispute has traditionally being observed between employees and the organization which appear as a war in different social classes. Similarly, the radical structuralism concept will act as partisan between labour and higher management team.
Next, the report will examine the literature articles by applying the Radical structuralism concept. For example, there is an issue between the organization and the stakeholders mainly employees and netizens such as the corporation has shown unethical behavior by being a hypocrite in their intentions in terms of misusing the charity events as a platform to conduct illegal activities. When there is a social media backlash in terms of negative feedback in bigger corporation, customers will not purchase the products no matter how useful the products which able to assist the consumers daily life .
Risk management framework is the structured procedure of identifying predictable danger, analysis and reacts to projects risk ( Woon & Falizah 2010) ;(Dr Regan 2003) .For example, the marketing team in a corporation would like to have a brand exposure in their products by reserving certain amount of funds to be donated to repeatable charity organizations. Next, project risk analysis has been evolving by the association of project manager and Baldry examined the thesis of risk management applied in managing public sector capital projects (Baldry 1998). In addition, the advantages and applications of executing risk management principles, tools with other methods and examine the relationship between project planning and project success story (Young & Smith 2009).
Industry expert in an organization should evaluate accordingly on how to minimize the risk being occurred which leads to handling risk in efficient way(Massingham 2009). For example, Zoysa and Russel identified three key factors are risk identifications, risk qualification and risk response duration when knowledge could be use as a platform to influence the decision makers when they about to make an important decision in an organization (Massingham 2009).
Next, researchers conduct an investigation on how to improve the development of the risk knowledge management. For example, by transferring knowledge to other individual who makes the decisions which enhance the access of knowledge and information being required.
4.Problem Analysis (Risk management in corporation)
It is imperative to have a risk management concept for the corporation in order to enable smoother operation by reacting to the present potential threat which organization has been facing accordingly.
Currently, the present corporation has undertaking with negative comments posted in the social media platform due to unethical behavior in several parts of the organization. Often, it remains cumbersome for the organization to deal with negative feedback caused by managers, higher management personnel and employees that will lead to poor reputation.
Next, an intense understanding of the vital connection on how an organization should handle to negative feedback by creating chances for leaders to restore its reputation (Sim 2009). Furthermore, reputation plays an important factor which remains the paramount and valuable because it gives confidence to its consumers. Hence, it encourages the customers to purchase the products offered by the corporation with good reputation.
Ultimately, the corporation reputation remains as a critical asset because not only have to achieve the shareholder satisfactions but also its employees and customers as well. If there is a failure to establish good relations with customers, chances that customers being loyal to that particular organization will be slim and instead will switch to the other competitor to purchase the products (Elsbach & Sutton 1992).
Firstly, mistakes could bring unpleasant results. Hence, For example, the management team remains insensitive towards employee’s perspective by not listening to their concerns and wellbeing considered as a fatal mistake.
In order for the company to improvise learning techniques , it must acknowledge and stand out from the mistakes being made(Weinzimmer & Esken 2017) which provides as a platform of effective chances for organizational learning because these occurrence acts a manifesto for organizational personal to ruin the present “ Working culture “ and clarify the past mistakes with innovative plan framework (Sitkin 1992). In fact, corporation should often seek to capitalize on the pass success activities and analyze how the management team can make the best out of mistakes by enhancing the technique which the corporations are currently using(Sitkin 1992).
Corporation often faces challenges in discovering latest technique on measuring employee’s performance .Usually, poor organizational performance forces organizations to perform systematic changes towards their structure in order to match the latest environment (Tusman & Romanelli 1985).
When organizations does not adapt immediately when employees performance is poor, the chance of having poor working culture will be higher. By handling poor performance using the right process will definitely enhance the organization performance. If required, interventions are necessary to assist employees and management to enhance their working relationship (Hlengane , & Bayat 2013).
Poor performance has always been an issue that relates to the manager and employees. Furthermore, it brings a serious attention for senior managers to monitor the key performance index (KPI) on how should the organization being managed effectively based on a regular basis. In contrast, poor performance has not been address carefully which remains as an personal issue. In other words, corporation that usually struggling to make a conversion and adapt into learning organization would eventually failed in the long term
(Mafini & Pooe 2013).
4.4. Understanding traditional risk
Economic risk is the most common which involves the business of being in business which raise concerns in terms of maintaining profit margin, sustaining economic growth and defend shareholders interest(Kytle & Gerard Ruggie, 2005) .As for the political risk , it includes managing public perception of corporation internationally . For example, an American company operates overseas is in midst of unpopular dispute such as mismanagement of legal environment, poor government relations and geo politics. (Kytle & Gerard Ruggie, 2005)
Based on the corporation perspective, social risks has been involved when an authorize stakeholder takes up an social issues and applies pressures on a corporation in terms of exploiting a vulnerability in the earning drive such as reputation in order for the company to amend their policies or changes in the marketplace(Kytle & Gerard Ruggie, 2005) .For example, higher management in an organization decided to use underhand methods just to achieve higher earnings in the case of the charity event even though they knew that it is wrong for them to misuse charity as a platform to earn more money .
Based on the research literature articles finding for risk management system, the organizations are required to do a traditional tree technique which reveals the weakness of the RAN current approach towards risk management (Massingham, 2009).
6. Solution of the proposal: Incorporation of ethical leadership ,corporate social responsibility and risk Matrix tool
To make sure all employees understand their designation, a genuine approach to ethical leadership within the corporation and organization corporal social responsibilities is critical. Next, the approach below will be integrated to promote corporate social responsibility to employees as well as higher management level.
Schein (2010) explained the maturity between organizational culture and leadership. As stated by (Samdani & Yameen2017) leaders are responsible for any unethical contentious .Furthermore, leaders are obliged to create a proper ethical structure and culture internally.
Next, research has presented that uncovering to organizational practices and framework results in high ethical awareness Ritter (2006). (Trevino ,Brown & Wall 2004)demonstrate how the chemistry between formal and informal organization cultural systems could positively affect ethical decision making. If there is disharmony, there will be a cultural failure which affects the overall employee’s morale.
The higher management especially the Chief Executive Officer (CEO) need to ensure that employees understand their job scope and duties towards the external stakeholders mainly clients . Therefore, the corporation top management team should take responsible by cultivations of socially ethical culture. Verbos et al . (2007)implemented practices such as spearhead of true leaders, proper alignment of ethical practices with organizational structure and operations, constant encouragement to practice and cultivate awareness internally.
Lastly, the higher management should consider having a proposal by formulating an social media approach for their internal activities within the organization and clients.
The procedure of conveying the social and environmental impact of the organizations to environmental interest group in society itself is likely known as the practice of corporate social responsibility (CSR) (Gray, Kouhy &Lavers 1995).In addition, CSR involves balancing economies, environmental and social practices of an organization while fulfilling the requirements of different stakeholders mainly internal and external. (Xueming & Bhattacharya 2006)
A socially responsible corporations will willing to accept any responsibility and outcomes of its activities on the environment and prepared to show accountability for their actions and decision making process (Kytle & Gerard Ruggie 2005). Stakeholder are the main people to ascertain the existence of an organizations in terms of financial and non financial abilities to achieve the organization’s mission and objectives .
For example, if the corporation want to advertise their products in the charity events, the management should consider donate money to the charity unconditionally which will improve the organization reputation. By having good corporation reputation, it will benefit the underprivileged people who are unable to access the basic needs and retain customer’s loyalty, providing an edge over competitors. Lastly, implementing CSR will increase staff turnover and enhancing customer’s confidence and satisfaction.
6.3 Using Risk Matrix
Risk matrix tools should be implemented in all corporations so that management are able to conduct project risk management activities internally (Landdell 2016). Moreover, there are five levels such as almost impossible , very low, low ,occasional ,high ,very high (Landdell 2016). Lastly,by utilizing the risk matrix allows the management team to identify and analyse the current situation that creates a potential threat to the success of the project in figure 1.
Figure 1:ERM IT Risk assessment tool (Hanna Landdell , 2016)
7. Conclusion
The corportation has a series of dispute be it internal and external that affected them negative towards their stakeholders. Miscommunication, failure and inappropriate communications were the reasons for this downfall.
The implementation of the ethical leadership and corporate social responsibility is deemed to be necessary because it will definitely improve the organization reputation permanently. Although it does not resolve the situation fully, the system ensures a proper structure of information usage and sharing to be practiced.
With the assistance of knowledge management system and risk management framework analysis, it will definitely benefit the corporation permanently. In addition , a couple of measures are suggested to be incorporated into organization culture by strengthen ethical leadership and accountability.
8.1.Literature review
Risk management framework is the structured procedure of identifying predictable danger, analysis and reacts to projects risk ( Woon & Falizah 2010) ;(Dr Regan 2003) .For example, the marketing team in a corporation would like to have a brand exposure in their products by reserving certain amount of funds to be donated to repeatable charity organizations. Next, project risk analysis has been evolving by the association of project manager and Baldry examined the thesis of risk management applied in managing public sector capital projects (Baldry 1998). In addition, the advantages and applications of executing risk management principles, tools with other methods and examine the relationship between project planning and project success story (Young & Smith 2009).
Industry expert in an organization should evaluate accordingly on how to minimize the risk being occurred which leads to handling risk in efficient way(Massingham 2009). For example, Zoysa and Russel identified three key factors are risk identifications, risk qualification and risk response duration when knowledge could be use as a platform to influence the decision makers when they about to make an important decision in an organization (Massingham 2009).
Next, researchers conduct an investigation on how to improve the development of the risk knowledge management. For example, by transferring knowledge to other individual who makes the decisions which enhance the access of knowledge and information being required.
4.Problem Analysis (Risk management in corporation)
It is imperative to have a risk management concept for the corporation in order to enable smoother operation by reacting to the present potential threat which organization has been facing accordingly.
Currently, the present corporation has undertaking with negative comments posted in the social media platform due to unethical behavior in several parts of the organization. Often, it remains cumbersome for the organization to deal with negative feedback caused by managers, higher management personnel and employees that will lead to poor reputation.
Next, an intense understanding of the vital connection on how an organization should handle to negative feedback by creating chances for leaders to restore its reputation (Sim 2009). Furthermore, reputation plays an important factor which remains the paramount and valuable because it gives confidence to its consumers. Hence, it encourages the customers to purchase the products offered by the corporation with good reputation.
Ultimately, the corporation reputation remains as a critical asset because not only have to achieve the shareholder satisfactions but also its employees and customers as well. If there is a failure to establish good relations with customers, chances that customers being loyal to that particular organization will be slim and instead will switch to the other competitor to purchase the products (Elsbach & Sutton 1992).
4.2. Not learning from mistakes
Firstly, mistakes could bring unpleasant results. Hence, For example, the management team remains insensitive towards employee’s perspective by not listening to their concerns and wellbeing considered as a fatal mistake.
In order for the company to improvise learning techniques , it must acknowledge and stand out from the mistakes being made(Weinzimmer & Esken 2017) which provides as a platform of effective chances for organizational learning because these occurrence acts a manifesto for organizational personal to ruin the present “ Working culture “ and clarify the past mistakes with innovative plan framework (Sitkin 1992). In fact, corporation should often seek to capitalize on the pass success activities and analyze how the management team can make the best out of mistakes by enhancing the technique which the corporations are currently using(Sitkin 1992)..
4.3. Poor performance from Management and employees
Corporation often faces challenges in discovering latest technique on measuring employee’s performance .Usually, poor organizational performance forces organizations to perform systematic changes towards their structure in order to match the latest environment.
When organizations does not adapt immediately when employees performance is poor, the chance of having poor working culture will be higher. By handling poor performance using the right process will definitely enhance the organization performance. If required, interventions are necessary to assist employees and management to enhance their working relationship.
Poor performance has always been an issue that relates to the manager and employees. Furthermore, it brings a serious attention for senior managers to monitor the key performance index (KPI) on how should the organization being managed effectively based on a regular basis. In contrast, poor performance has not been address carefully which remains as an personal issue. In other words, corporation that usually struggling to make a conversion and adapt into learning organization would eventually failed in the long term
4.4. Understanding traditional risk
Economic risk is the most common which involves the business of being in business which raise concerns in terms of maintaining profit margin, sustaining economic growth and defend shareholders interest .As for the political risk , it includes managing public perception of corporation internationally . For example, an American company operates overseas is in midst of unpopular dispute such as mismanagement of legal environment, poor government relations and geo politics.
Based on the corporation perspective, social risks has been involved when an authorize stakeholder takes up an social issues and applies pressures on a corporation in terms of exploiting a vulnerability in the earning drive such as reputation in order for the company to amend their policies or changes in the marketplace .For example, higher management in an organization decided to use underhand methods just to achieve higher earning in the case of the charity event even though they knew that it is wrong for them to misuse charity as a platform to earn more money .
To make sure all employees understand their designation, a genuine approach to ethical leadership within the corporation and organization corporal social responsibilities is critical. Next, the approach below will be integrated to promote corporate social responsibility to employees as well as higher management level.
6.1 Ethical Leadership
Schein (2010) explained the maturity between organizational culture and leadership. As stated by (Samdani & Yameen2017) leaders are responsible for any unethical contentious .Furthermore, leaders are obliged to create a proper ethical structure and culture internally.
Next, research has presented that uncovering to organizational practices and framework results in high ethical awareness Ritter (2006). (Trevino ,Brown & Wall 2004)demonstrate how the chemistry between formal and informal organization cultural systems could positively affect ethical decision making. If there is disharmony, there will be a cultural failure which affects the overall employee’s morale.
The higher management especially the Chief Executive Officer (CEO) need to ensure that employees understand their job scope and duties towards the external stakeholders mainly clients . Therefore, the corporation top management team should take responsible by cultivations of socially ethical culture. Verbos et al . (2007)implemented practices such as spearhead of true leaders, proper alignment of ethical practices with organizational structure and operations, constant encouragement to practice and cultivate awareness internally.
Lastly, the higher management should consider having a proposal by formulating an social media approach for their internal activities within the organization and clients.
6.2 Corporate social responsibility
The procedure of conveying the social and environmental impact of the organizations to environmental interest group in society itself is likely known as the practice of corporate social responsibility (CSR) (Gray, Kouhy &Lavers 1995).In addition,CSR involves balancing economies, environmental and social practices of an organization while fulfilling the requirements of different stakeholders mainly internal and external. (Xueming & Bhattacharya 2006)
A socially responsible corporations will willing to accept any responsibility and outcomes of its activities on the environment and prepared to show accountability for their actions and decision making process (Kytle & Gerard Ruggie 2005). Stakeholder are the main people to ascertain the existence of an organizations in terms of financial and non financial abilities to achieve the organization’s mission and objectives .
For example, if the corporation want to advertise their products in the charity events, the management should consider donate money to the charity unconditionally which will improve the organization reputation. By having good corporation reputation, it will benefit the underprivileged people who are unable to access the basic needs and retain customer’s loyalty, providing an edge over competitors. Lastly, implementing CSR will increase staff turnover and enhancing customer’s confidence and satisfaction.
6.3 Using Risk Matrix
Risk matrix tools should be implemented in all corporations so that management are able to conduct project risk management activities internally . Moreover, there are five levels such as almost impossible , very low, low ,occasional ,high ,very high (Hanna Landdell , 2016). Lastly,by utilizing the risk matrix allows the management team to identify and analyse the current situation that creates a potential threat to the success of the project in figure 1.
Figure 1:ERM IT Risk assessment tool (Hanna Landdell , 2016)
1)Do you feel your perspective being heard by the management team in an organization?
Neohumanism: Most of the employees thinks that the higher management does not listen to them given that they are willing to provide their genuine feed back to enhance the organizations structure.
Radical Structuralism : different tools can work out in different situation and background .Passionate and diligent employee are the key factor to improve the company operations by providing constructive feedback . However, the management team will not have the same perspective as the employees.
2) Does your organization encourage employees to provide feedback?
Neohumanism: Most of the decision has been finalized by the management without consulting the employees feedback .
Radical structurism : All the decisions have been consulted by the employees before making any decision making process .
3) Do you feel valued, appreciated, heard and respected by company?
Neohumanism:No , the employees does not feel appreciated since the management does not listen to their feedback and concern
Radical structurism: Management team took some time by conducting a staff meeting knowing what happening on the ground .
4) Is implementing a good corporate social responsibility (CSR) process necessary(Gray, Kouhy &Lavers 1995)?
Neohumanism:CSR thesis might not applies to all company because many of the management team w ill not comply with that .
Radical structurism:Some of the management team will comply with CSR so that organization receive good reputation and gain customers confidence .
5)Does leading figures need to have traits such as ethical leadership permanently Ritter (2006).?
Neohumanist: Expect their employees to comply with their instructions with no question asked .
Radical stucturism : Will listen to their employees by allowing them to voice their concerns before making any decisions.
6) Does Risk Matrix tools are able to improve the efficiency in terms of making critical decisions (Landdell , 2016).?
Neohumanist : some of the employees especially elderly find it not useful due to technology advancement .
Radical structurism : Passionate employees will conduct risk matrix tools to make any important analysis and decisions.
.
8.3References
Beth ,K & John ,G R, 2005. Corporate social Responsibilty as risk management. [Online]
Available at: https://www.hks.harvard.edu/sites/default/files/centers/mrcbg/programs/cri/files/workingpaper_10_kytle_ruggie
[Accessed 4 October 2019].
Coelho, PRP, McClure,JE & spry,JA , 2003 . The social responsibility of corporate Management: A classical Critique. American Journal of Business , 18(1), pp. 15-24.
David ,B, 1998. The evaluation of risk management in public sector capital projects. International Journal of Project Management, 16(1), pp. 35-41.
Dr Sean T,Regan , 2003. Risk management Implementation and analysis. [Online]
Available at: https://search.proquest.com/openview/533305e2fba438049916bb02e15b960a/1?pq-origsite=gscholar&cbl=27161
[Accessed 4 October 2019].
Elsbach ,K & Sutton , R, 1992. Acquiring Organizational Legitimacy through illegitimate actions: A marriage of instutional and improession management theories. Academy of Management Journal, 35(4), pp. 699-738.
Fong ,W,L& Falizah A, S , 2010. Enterprise Risk Management Framework and The Empirical Determinants of Its Implementation. [Online]
Available at: https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Fong_Woon_Lai/publication/278002258_Enterprise_Risk_Management_Framework_and_The_Empirical_Determinants_of_Its_Implementation/links/55f0dce808ae0af8ee1d35f0/Enterprise-Risk-Management-Framework-and-The-Empirical-Determ
[Accessed 4 October 2019].
Gray,R, Kouhy,R &Lavers,S, 1995. Corporate Social and environmental reporting : A review of the literature and a longitudinal study of UK disclosure’. Accounting, Auditing &Accountability Journal, 8(2), pp. 47-77.
Hanna, L , 2016. The risk Matrix as a tool of analysis. [Online]
Available at: https://www.diva-portal.org/smash/get/diva2:944825/FULLTEXT01
[Accessed 4 October 2019].
Hirschheim, R& Klein , HK , 1989. Four Paradigms of information system development Commun.. ACM, 32(10), pp. 1199-1216.
Hlengane , N & Bayat , M, 2013. Poor employees work performance -A case study – Cambridge police station. Kuwait chapter of the Arabian Journal of Business and management Review, 2(12), pp. 80-92.
Leslie, A, 2006. Leading a New Generation:New Born and nursing review. Elsevier, 6(1), pp. 7-9.
Mafini C& Pooe,D, 2013. The relationship between employee satisfaction and organisational performance. Evidence from a South African government department , Journal of industrial Psychological , 39(1), pp. 1-9.
Maryanne ,G 2012. Speaking up ,being heard:Register Nurse Perception of workplace communication. Californa State University Fullerton , 20(3), pp. 361-371.
Palaiologos, A., Papazekos, P. and Panayotopoulou, L., 2011. “Organizational justice and employee satisfaction in performance appraisal”. Journal of European Industrial Training, 35(8), pp. 826-840.
Peter,M 2009. Knowledge Risk management a framework. University of Wollogong , Australia , 14(3), pp. 464-485.
Ritter , B , 2006. ‘ Can Business Ethics be Trained? A study of the Ethical Decision-Making Process in Business Students’,. Journal of Business Ethics , 68(2), pp. 153-164.
Roger, M & Donald ,L 2001. Understanding and managing risks in large engineering projects. Elsevier, 19(8), pp. 437-443.
Samdani, H & Yameen, A, 2017. An engagement story:engaging employees through ethical leadership’. The Business & Management review, 8(4), pp. 126-149.
Schein ,EH, 2010. Organizational Culture and Leadership. John Wiley& Son, Volume 2.
Sim , R, 2009. Towards a better Understanding of organizational efforts to rebuild reputation Following an ethical scandals. Journal of business Ethics, 90(4), pp. 453-472.
Sitkin , SB , 1992. ‘Learning through failure : The strategy of Small Losses’ ,. Research in Organizational Behavior, Volume 14, pp. 231-266.
Trevino, LK,Brown , ME & Wall, SJ, 2004. Managing to be Ethical : ‘Debunking Five Business Ethics Myths’. The academy of Management Executive (1993-2005), 18(2), pp. 69-83.
Tusman ,ML & Romanelli, E , 1985. Organizational evolution: A metamorphosis model of convergence and reorientation. Research in organizational Behavior , Volume 7, pp. 171-222.
Verbos, A , Gerard, J, Forshey ,P, Harding,C& Miller,J, 2007. The positive Ethical organization : ‘Enacting a living code of ethics and ethical organizational Identity ‘. Journal of Business Ethics, 76(1), pp. 17-33.
Weinzimmer ,LG & Esken,CA, 2017. Learning from mistakes: How mistake tolerance positively Affects organizational Learning and performance. The Journal of applied behavioral science, 53(3), pp. 322-348.
Xueming , L & Bhattacharya ,C,B, 2006. Corporate social responsibilty ,Customer satisfaction and market Value. Sage Publication, 70(4), pp. 1-18.
Young H, K & Brian ,M, S, 2009. Managing risks in mega defense acquisition projects: Performance, policy, and opportunities. International Journal of Project Management , 27(8), pp. 812-820.
28
Organisational Analysis
Exploring epistemologies of ignorance
‹#›
“The only thing more valuable than the illusion of perfect knowledge is the ability to profess perfect ignorance.”
(Davies & McGoey,
2
012: 81)
RMIT University
2
‹#›
2
Lecture Aims
Previously: epistemology
→ understanding what counts as knowledge, being able to deconstruct knowledge claims
→ responsible decision-making.
Today: ignorance
→ Understanding ignorance in relation to knowledge
→ Deconstructing ignorance
→ Connections to organisational behaviour
→ Connections to Organisational Analysis learning outcomes
→ A challenge to you, in your future careers
RMIT University
3
‹#›
3
Epistemology: reminder
“The nature of knowledge, its possibility, scope and general basis.”
Deals with questions such as, How do we know that something is true, and trustworthy, rather than mere opinion or belief? How can we be certain? On what basis can we consider our beliefs to be justified?
RMIT University
4
(Hamlyn, 1995: 242, cited in Crotty,1998: 8)
‹#›
4
Ignorance: definitions
“The state or fact being ignorant; lack of knowledge, learning or information.” (Macquarie Dictionary, 2002)
‘Agnotology’: “The cultural reproduction and transmission of ignorance.” (McGoey, 2012: 4, referencing Proctor)
“Non-knowledge.” (McGoey, 2012: 3)
RMIT University
5
‹#›
5
Ignorance: conceptions
Some conceptions (Kassar, 2018):
“Lack of knowledge / true belief”
“Actively upheld false outlooks” (e.g. Charles Mills, José Medina)
“Bad epistemic practice” (e.g. Alcoff, 2007)
RMIT University
6
‹#›
6
Ignorance v knowledge?
“Ignorance and knowledge are often thought of as opposite phenomena.” (McGoey, 2012: 553)
Knowledge: “a source of power”. Ignorance: “a barrier to consolidating authority in political and corporate arenas.” (McGoey, 2012: 553)
RMIT University
7
‹#›
7
Yet …
“Ignorance is like Kansas, a great place to be from.”
(Proctor, 2008)
RMIT University
8
‹#›
8
Three cases
RMIT University
9
“Doubt is our product”
‹#›
Images from Unsplashed
9
Ignorance
“A productive force in and itself … the twin and not the opposite of knowledge.” (McGoey, 2012: 3)
Ignorance can be strategic. (McGoey, 2012)
Ignorance can be a resource that helps one retain privilege & power. (McGoey, 2012)
Ignorance can be manufactured for profit. (Proctor, 2008)
Ignorance can be motivated. (Smith, 2008)
Ignorance can suppress epistemological diversity. (DeSousa Santas, 2009)
RMIT University
10
‹#›
10
RMIT University
Ignorance that advances and privileges: Another epistemic vice?
“Epistemic malevolence”: “Wilful hiding of the truth, denying people access to the truth; “spread of ignorance and confusion”
“Epistemic insouciance” (indifference): Disregarding the importance of truth, coherence, honesty, and reasoning. E.g. social media platforms
“Epistemic hubris” (unfounded over-confidence): Unfounded arrogance in the validity of one’s own beliefs
“Epistemic injustice”: Dismissing people’s experiential knowledge and lived experience (e.g. not taking seriously your employees’ experiences and knowledge)
Baird & Calvard, 2019
‹#›
11
Ignorance at the global level
A fundamental property of (some) political philosophies?
E.g. Liberalism? E.g. Neo-liberalism? (Mills, 2015)
E.g. “White ignorance” (Mills, 2015; Medina, 2013)
E.g. “Epistemological asymmetry / fascism” (DeSousa Santos, 2009)
RMIT University
12
‹#›
12
Individual level
Individual level
Ecology of ignorance & paradox of embedded agency
RMIT University
13
Individual level
Organisational level
Societal level
Paradox of embedded agency:
“How can actors change institutions if their actions, intentions and rationality are all conditioned by the very institution they wish to change?” (Holm, 1995, cited in Battilana & D’Aunno, 2009: 31)
A question and challenge:
Are you independent variables, or dependent variables?
‹#›
13
RMIT University
Consider your learning outcomes
Your learning outcomes (Lecture 1)
A question and challenge:
Are you independent variables, or dependent variables?
‹#›
14
Ignorance: implications and remedies
Retrain ourselves, ongoingly (Medina, 2013)
Seek to become a “learned ignorant” (DeSousa Santos, 2009: 115)
Respect uncertainty and limitations of knowledge; declare them
Foster diversity of thought (see prior lecture)
RMIT University
15
‹#›
15
References
Davies, W & McGoey, L (2012) Rationalities of ignorance: On financial crisis and the ambivalence of neo-liberal epistemology. Economy and Society, 41(1): 64–83.
DeSousa Santos, B. (2009) A non-Occidentalist West? Learned ignorance and ecology of knowledge. Theory, Culture & Society, 26(7-8): 103–125.
El Kassar, N (2018) What ignorance really is. Examining the foundations of epistemology of ignorance. Social Epistemology, 32(5): 300–310.
McGoey, L (2012) The logic of strategic ignorance. The British Journal of Sociology, 63(3): 553 – 576.
McGoey, L (2012) Strategic unknowns: Towards a sociology of ignorance. Economy and Society, 41(1): 1–16.
Mills, CW (2008) Racial liberalism. PMLA 123(5): 1380–1397.
Mills, CW (2012) Occupy liberalism! Or, ten reasons why liberalism cannot be retrieved for radicalism (and why they’re all wrong). Radical Philosophy Review 15(2): 305–323.
Proctor, RN (Agnotology: A missing term to describe the cultural production of ignorance. In Agnotology: The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance, (Eds. RN Proctor and L Schiebinger). Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.
Smith, MS (2008) Racism and motivated ignorance. The Ardent: Anti-racism & Decolonization Review, 1(1): iii – xiv).
RMIT University
16
‹#›
Environmental Analysis –
The Boundaryless Organisation
Organisational Analysis
‹#›
Aims
Understand the notion of a “boundaryless” organisation and show how this impacts organisational activities and environmental sustainability
Postmodernism: The “boundaryless” organisation
Understand the impetus for carbon accounting and reporting
Understand the process of carbon accounting and reporting
Understand the critiques of carbon accounting and reporting
‹#›
Employment Pathways – Singapore
‹#›
RMIT University
4
Postmodernist Analysis
Meta-theoretical Underpinnings:
Ontology: Organisations as ‘ideas’ created and constrained through conceptualisation/theorisation and materialised through language and discourse
Epistemology: Discovering how organisations are imagined entities where power and social arrangements are reinforced through language (e.g. organisational boundaries)
‹#›
Organisational Efficiency:
The Prevalent Narrative
Efficiency as a prevalent organisational mindset
Financial performance measures (efficiency, profitability, level of debt, etc.) are often the leading criteria to measure organisational effectiveness.
Efficiency: the capacity and ability of an organisation to produce desired results with a minimum expenditure of labour, time, energy, resources and/or money.
Focus = speed and cost
‹#›
5
RMIT University
6
Postmodernism – Conceptualising the “Boundaryless” Organisation
What if we challenge contemporary conceptualisations of organisations?
Reject the hard differentiations, e.g. organisations, hard/soft structures and categorisations
Recognise how we conceptualise organisations is constrained by various complex social and organisational pressures
Our perceptions of organisational boundaries have changed
‹#›
Organisation
Environment (Externality)
Previous Role of Management
Conceptualisation of a real boundary
Why “boundaryless”?
Should you include an off-site, out-sourced data centre in the carbon footprint as a Scope 3 emission?
Scope 1 emission: Direct emissions from owned or controlled sources
Scope 2 emission: Indirect emissions from the generation of purchased energy
Scope 3 emission: All indirect emissions (not included in scope 2)
‹#›
Impact on the Environment
Organisational activities cause emissions of greenhouse gases
Burning gas for heating, or using electricity generated from coal, natural gas, operating a supply chain, manufacturing
The quantity of greenhouse gas emissions from electricity use depends on the efficiency of resources
The quantity of emissions from cars or trucks depends on the efficiency of the logistics, e.g., the amount of time spent idling in traffic
Recycling will reduce the amount of waste sent to landfills, as well as the greenhouse gas emissions that result from disposal of waste
Hence Carbon Accounting
‹#›
Carbon Accounting –
Efficiency and Compliance
Use footprint to maximise efficiency of resources and save costs
Identify cost saving opportunities. Significant sources of greenhouse gases (GHGs) are also associated to resources that cost money (i.e., energy consumption)
Managing resource risk. Identify key raw materials and whether their supply may be limited in the future
Legislation and compliance though carbon disclosure
Use footprint to meet regulatory requirements
‹#›
Sustainability Performance of the Value Chain
Based on the value chain:
Identify portion of the value chain for analysis
Produce detailed process maps
Identify carbon-related conversion (consumption) related to each step
* A source is any process or activity through which a greenhouse gas is released into the atmosphere
** A sink is a reservoir that accumulates and stores more carbon than is released
‹#›
Conceptualisation of Life Cycle – Postmodernism
Note: Interpretation – Organisations as ‘ideas’ created and constrained through conceptualisation/
theorisation
Identify purpose and key stakeholders
Consult with stakeholders
‹#›
Scope 1 emissions
The GHG emissions released to the atmosphere as a direct result of an activity, or series of activities at a facility level.
Sometimes referred to as direct emissions.
Examples are:
emissions produced from manufacturing processes, such as from the manufacture of cement
emissions from the burning of diesel fuel in trucks
fugitive emissions, such as methane emissions from coal mines, or production of electricity by burning coal.
Scope 1 Emissions
National Greenhouse Accounts Factors, , Australian National Greenhouse Accounts, Published by the Department of the Environment, Commonwealth of Australia 2015
‹#›
Scope 2 Indirect. The emissions released to the atmosphere from the indirect consumption of an energy commodity
For example, ‘indirect emissions’ come from the use of electricity produced by the burning of coal in another facility.
Scope 2 Emissions
‹#›
Scope 3 Emissions
Indirect GHG emissions, other than scope 2 emissions, that are generated in the wider economy.
They occur as a consequence of the activities of a facility, but from sources not owned nor controlled by that facility’s business.
Sustainable procurement – examples are extraction and production of purchased materials, transportation of purchased fuels, use of sold products and services, and flying on a commercial airline by a person from another business.
‹#›
Analysing Overall Emission is Inadequate
Procedures documents may need to be revised and expanded to provide improved information and linkages to data sources
Obtaining the cost of staff use of taxis from a financial system, e.g. SAP
‹#›
Determine carbon emissions at each activity
Determine source of each emission
Identify measurements available for each emission and each source
‹#›
Quantify Carbon Equivalent
Quantify each emission source
Electricity?
Gas?
Diesel?
Petrol?
Paper consumption?
Determine CO2 equivalent tonnes for each emission
Compare against point of obligation as well as total obligation
Source: 2007 Full fuel cycle emissions factor. National Greenhouse Accounts (NGA) Factors, January 2008, Commonwealth of Australia, Department of Climate Change. Available at http://www.climatechange.gov.au/workbook/pubs/workbook-feb2008
‹#›
Locate the CO2e Frameworks
National Greenhouse and Energy Reporting (Measurement) Determination 2008
The National Greenhouse Accounts (NGA) Factors, 2015 workbook and the Australian Standard
Adapted from: https://www.environment.gov.au/system/files/resources/3ef30d52-d447-4911-b85c-1ad53e55dc39/files/national-greenhouse-accounts-factors-august-2015
‹#›
Calculating Waste Disposal
Emissions from waste disposal to landfill and wastewater treatment
https://www.environment.gov.au/system/files/resources/3ef30d52-d447-4911-b85c-1ad53e55dc39/files/national-greenhouse-accounts-factors-august-2015
The National Greenhouse Accounts (NGA) Factors has been prepared by the Department of the Environment and is designed for use by companies and individuals to estimate greenhouse gas emissions.
Disposals of 50 tonnes of paper:
50 x 2.9 = 147 tonnes CO2e
‹#›
Paper Usage and Carbon Equivalent
See: http://www.treeproject.org.au/membership/paper-usage-calculator.htm
Proliferation of online calculators
‹#›
Develop strategies for reducing carbon footprint
Action Plan:
Short-list high carbon sources
Determine root cause of emissions
Identify relevant carbon sinks
Investigate methods for reducing emissions, implications
Prepare recommendation for improvement
‹#›
‹#›
Carbon Reporting
Yes, it is true that market demand is a major driver.
Customer requirements and external communication – e.g. buyers and therefore retailers are increasingly demanding climate information
Differentiation –marketing benefits and differentiation of product/service
Brand association and reputation risk
Identify high profile issues and manage these through transparency of reporting and action plans
‹#›
Postmodernism & Critique
Remember that for organisations:
……‘knowledge serves power by shaping the boundaries of what may legitimately be thought and spoken in organisational settings’ (Taylor, 2005: 126).
We need to evoke alternatives to established thinking, which may be constraining, harmful & unproductive.
Question organisational assumption, the application of this knowledge (decision-making) and organisational outcomes.
RMIT University
24
What are our responsibilities towards the environment?
‹#›
Sustainability Reporting – Organised Hypocrisy
Critical Theory critique of Sustainability Reporting
Reality is that that Sustainability discourse is ubiquitous
There is an argument that societal and institutional pressures drive organisations to engage in hypocrisy and develop façades, thereby severely limiting the prospects that sustainability reports will ever evolve into substantive disclosures
Who is driving the agenda in organisations?
Cho, C. H., Laine, M., Roberts, R. W., & Rodrigue, M. (2015). Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and sustainability reporting. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 40, 78-94.
‹#›
Postmodernist – Beware Trapped by Narratives
Sustainability reporting – A contextual dialogue between accounting academics, politicians and lobbyists
Current efforts at integrated reporting are unlikely to change how large companies do business in order to address the risk of climate change in the short term
Authors Atkins et al. (2015) use a song cycle to describe how we are trapped in a dialogue (talking), but not taking adequate action
Atkins, J., Atkins, B. C., Thomson, I., & Maroun, W. (2015). “Good” news from nowhere: imagining utopian sustainable accounting. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 28(5), 651-670.
‹#›
Authentic Approach to the Environment
Company ethos approach
Organisational ethics (then strategy): Use sustainability as a driver for specific projects
Use results of footprint study to reduce and at least manage negative impacts
Authentic approach to employee satisfaction
Internal communications – further motivate internal engagement on sustainability projects
‹#›
Summary – Interpreting the Relationship Between Organisation and the Environment
Built upon reflexivity: questioning the assumptions that underlie our interpretation and ‘understanding’ of the environment
RMIT University
28
‹#›
References
Binh Bui, Charl de Villiers, Business strategies and management accounting in response to climate change risk exposure and regulatory uncertainty, In The British Accounting Review, Volume 49, Issue 1, 2017, Pages 4-24,
Schaltegger, S., Etxeberria, I. Á., and Ortas, E. (2017) Innovating Corporate Accounting and Reporting for Sustainability – Attributes and Challenges. Sust. Dev., 25: 113–122.
National Greenhouse and Energy Reporting (Measurement) Determination 2008
The National Greenhouse Accounts (NGA) Factors, 2015 workbook and the Australian Standard
Giovanna Michelon, Silvia Pilonato, Federica Ricceri, Robin W Roberts, (2016) “Behind camouflaging: traditional and innovative theoretical perspectives in social and environmental accounting research”, Sustainability Accounting, Management and Policy Journal, Vol. 7 Issue: 1, pp.2-25
Sullivan, R., & Gouldson, A. (2012). Does voluntary carbon reporting meet investors’ needs? Journal of Cleaner Production, 36, 60–67
Haller, A., van Staden, C., & Landis, C. (2016, October 8). Value added as part of sustainability reporting: Reporting on distribuational fairness or obfuscation? Journal of Business Ethics
Cho, C.H. , Laine, M. , Roberts, R.W. and Rodrigue, M. (2015), “Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and sustainability reporting”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 40, pp. 78-94.
‹#›
29
Organisational Analysis
Thought diversity and thought leadership
‹#›
“The world as we have created it is a process of our thinking. It cannot be changed without changing our thinking.”
RMIT University
2
Albert Einstein
‹#›
2
Lecture Aims
Understand how the mind (and therefore our thinking) is socially constructed
Understand why diversity of thought is elusive
Understand why diversity of thought is desirable
Understand diversity of thought:
At the individual level
At the organisational level
At the global level
Understand ‘thought leadership’
RMIT University
3
‹#›
3
RMIT University
The social construction of thought
To survive, humankind needs psychological economies (Berger & Luckmann, 1966)
Key premises
‹#›
4
RMIT University
Psychological economies – why?
To “free the individual from the burden of ‘all those decisions’” and create psychological space so that we can direct our attention toward things that advance our odds of survival and progress, as a species (Berger & Luckmann, 1966: 71).
“The background of habitualized activity opens up a foreground for deliberation and innovation” (Berger & Luckmann, 1966: 71).
‹#›
Pictures: “Hull Riveting”, by Frederick B Taylor (1906)
“The Hand-Mill”, by Robert Ronald McIan (1803-1856)
Cave painting of hunting scene.
5
RMIT University
The social construction of thought
To survive, humankind needs psychological economies (Berger & Luckmann, 1966)
Key premises
So we create “typifications” (Schutz & Luckmann1973) and “thought categories” (Douglas, 1986; Schutz & Luckmann, 1973)
‹#›
6
RMIT University
Psychological economies – how?
Typifications: akin to stereotypes and learned from birth, typifications are a way of quickly making sense of the world by mentally putting everything we need to know and understand into designated boxes. We apply them to people, creatures, situations, and things (Schutz, 1962; 1970).
Thought categories: we make sense of the universe by categorising everything around us, in binary ways. Things that do not fit into the categories we have created, we abhor. When things defy categorisation, or are in the wrong category, or move from one category to another, they are out of place, they do not fit in, and they are transgressive (Douglas, 1966).
‹#›
7
RMIT University
Psychological economies – how?
Typifications and thought categories are passed from generation to generation, through a process of socialisation. The way we think is socially constructed. The thinking process, itself, is institutional in nature.
“Cognition is the most socially-conditioned activity of man”
([sic] Ludwik Fleck, 1935: 42)
‹#›
8
RMIT University
“Thought categories” (Mary Douglas, 1966)
‹#›
On thought categories, see: Mike Callaghan on Mary Douglas’s Purity and Danger:
9
RMIT University
The social construction of thought
To survive, humankind needs psychological economies (Berger & Luckmann, 1966)
Key premises
So we create “typifications” (Schutz & Luckmann1973) and “thought categories” (Douglas, 1986; Schutz & Luckmann, 1973)
Typifications and thought categories are shared by members of a society. They constitute our collective “basic assumptions” about the world, they determine what is relevant to us and what is not, and they provide shared schema for understanding. (Douglas, 1986; Schutz, 1944)
‹#›
10
RMIT University
The social construction of thought: implications
Our mental equipment operates in the same way. Societies share a “thought style” (Douglas, 1986). There is a sameness about the way we think.
Paradox: creating psychological freedom for innovation depends on the uncritical acceptance of fundamental assumptions
True novelty is transgressive and illegitimate (Hargadon & Douglas, 2001)
Societies teach their members to think in the same way → thought homogeneity
‹#›
11
RMIT University
The social construction of thought: implications
Our mental equipment operates in the same way. Societies share a “thought style” (Douglas, 1986). There is a sameness about the way we think.
Societies teach their members to think in the same way → thought homogeneity
Members of society share some “thinking and feeling alike”; societies as wholes generate different kinds of knowledges
(Douglas, 1986: 9)
From epistemology lecture:
“What of a truth that is bounded by these mountains and is falsehood to the world that lives beyond?”
Michel Eyquem de Montaigne
‹#›
12
RMIT University
What does this mean for ingenuity, innovation, and diversity of thought?
Within societies, diversity of thought is challenging
Trans-cultural, trans-societal, and trans-experiential exchange of ideas → diversity of thought
‹#›
13
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Epistemologies at the global level
‹#›
14
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Similar cultures have similar schema → easier to share knowledge, but arguably the variety of insights is diminished.
Epistemologies at the global level
‹#›
15
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Similar cultures have similar schema → easier to share knowledge, but arguably the variety of insights is diminished.
Epistemologies at the global level
Similar cultures share similar epistemologies
Is it possible, at a global level, for there to be a hegemonic, shared epistemology?
‹#›
16
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Similar cultures have similar schema → easier to share knowledge, but arguably the variety of insights is diminished.
Epistemologies at the global level
De Sousa Santos (2018):
There exists a “cognitive empire”: Eurocentric thought
The “epistemologies of the South” – a “collection of knowledges born of and anchored in the experiences of marginalized peoples who actively resist capitalism, colonialism, and patriarchy” – have been oppressed
‹#›
17
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Similar cultures have similar schema → easier to share knowledge, but arguably the variety of insights is diminished.
Epistemologies at the global level
Yet, “the understanding of the world by far exceeds the Western understanding of the world” (de Sousa Santos, 2014: viii)
And, “the basic tradition of Western thinking has not provided a simple model of constructive thinking” (de Bono, 1985: 3)
‹#›
18
Culture 9
Culture 2
Culture 8
Culture 1
Culture 4
Culture 7
Culture 3
Culture 6
Culture 5
Similar cultures have similar schema → easier to share knowledge, but arguably the variety of insights is diminished.
Epistemologies at the global level
Yet, “the understanding of the world by far exceeds the Western understanding of the world” (de Sousa Santos, 2014: viii)
And, “the basic tradition of Western thinking has not provided a simple model of constructive thinking” (de Bono, 1985: 3)
Relevance to organisational analysis and management?
Global business
International trade and diplomacy
International institutions (e.g. World Bank; International Monetary Fund)
Multi-national organisations
International development organisations
Etc. etc.
‹#›
19
RMIT University
How to achieve diversity of thought?
Don’t “[filter] out people who raise unacceptable questions” (Chomsky, 1987: 30, cited in de Sousa Santos, 2018: 222).
Recall epistemology lecture. If knowledge is tacit and embodied, then we must give great credence to personal experience. Incorporate into teams people who have come from places, been places, done things, seen things, and experienced things that you and others have not. Actively seek trans-experiential input.
Enlist those who can broker, translate, and mobilise knowledge. To move knowledge around and beyond organisation, you need diplomats who can decode, interpret, and break down disciplinary and cognitive boundaries.
If we are hard-wired to recoil from cognitive boundary-crossing phenomena (Douglas, 1966), then we must resist these instincts.
Seek out diverse epistemologies.
‹#›
20
RMIT University
How to achieve diversity of thought?
Facilitate “perspective taking”: “the ability to entertain the perspective of another” (Galinsky & Moskowitz, 2000: 708).
Increases “self-other overlap”, suppressing “accessibility of stereotypes” and increasing openness to others (Galinsky & Moskowitz, 2000).
Can stimulate creativity in teams if they are diverse, but depends on “degree to which team members engage in perspective taking” (Hoever et al., 2012: 982).
Engage in “parallel thinking” rather than argument (de Bono, 1985).
White hat: neutral & objective; gather facts & figures
Red hat: emotions; emotional viewpoints
Black hat: caution & careful; search for weaknesses in ideas
Yellow hat: sunny & positive; hope, positive thinking
Green hat: fertile growth; creativity & new ideas
Blue hat: cool, controlled; organise the thinking process
‹#›
21
RMIT University
How to achieve diversity of thought?
Engage in multi-paradigmatic perception
‹#›
22
RMIT University
Seeking diversity of thought: a further epistemological virtue?
Recall “virtue epistemology”: “the study of the cognitive character traits and attitudes that make us effective at, and responsible for, acquiring and transmitting epistemic goods”. (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
Might not we consider the active search for diversity of thought an epistemological virtue?
‹#›
23
RMIT University
Thought leadership
https://www.abc.net.au/news/2018-11-24/banking-royal-commission-commonwealth-bank-bosses-not-learning/10549754
Your learning outcomes (Lecture 1)
‹#›
24
RMIT University
Thought leadership
https://www.abc.net.au/news/2018-11-24/banking-royal-commission-commonwealth-bank-bosses-not-learning/10549754
Your learning outcomes (Lecture 1)
Foster epistemic virtues within self and others
Facilitate and harness diversity of thought – within self, within teams, within organisations, and within society
Recognise and address, where possible, cognitive injustices
‹#›
25
Lecture Aims
Understand how the mind (and therefore our thinking) is socially constructed
Understand why diversity of thought is elusive
Understand why diversity of thought is desirable
Understand diversity of thought:
At the individual level
At the organisational level
At the global level
Understand ‘thought leadership’
RMIT University
26
‹#›
26
“The mind is not a vessel to be filled, but a fire to be kindled.”
RMIT University
27
Plutarch, AD 46-119
‹#›
27
References
Baird, C., & Calvard, T.S. (2019). Epistemic vices in organizations: Knowledge, truth, and unethical conduct. Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 160: 263–276.
Berger, P. & Luckmann, T. (1066). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. USA: Penguin Books.
Burrell, G. & Morgan, G. (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis: Elements of the Sociology of Corporate Life. New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
De Bono, E. (1985). Six Thinking Hats. Melbourne: Penguin Books.
De Sousa Santos, B. (2014). Epistemologies of the South. New York, NY: Routledge.
De Sousa Santos, B. (2018). The End of the Cognitive Empire: The Coming of Age of Epistemologies of the South. Croydon, UK: Duke University Press.
Douglas, M. (1986). How Institutions Think. New York: Syracuse University Press.
Galinsky, A.D. & Moskowitz, G.B. (2000). Perspective-taking: Decreasing stereotype expression, stereotype accessibility, and in-group favoritism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(4): 708–724.
Hoever, I.J., van Kippenberg, D., van Ginkel, W.P., & Barkema, H.G. (2012). Fostering team creativity: Perspective-taking as key to unlocking diversity’s potential. Journal of Applied Psychology, 97(5): 982–996.
Schutz, A. & Luckmann, T. (1973). The Structures of the Life World. London: Heinemann Educational Books Ltd.
RMIT University
28
‹#›
Organisational Analysis
Organisational Knowledge and Knowledge Management
‹#›
Aims
To discuss knowledge as an organisational resource (VIRO)
To discuss knowledge creation cycles in organisations
To build on your understanding of knowledge cycles organisations.
Codifying knowledge
Controlled dictionaries, vocabularies
Taxonomies
Folksonomies
Organisational Implications
‹#›
Definition of Knowledge Management
“Knowledge Management is the process of capturing, distributing, and effectively using knowledge.”
Davenport, T. and Prusak, L. (1998)
This definition does not commit any stakeholder to any particular form of method or technology.
‹#›
Job Profiles in Knowledge Management
‹#›
Knowledge and Competitive Advantage
As a Resource:
Knowledge, in the organisational context, is:
the sum of what is known among organisational members.
Organisational success requires organisations to develop new techniques and competencies to fully utilise the intelligence & knowledge among its organisational members.
To become aware of and utilise both explicit and tacit knowledge.
‹#›
Knowledge – Resource Based View
Competitive Advantage
Part of strategy is taking a resource based view of the organisation
Knowledge, learning are intangible resources
Competition in the ‘knowledge economy’ requires organisations:
to acquire & make use of (i.e. exploit) existing knowledge (within and beyond the organisation)
manage and utilise knowledge innovatively through exploration and searching for new options
‹#›
Explicit versus Tacit Knowledge
Explicit knowledge:
Can be codified (tangible)
Precisely and formally articulated
Easy to transfer, share, document and communicate
“Explicit knowledge is emphasised as a management tool to be exploited as organisational knowledge. Groupware, intranets, list servers, knowledge repositories, database management and knowledge action networks allow the sharing of organisational knowledge”
Scarbrough et al. (1999)
“Managers hope that these tools will retain knowledge within the company when employees have left, and also that this will encourage learning and the flourishing of communities of interest across functional boundaries”
Radcliffe-Martin, Coakes and Sugden (2000)
‹#›
Explicit versus Tacit Knowledge
Tacit knowledge:
Subconsciously understood or applied
Difficult to articulate and often context-specific
Developed from direct action and experience
Shared through conversation or story-telling
“Tacit knowledge is not available as a text. . . .It involves intangible factors embedded in personal beliefs, experiences, and values” (Pan and Scarbrough 1999).
‹#›
Knowledge as a Resource
Resource Analysis (VIRO)
Organisational Analysis examines resources as:
V – Valuable
I – Imitable (or non-imitable)
R – Rare
O – Organised (well deployed)
Preparing some business students for their Capstone course
How do we put a “value” on knowledge as a resource?
‹#›
Challenges to Knowledge Management
A number of challenges exist to KM
Different knowledge formats in organisations
Lack of systems integration
Knowledge creation – how does this occur?
Knowledge loss
focus on artefact rather than process
‹#›
Knowledge Formats
Whether we are aware, knowledge is held in organisations in various ways:
Think of all the paper based instances you can encounter
Digital: Databases, and serialised in different formats
What has been missed?
‹#›
Diversity of Applications in Organisations
SAP
Procurement
Manufacturing Planning
Sales
Finance
HR
No system is integrated – different formats
Nor may it desirable for systems to integrated
‹#›
Lack of Systems Integration
Does digitisation offer the solution?
The challenge:
once digitisation occurs, knowledge can become more difficult to discover
No system is integrated, with different data formats causing problems
Nor is it always desirable for systems to be completely integrated
‹#›
Knowledge loss
Remember Organisational Learning Cycles
Single, Double and Triple Loop Learning
Organisational Learning Occurs through a number of activities, e.g.
Strategy
Human Resources
Project management – Project start to completion
Human interaction, e.g. Concurrent Engineering
Design thinking, e.g. Controlled Convergence
Manufacturing
Sales
Marketing
All of these are value adding activities – How?
‹#›
The Richness of Knowledge
Focus on artefact (end result) rather than process
A large part of learning is a social activity
Remember organisational isomorphism: how do we become the same?
Or rather, should we be the same?
……….. and therefore knowledge loss
‹#›
Spiral of Knowledge Creation
Let’s discuss these four steps
When value adding activities occur: (i) existing knowledge is drawn upon and (ii) new knowledge is generated.
Nonaka I, Toyama R and Konno N (2000)
‹#›
The Challenge of Knowledge Management – the “Sociology” of Knowledge Creation
Knowledge is constantly being constructed
What we often think of as being “knowledge” is only the end result
What is often missed out, is the process of knowledge creation.
Innovation
Social interaction
Individual thinking
Nonaka I, Toyama R and Konno N (2000)
‹#›
Knowledge Capture Must be Continuous
The process of socialisation, i.e. Design, Development
Codifying is continuous and the meaning of codes changes, i.e. easily forgotten
In a neohumanist – postmodernist sense, the organisational narrative changes
‹#›
Knowledge Management – Understanding Ontology
Remember, there may be different ontological assumptions
Therefore, if you understand ontology, the neohumanist (postmodernist) paradigm views knowledge as liberating.
‹#›
Role of Consultants in Analysis
As a consultant or manager, you must become aware that ‘ideas’ and ‘values’ influence social and organisational behaviour.
The social world is negotiated, organised and reproduced (i.e. constructed) by our interpretations of events, the action of others and the symbols around us.
The social world is ‘objectified’ through repeating past behaviours and shared experience, understanding (i.e. meaning) and interaction.
Inter-subjectivity: an individual’s internalisation and interpretation of shared experience and meaning.
The Social Construction of Reality (Berger and Luckmann,1966)
‹#›
The Neohumanist Perspective
Each organisation has its narrative… captured in language and imagery.
‹#›
Meta-Data, Tagging
We now examine the technical aspects of knowledge management
Not in terms of technical platforms, but how knowledge is “highlighted”
Assuming individuals recognise patterns
Wants to highlight an aspect of knowledge that is interesting
For the purpose of creating interest and sharing
‹#›
Meta-Data
Example of tagging
Do you use document properties?
‹#›
Document Meta-Data
Purpose of “tagging” is to give more information about an artefact
Make knowledge “discoverable”
Microsoft Word Document
Document Properties
Opportunities for you to “tag”
‹#›
Tagging – Making Knowledge Discoverable
Database
Knowledge Management Platform
Database
Database
Knowledge Management solutions exist – often technology driven.
Application
Application
Application
Tags
Tags
Tags
‹#›
How do You Codify Knowledge?
We will discuss some ways of “codifying” knowledge.
Codes identify and associate meaning
Taxonomies (enterprise taxonomies)
Folksonomies
#Hashtag
Trending
‹#›
How do you codify knowledge?
Codes that identify and associate meaning
Taxonomies (enterprise taxonomies)
Folksonomies
#Hashtag
Trending
‹#›
Enterprise Taxonomies
Formal Classification structure
Developed top-down
Namespace – contextual
Hierarchical (parent-child relationships)
Controlled – rules are created for each taxonomy term
Taxonomy terms tend not to appear in more than one branch
Vocabulary tagging makes knowledge visible, i.e. findable/retrievable/discoverable, but organisations tend to lack the time or resources to build a taxonomy
‹#›
A system of collating and harvesting concepts
User generated, i.e. own vocabulary
Non-hierarchical
Bottom-up
Trending
#Hashtagging
Folksonomies
‹#›
The Rise of Fake-News
In a social media sense, just because something trends, is it “correct”?
‹#›
Critical Thinking – Consequences
Could the notion of “fake news” affect organisations? How would you manage it?
The requirement of “truth” is part of the analysis of knowledge” (Tienson J., 1973)
‹#›
Analysing the Organisational Narrative
As a tool, we look at a further perspective which is the organisational narrative.
What or who controls language use?
the meaning (semantics) e.g. dictionary, meta-data?
‹#›
Summary
We have covered a number of issues relating to knowledge management
Technology solutions exist
You now understand the sociology behind KM
More equipped to understand what needs to be captured
Focus on the social process and not the artifact
‹#›
References
Davenport, T. and Prusak, L. (1998). Working knowledge: how organizations manage what they know. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press.
Hislop, D., 2018. Knowledge Management in Organizations: A critical introduction. 4th ed. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Nonaka I and Takeuchi H (1995) The Knowledge-Creating Company: How Japanese companies create the dynamics of innovation. New York: Oxford University Press.
Nonaka I, Toyama R and Konno N (2000) SECI, Ba and leadership: a unified model of dynamic knowledge creation. Long Range Planning 33(1): 5-34.
Laucuka, A. (2018). Communicative Functions of Hashtags, Economics and Culture, 15(1), 56-62
Donald, H., 2018. Knowledge Management In Organizations. Oxford University Press.
‹#›
Organisational Analysis
Knowledge and the Learning Organisation
‹#›
The course is about analysing organisations
The purpose is to encourage you to analyse aspects of the learning organisations and knowledge
How knowledge is generated individually
What knowledge is focused upon, i.e. analysing what persuades us to believe the truth
Collective learning, i.e. does “shared” knowledge exist?
‹#›
Aims
Background – The Knowledge Economy
Understand Explicit vs Tacit Knowledge
Individual vs Organisational Learning
Recognising learning cycles in organisations
How do organisations learn?
Single-loop, Double-loop Learning and Triple Loop
The Organisational Maturity Paradox: Limitations of Process Conformance
‹#›
Employment Profiles…
Perform a job search for yourself…
‹#›
Employment Profiles…
Perform a job search for yourself…
‹#›
Origins of the “Knowledge Economy”
In a post-industrial society, national prosperity, is claimed to be depended upon nation’s capturing the ‘high-road’ end of the service economy—the knowledge economy.
‹#›
Singapore tops most charts for competitiveness, digitisation… But is it a true “knowledge economy”?
What are your thoughts?
‹#›
The Knowledge Economy
The Knowledge Economy is defined as:
“production and services based on knowledge-intensive activities that contribute to an accelerated pace of technical and scientific advance” ***
“The key component of a knowledge economy is a greater reliance on intellectual capabilities than on physical inputs or natural resources”.
Powell and Snellman (2004)
*** as well as rapid obsolescence
‹#›
Knowledge – Resource Based View
Competitive Advantage
Part of strategy is taking a resource based view of the organisation
Knowledge, learning are intangible resources
Competition in the ‘knowledge economy’ requires organisations:
To acquire & make use of (i.e. exploit) existing knowledge (within and beyond the organisation)
Manage and utilise knowledge innovatively through exploration and searching for new options
‹#›
Explicit versus Tacit Knowledge
Explicit knowledge:
Can be codified (tangible)
Precisely and formally articulated
Easy to transfer, share, document and communicate
“Explicit knowledge is emphasised as a management tool to be exploited as organisational knowledge. Groupware, intranets, list servers, knowledge repositories, database management and knowledge action networks allow the sharing of organisational knowledge”
Scarbrough et al. (1999)
“Managers hope that these tools will retain knowledge within the company when employees have left, and also that this will encourage learning and the flourishing of communities of interest across functional boundaries”
Radcliffe-Martin, Coakes and Sugden (2000)
‹#›
Explicit versus Tacit Knowledge
Tacit knowledge:
Subconsciously understood or applied
Difficult to articulate and often context-specific
Developed from direct action and experience
Shared through conversation or story-telling
“Tacit knowledge is not available as a text. . . .It involves intangible factors embedded in personal beliefs, experiences, and values” (Pan and Scarbrough 1999).
‹#›
Knowledge and Competitive Advantage
As a Resource:
Knowledge, in the organisational context, is:
the sum of what is known among organisational members.
Organisational success requires organisations to develop new techniques and competencies to fully utilise the intelligence and knowledge among its organisational members.
To become aware of and utilise both explicit and tacit knowledge.
‹#›
Analysing Organisations as Social Constructs
The sum of what is known among organisational members
Knowledge is socially constructed through an ongoing and dynamic process
‹#›
Social Constructivist
Meta-theoretical Underpinnings
Ontology: subjectivism – what is real is that which we agree is real (i.e. that which is meaningful).
Epistemology: interpretivism: truth is relative to time and place and the individuals who are involved in constructing meaning.
Organisations are ‘meaningful’ and are (re)constructed by their members through meaningful interaction with one another.
This has implications for designers, consultants, engineers, scientists……..
‹#›
Symbolic Interpretivist Analysis
As a consultant:
You understand that reality is socially constructed through an ongoing and dynamic process
The your goal is to arrive at context specific and relative statements of the logic of organisational reality.
Analysis: Qualitative (e.g. Ethnography)
Inductive: a process of developing theory from observation and interpretation
‹#›
How Organisations Learn?
Recognising Social Constructivism:
A social construct is an idea which may appear to be natural and obvious to those who accept it, but in reality is an invention of a particular culture or society
People act on their interpretations and knowledge about a given phenomena and thereby internalise and reproduce that idea/notion/reality
‹#›
Organisational Isomorphism
Instutional Theory: How individuals become the “same”
Coercive Pressures (Isomorphism)
Mimetic Pressures (Isomorphism)
Normative Pressures (Isomorphism)
‹#›
Social Constructivism
Analysis:
Be aware of the social processes that frame or influence perceptions of organisational life.
Highlights the fluid, diverse and subjective aspects of organisational activity and decision-making.
Makes us consider the ‘value’ ladenness of ‘facts’ that organisations rely upon.
To bring about organisational change requires ‘rewiring’ the minds of the ‘constructors’.
In some readings, this is referred to as “symbolic interprevist”
‹#›
The Learning Organisation
“Organisations where people continually expand their capacity to create the results they truly desire, where new and expansive patterns of thinking are nurtured, where collective aspiration is set free, and where people are continually learning to learn together”
Senge (1990, 2014).
“an organisation that facilitates the learning of all its members and consciously transforms itself and its context”
Ellkin and Cone (2009)
‹#›
Learning Organisations
Or, as chief executive […… ] was forced to admit, there was “a culture of us not learning from issues of misconduct in the past”.
Customers weren’t prioritised and executives were too timid to call out bad behaviour. Mr […..] called it “too much fragility … to hear criticism”.
Do organisations engage sufficiently in understanding what learning entails?
‹#›
Learning Organisations and Organisational Change
According to Donald Schön:
“we must invent and develop ‘learning systems’, that is to say, systems capable of bringing about their own continuing transformation.
The task which the loss of the stable state makes imperative, for the person, for our institutions, for our society as a whole, is to learn about learning”
Schön (1973)
‹#›
Analysing Learning Cycles
‹#›
Analysing Learning Cycles
‹#›
Analysing Learning Cycles
Romme and Van Witteloostuijn (1999) describe triple-loop learning as a higher order learning process or methodologies giving members of an organisation the ability to re-frame and “see things in totally new ways
‹#›
Why and What is “Higher Order”?
‹#›
A Higher Order of Learning
Romme and Van Witteloostuijn (1999) describe triple-loop learning as a higher order learning process or methodologies giving members of an organisation the ability to re-frame and “see things in totally new ways
‹#›
Summary
Functionalism
Can you recognise
what perspective?
‹#›
References
Elkin, G., Cone, M. H., & Liao, J. (2009). Chinese pragmatism and the learning organisation. The Learning Organization, 16(1), 69-83.
Georges L. Romme, A., & Van Witteloostuijn, A. (1999). Circular organizing and triple loop learning. Journal of Organizational Change Management, 12(5), 439-454.
Pan, S.L. and Scarbrough, H. 1998. ‘A Socio-technical View of Knowledge Sharing at Buckman Laboratories’. Journal of Knowledge Management, 2(1) September: 55–66.
Powell WW, Snellman K. The Knowledge Economy. Annual Review of Sociology,. 2004;30:199-220.
Radcliffe-Martin V, Coakes E and Sugden G (2000) Knowledge Management Issues in Universities Vine 121 pp14-18
Scarborough, H., Swan, J. and Preston, J. (1999), ‘Knowledge management: a literature review’, Issues in People Management, Institute of Personnel and Development, London.
Schon, D. A. (1973). Beyond the stable state: Public and private learning in a changing society. Harmondsworth, UK.: Penguin.
Senge, P. M. (1990). The fifth discipline: The art and practice of the learning organization. New York: Currency Doubleday.
Senge, P. M. (2014). The fifth discipline fieldbook: Strategies and tools for building a learning organization. Crown Business.
‹#›
Organisational Analysis
Epistemology
‹#›
Lecture Aims
Provide a rationale for understanding epistemology
Define knowledge
Discuss how to differentiate knowledge from mere claims
Relate this to the four paradigms
Next steps
RMIT University
2
Provide a rationale for understanding epistemology
Define knowledge
Discuss how to differentiate knowledge from mere claims
Relate this to the four paradigms
Next steps
‹#›
2
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
‹#›
3
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
DISTORTED IDEOLOGIES
MULTIPLE WAYS OF INTERPRETING ‘RAW FACTS’
SOCIALLY CONSTRUCTED REALITIES
‹#›
4
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
DISTORTED IDEOLOGIES
MULTIPLE WAYS OF INTERPRETING ‘RAW FACTS’
http://www.professionalsaustralia.org.au/blog/management-decision-making/
On what grounds can you claim to really know something?
As a manager or analyst, how will you know what to do?
What is your decision-making methodology?
‹#›
5
Epistemology
“The nature of knowledge, its possibility, scope and general basis.”
Deals with questions such as, How do we know that something is true, and trustworthy, rather than mere opinion or belief? How can we be certain? On what basis can we consider our beliefs to be justified?
RMIT University
6
(Hamlyn, 1995: 242, cited in Crotty,1998: 8)
‹#›
6
What is knowledge?
Philosophers would argue that to count as “knowledge”, a proposition or claim must be subject to some tests ….
RMIT University
7
Philosophers would argue that to count as “knowledge”, a proposition or claim must be subject to some tests ….
Knowledge
Knowledge
Knowledge
Knowledge
‹#›
7
What is knowledge?
Philosophers would argue that to count as “knowledge”, a proposition or claim must be subject to some tests ….
RMIT University
8
Philosophers would argue that to count as “knowledge”, a proposition or claim must be subject to some tests ….
Knowledge is a belief that is justified in some way
‹#›
8
But, there are different kinds of knowledge…
“Episteme” (facts); “techne” (skill); “phronesis” (practical wisdom)
Aristotle, Ethics (1976: 207–210)
Knowing “how” v. knowing “that” v. “understanding-why”
Ross (2020)
Tacit (embodied, uncodified, difficult to pass on to others) and explicit (codified, transmittable, storable)
The ability to “integrate … information into specific action contexts”
Seirafi (2012: n.p.)
RMIT University
9
‹#›
9
And, knowledge is socially situated…
Knowledge is situated and socially differentiated.
(Berger & Luckmann, 1966)
The knowledge of a worker is different from the knowledge of a manager. The knowledge of an engineer is different from the knowledge of an architect. The knowledge of a mason is different from the knowledge of a carpenter. The knowledge of a doctor is different from the knowledge of a nurse. The knowledge of a legal advisor is different from the knowledge of a marketer. The knowledge of a sales person is different from the knowledge of a logistics and supply chain manager. And so on, and so on ….
RMIT University
10
‹#›
10
So how do we distinguish knowledge from non-knowledge?
Knowledge:
Has some truth to its premise
Has to correspond with organisational ‘reality’ in some way (remembering that reality may be co-created by people within the organisation)
Has to be trustworthy, reliable, or verifiable
Has to check out against empirical reality (what our perception and senses tell us)
RMIT University
11
‹#›
11
So how do we distinguish knowledge from non-knowledge?
Knowledge:
Has some truth to its premise
Has to correspond with organisational ‘reality’ in some way (remembering that reality may be co-created by people within the organisation)
Has to be trustworthy, reliable, or verifiable
Has to check out against empirical reality (what our perception and senses tell us)
RMIT University
12
Examine how a knowledge claim has been arrived at. On what basis is this belief justified? Perception? Reasoning? Data?
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Do your due diligence.
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Triangulate your sources.
What do your senses, perception, and experience tell you? Observe closely. Is the knowledge claim consistent with what you see and hear going on around you?
“Virtue epistemology”: “the study of the cognitive character traits and attitudes that make us effective at, and responsible for, acquiring and transmitting epistemic goods”. (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
“Effective and responsible inquiry” (Hookway, 2003, cited in Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
E.g. “Facing the truth” (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 265)
‹#›
12
Knowledge:
Has some truth to its premise
Has to correspond with organisational ‘reality’ in some way (remembering that reality may be co-created by people within the organisation)
Has to be trustworthy, reliable, or verifiable
Has to check out against empirical reality (what our perception and senses tell us)
RMIT University
13
Examine how a knowledge claim has been arrived at. On what basis is this belief justified? Perception? Reasoning? Data?
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Do your due diligence.
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Triangulate your sources.
What do your senses, perception, and experience tell you? Observe closely. Is the knowledge claim consistent with what you see and hear going on around you?
“Virtue epistemology”: “the study of the cognitive character traits and attitudes that make us effective at, and responsible for, acquiring and transmitting epistemic goods”. (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
“Effective and responsible inquiry” (Hookway, 2003, cited in Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
E.g. “Facing the truth” (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 265)
… So we have “Epistemic Virtue”….
‹#›
.
13
Knowledge:
Has some truth to its premise
Has to correspond with organisational ‘reality’ in some way (remembering that reality may be co-created by people within the organisation)
Has to be trustworthy, reliable, or verifiable
Has to check out against empirical reality (what our perception and senses tell us)
RMIT University
14
Examine how a knowledge claim has been arrived at. On what basis is this belief justified? Perception? Reasoning? Data?
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Do your due diligence.
Is this consistent with other people’s perceptions of what is going on? Ask them. Listen. Observe. Triangulate your sources.
What do your senses, perception, and experience tell you? Observe closely. Is the knowledge claim consistent with what you see and hear going on around you?
“Virtue epistemology”: “the study of the cognitive character traits and attitudes that make us effective at, and responsible for, acquiring and transmitting epistemic goods”. (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
“Effective and responsible inquiry” (Hookway, 2003, cited in Baird & Calvard, 2019: 264)
E.g. “Facing the truth” (Baird & Calvard, 2019: 265)
… But what about “Epistemic Vice”?
“Epistemic malevolence”: “Wilful hiding of the truth, denying people access to the truth; “spread of ignorance and confusion”
“Epistemic insouciance” (indifference): Disregarding the importance of truth, coherence, honesty, and reasoning. E.g. social media platforms
“Epistemic hubris” (unfounded over-confidence): Unfounded arrogance in the validity of one’s own beliefs
“Epistemic injustice”: Dismissing people’s experiential knowledge and lived experience (e.g. not taking seriously your employees’ experiences and knowledge)
Baird & Calvard, 2019
‹#›
14
A different kind of vice?
“Bulls@#t”
“Articulated without concern for the criteria of the truth” and intended to mislead
“Articulated to pursue [one’s] own purposes and interests”
(Spicer, 2013)
RMIT University
15
‹#›
15
A different kind of vice?
RMIT University
16
“Bulls@#t”
A way to pretend meaninglessness doesn’t exist (see neo-humanism) by inflating what one knows and does
An attempt to avoid interrogation
But, it is not benign. It can distract organisations from primary organisational tasks.
It can engender organisational cynicism
It can be an affront to what organisational members believe truly matters
(Spicer, 2013)
‹#›
16
RMIT University
17
‹#›
17
RMIT University
18
‹#›
18
“There are [three] things in the world you never want to let people see how you make ‘em – laws, sausages, [and knowledge].”
(Leo McGarry, White House Chief of Staff …. In the fictional series, The West Wing)
RMIT University
19
Epistemology allows you to do just that – see how knowledge gets made
‹#›
19
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
‹#›
20
“Paradigms should be mixed to create intellectual tensions and new insights.” (Saemundsson, 2006: 350, reviewing Tsoukas)
RMIT University
21
‹#›
21
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
Positivism
Anti-positivism
“Truth is truth to the end of reckoning.”
William Shakespeare, Measure for Measure
“What of a truth that is bounded by these mountains and is falsehood to the world that lives beyond?
Michel Eyquem de Montaigne
Perception and intuition lead to bias, which lead to faulty beliefs
Perception, intuition, experience lead to substantiated beliefs
“Figures often mislead people … there is no shame in that: words can mislead as well. The problem with numbers is our tendency to treat them with some degree of awe, as if they are somehow more reliable than words … this belief is wholly misplaced” (Devlin, cited in Matthews, 2008)
Can we meet somewhere in the middle?
‹#›
22
RMIT University
23
This is the process of Organisational Analysis
Process of Organisational Analysis is seldom discussed….nor documented.
What leads to the acceptance that the representations of organisations, as found in models or formalisms is correct?
Analysis
Business models as the “product” or output
‹#›
“Man is condemned to be free; because once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he does” [sic]
Jean Paul Sartre
RMIT University
24
‹#›
24
We don’t offer easy answers, we pose questions and encourage you to consider the what the answers might be….
RMIT University
25
‹#›
25
Lecture Aims
Provide a rationale for understanding epistemology
Define knowledge
Discuss how to differentiate knowledge from mere claims
Relate this to the four paradigms
Next steps
RMIT University
26
Provide a rationale for understanding epistemology
Define knowledge
Discuss how to differentiate knowledge from mere claims
Relate this to the four paradigms
Next steps
Provide a rationale for understanding epistemology
Define knowledge
Discuss how to differentiate knowledge from mere claims
Relate this to the four paradigms
Next steps
‹#›
26
Next steps
We begin to discuss how knowledge is actually used in practice in organisations
Please review your tutorial activities in Canvas for the current and coming weeks
Assignment 1 is due at the end of Week 6!
You must be in your groups at this stage; if you are not, see your Lecturer
RMIT University
27
‹#›
27
References
Baird, C., & Calvard, T.S. (2019). Epistemic vices in organizations: Knowledge, truth, and unethical conduct. Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 160: 263–276.
Berger, P. & Luckmann, T. (1066). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. USA: Penguin Books.
Burrell, G. & Morgan, G. (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis: Elements of the Sociology of Corporate Life. New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
Greenhalgh, T., & Wieringa, S. (2011). Is it time to drop the ‘knowledge translation’ metaphor? A critical literature review. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine. Vol. 104: 501–509.
Hirschheim, R., & Klein, H.K. (1989). Four paradigms of information systems development. Communications of the ACM. Vol. 32(10): 1199-1216.
Matthews, D. (2008). Metadecision-making: Rehabilitating Interdisciplinarity in the Decision Sciences. Systems Research and Behavioural Science. Vol. 25: 157–179.
Ross, L.D. (2020). Is understanding reducible? Inquiry. Vol. 63(2): 117–135.
Saemundsson, R.J. (2006). Review of complex knowledge: Studies in Organizational Epistemology by Haridimos Tsoukas. Journal of Management Governance, Vol. 10: 347-350.
Sierafi, K. (2012). Organizational Epistemology: Understanding Knowledge in Organizations. Heidelberg: Springer.
Spicer, A. (2013). Shooting the shit: The role of bullshit in organisations. M@n@agement, Vol. 16: 653–666: https://www.cairn.info/revue-management-2013-5-page-653.htm Accessed 16th August, 2020.
RMIT University
28
‹#›
Organisational Analysis
Four paradigms in organisational analysis: Neo-humanism
‹#›
Lecture Aims
Introduce neo-humanism (also called radical humanism) and show how it manifests in organisational analysis
Illustrate the effects of neo-humanism
Discuss the advantages and limitations of neo-humanism
Next steps
RMIT University
2
Introduce neo-humanism (also called radical humanism) and show how it manifests in organisational analysis
Illustrate the effects of neo-humanism
Discuss the advantages and limitations of neo-humanism
Next steps
‹#›
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Neo-humanism
‹#›
3
RMIT University
Scenario 1
Scenario 2
Irrational, insatiable growth & acquisition, to the destruction of own company
Controlled by subconscious, narcissistic impulses and desires
Absence of self-knowledge
Existential crisis & alienation
Rejection of employment institutions, regimes, constraints, and their ends
Rejection of system of production & distribution
Rejection of surveillance & encroachment on civil liberties
Freedom from interference by authority
Seeking end to illegitimate power of authorities, at enormous personal cost
Abject failure of imagination and foresight
Abject failure to question
Self-delusion
Preferencing the interests of the corporation over people and nature
Uncontrolled anger arising from subconscious fears
Clumsy deployment of improvement tools that question workers’ professional skills & competence
Scenario 3
Scenario 4
Scenario 5
‹#›
IMAGES:
Image at bottom right is of animal activists outside Flinders Street in Melbourne.
Image of three statues and person standing on chair, see Wikipedia: “Anything to Say? is an itinerant bronze sculpture and art installation by Italian artist Davide
Dormino
which was placed in Berlin’s Alexanderplatz on May Day 2015. It features the whistleblowers Edward Snowden, Julian Assange, and Chelsea Manning standing on three chairs; the entire installation (which includes a fourth, empty chair meant as a platform for public speaking) is to go on a global tour. The installation was unveiled by “ANYTHINGTOSAY,” a private art project supported with an international crowdfunding.[1]
[2] ”
Other images indictive of existential angst, silencing, alienation, oppression, and psychic pain.
4
RMIT University
What unites these scenarios?
What do they have in common?
What do they mean for you, as future managers?
‹#›
5
RMIT University
Neo-humanism:
Rejects the idea of “rational man” [sic]
Critiques, dissents, and searches for alternatives
Calls for spiritual and psychic emancipation, belongingness, and for control to be given back to the employee
Calls for meaning to be restored to work
Rejects obedience & compliance to organisational edicts and norms; rejects indoctrination
Imagines new organisational possibilities
Seeks to transcend existing power arrangements (e.g. capitalism and managerial prerogative)
Believes that organisations should serve human beings, not that human beings should serve organisations (Aktouf, 1992)
Burrell & Morgan, 1979; Hirschheim & Klein, 1989; Aktouf, 1992; Aktouf & Holford, 2008
‹#›
6
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Managers ensure that human beings serve organisations
Managers see human beings as instruments of production
Organisations & managers must serve human beings (A, 1992)
Human beings are ends in and of themselves
Managers legitimate organisational projects by securing consensus through participation
Most consensus is a falsity, and achieved via “manipulation” of our perceptions, self-image, feelings, identity, etc. (A, 1992)
So-called “participation” creates false interactions. “Consensus without the operation of power” is needed (B&M, p. 295)
Burrell & Morgan, 1979; Aktouf, 1992; Aktouf & Holford, 2008
Managers side with & are agents of capitalist interests
Managers are complicit in the exploitation of workers
Human beings cannot be reduced to a pre-specified class or identity; human beings are diverse
Ideology distorts understanding & must be dismantled
‹#›
7
RMIT University
‹#›
8
RMIT University
To know what to do, we must change the way we think (a shift in consciousness)
Shifts in consciousness require freedom from external & internal regulation, rejection of narratives that dictate who we should be, & freedom from undistorted communication
Knowing what to do involves “ideal” communication & placing the human condition at the centre of our deliberations
So-called general laws about the “best way” of doing something perpetuate repressive systems of production
What counts as “knowledge” is deeply uncreative & typically serves power
The way we think is the product of institutional forces
Knowledge is obscured by systems of work & production that domesticate us & impede true reflection & insight
‹#›
9
Shifts in consciousness require freedom from external & internal regulation, rejection of narratives that dictate who we should be, & freedom from undistorted communication
RMIT University
To know what to do, we must change the way we think (a shift in consciousness)
Knowing what to do involves “ideal” communication & placing the human condition at the centre of our deliberations
So-called general laws about the “best way” of doing something perpetuate repressive systems of production
What counts as “knowledge” is deeply uncreative & typically serves power
The way we think is the product of institutional forces
Knowledge is obscured by systems of work & production that domesticate us & impede true reflection & insight
‹#›
10
Value of neo-humanism
RMIT University
11
Diagnostic ‘tool’ to anticipate and explore implications of management decisions (risk exploration)
Creative, generative thinking that serves people (ultimately, how can this do wrong by organisations?)
Basis of genuine transformation
Genuinely participative employees, free from psychological and social burdens, able to express their ideas and fulfil their potential
“Ideal”, “undistorted” communication – best of humanity & creativity poured into organisational decision-making
‹#›
11
A neo-humanist’s perspective on functionalist hierarchy
RMIT University
12
HYR Consulting; “Radical humanism in the rise of AI and data analytics”
Tim Leberecht
‹#›
12
Neo-humanism in practice (Aktouf, 1992)
RMIT University
13
Call out unethical behaviour, dishonesty and partial truths, particularly as these affect workers and the community and environment
Resist the fragmentation of work & the destruction of its meaning
Denounce and resist intensification of work
Facilitate genuine worker participation in decisions and profits
Dissolve organisational boundaries when conceiving of the responsibility of the firm
‹#›
13
Neo-humanism in practice
RMIT University
14
Cascades Inc (Aktouf, 1992)
Pulp & papermill
No organisational charts, no official titles or positions, no job descriptions, no time sheets, no supervisory mechanisms
Direct & informal relations at all levels
Self-managing teams etc.
“Spectacular success”
‹#›
14
Neo-humanism in practice
RMIT University
15
Logistics Inc (Burns, 2015)
Giant logistics & transportation firm
Systematically hires & trains ex-prisoners for employment & career opportunities
Disregards any complaints from share-holders; educates concerned employees
Proudly advertises work, despite risk to reputation
Transforms lives, including existing employees; “some of our best employees”
‹#›
15
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Existing systems of production are controlling forces that domesticate, impoverish, and prevent people from reaching their potential
Organisations oppress people and ruin the earth through their reckless and irrational short-term pursuit of profit
Foundational management concepts & practices must be re-thought
Organisations must serve people, not the other way around
Critique is vital & must be maximised
Assumptions about organisations and society
Order & regulation
`
Conflict & radical change
‹#›
16
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Shifts in consciousness hold the key to reimagining work, management, & organisations
Yet, our consciousness (how we think and what we know) is dominated by existing beliefs about how the world should work
We must reject as “knowledge” those management ideas that do not reckon at the deepest level with their implications for human beings
True insight can only be attained by removing barriers to free thought – sub-conscious fears & anxieties; fear of control & authority; impulses to conform and comply; group-think
Assumptions about our knowledge of society
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Objectivism
‹#›
17
RMIT University
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Conflict & radical change
Order & regulation
Burrell & Morgan, 1979
‹#›
18
Limitations of neo-humanism
RMIT University
19
Better at critique, less effective in practice
Focuses on the power / lack of power of our consciousness (mind), but pays less attention to the “material” forces that alienate and oppress people
To date, vulnerable to marginalisation by the “pragmatic” elite
Can verge on anti-organisation stance and anarchistic individualism; this makes enemies – how to be constructive, yet maintain necessary critique?
‹#›
19
Parting words ….
RMIT University
20
People are “more than [what] the job requires” ….
Aktouf, 1992, p. 418
‹#›
20
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Assumptions about our knowledge of society
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Order & regulation
Assumptions about society
Conflict & radical change
Radical structuralism
Social relativism
Neo-humanism
Functionalism
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions, four paradigms
Four radically different ways of seeing organisations
‹#›
21
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Assumptions about our knowledge of society
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Order & regulation
Assumptions about society
Conflict & radical change
Social relativism
Neo-humanism
Functionalism
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions, four paradigms
Four radically different ways of seeing organisations
‹#›
22
Lecture Aims
RMIT University
23
Introduce neo-humanism and show how it manifests in organisational analysis
Illustrate the effects of neo-humanism
Discuss the advantages and limitations of neo-humanism
Next steps
Introduce neo-humanism and show how it manifests in organisational analysis
Illustrate the effects of neo-humanism
Discuss the advantages and limitations of neo-humanism
Next steps
‹#›
Next steps
Please review your tutorial activities in Canvas for the current and coming weeks
Finalise your groups for your Group Assignment
Continue to work on Assignment 1 – due in Week 6
RMIT University
24
‹#›
24
References
Aktouf, O. (1992). Management and theories of organizations in the 1990s: Toward a critical radical humanism? Academy of Management Review. Vol. 17(3): 407-431.
Burns, P. (2015). A neo-institutional study of firms that provide ‘reintegrative’ employment opportunities to former prisoners in a liberal individualist society. Unpublished thesis.
Burrell, G. & Morgan, G. (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis: Elements of the Sociology of Corporate Life. New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
Hirschheim, R., & Klein, H.K. (1989). Four paradigms of information systems development. Communications of the ACM. Vol. 32(10): 1199-1216.
Morgan, G. (1997). Images of Organization. Thousand Oaks, California: Sage Publications.
RMIT University
25
‹#›
Organisational Analysis
Radical Structuralism
‹#›
1
Lecture Aims
Introduce radical structuralism and show how it manifests in organisational analysis
Illustrate the effects of radical structuralism
Discuss the advantages and limitations of radical structuralism
Next steps
RMIT University
2
‹#›
RMIT University
3
FILMS:
Blue Collar (1978), about union corruption and dividing workers against each other
Billy Elliot (2000), set during the 1984-85 miners’ strike; moving picket line scene
Dirty Pretty Things (2002), about immigrant workers, legal and illegal
The Measure of a Man (2015), French film about a middle aged man who loses his factory job, finds another, where he is required to spy on his co-workers.
Norma Rae (1979), about unionizing efforts in a textile factory
North Country (2005) about a class action against sexual harassment in a mining company
Salt of the Earth (1954), about a New Mexico miners’ strike – really controversial at the time, ahead of its time (during the cold war) because of its awareness of racial and gender equity issues.
3
RMIT University
4
What are organisations? Systems of order? Or systems of exploitation and oppression?
4
What is your purpose, or intention?
You have come here to learn about management.
This entails confronting the unsavoury aspects of organisations, and understanding the concepts of power, control, conflict, and exploitation. These aspects of management and organisations are not anomalous. They are part of economic life and must be understood if they are to be addressed.
You have come here to learn about management.
This entails confronting the unsavoury aspects of organisations, and understanding the concepts of power, control, conflict, and exploitation. These aspects of management and organisations are not anomalous. They are part of economic life and must be understood if they are to be addressed.
Radical structuralism – a “conflict and radical change” paradigm – allows you to see, examine, and understand these aspects of organisational life
‹#›
5
But how can we understand power, control, social division, and conflict?
Critical theory, the foundations of radical structuralism
Critical Theory allows us to analyse the roots of dissent, conflict, and coalition.
Critical theory enables managers to understand both sides of an argument.
Critical theory enables managers to understand that antagonism stems from deep-seated and profoundly different assumptions and world-views.
‹#›
6
The intellectual foundations of critical theory and radical structuralism may be found in the work of Karl Marx.
Marx provided a critique of the political economy and the status quo. Concerned with social division, inequality, and conflict within the political economy.
Earlier work dealt with alienation (estrangement from our work and what we produce); later work focused more on the political economy and the antagonistic arrangements within, which Marx theorized would lead to crisis and therefore radical change.
Radical structuralism
“Philosophers have hitherto only interpreted the world in various ways; the point is to change it.”
Karl Marx (1818 – 1883)
‹#›
7
Radical structuralism
Organisations are analysed as capitalist class relations (i.e. owner and labourer).
Organisations are portrayed in terms of:
Capitalist mode of production characterised by exploitation and alienation of the workers by the owners of the means of production.
Calls for worker emancipation, and for the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian organisation.
A critical organisational discourse emerges:
In the US:
C. Wright Mills (1956) The Power Elite
A. Gouldner (1954) Patterns of Industrial Bureaucracy
A. Gouldner (1955) Wildcat Strike
In the UK:
R. Dahrendorf (1959) Class and Class Conflict in an Industrial Society
‹#›
8
Organisations are portrayed as systems of oppression, rather than as systems of order.
Stories emerge of social divisions, power, exploitation, inequality and conflict within organisations.
Social classes in organisations are made visible.
Worker emancipation requires the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian form of organisation.
Radical structuralism
Systems of production?
Systems of oppression?
‹#›
9
Organisations are portrayed as systems of oppression, rather than as systems of order.
Stories emerge of social divisions, power, exploitation, inequality and conflict within organisations.
Social classes in organisations are made visible.
Worker emancipation requires the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian form of organisation.
Radical structuralism
Systems of production?
Systems of oppression?
Irreconcilable ideologies
“An idea is something you have; an ideology is something that has you.”
Morris Berman, historian
‹#›
10
Why should contemporary managers care?
Radical structuralism
“Capitalist organisations alienate and exploit workers” (Burawoy, 1979).
Critical theorists have shifted the image of management and the theoretical agenda “from saviour to problem” (Crowther & Green, 2004: 119).
Emergence of pejorative language in the description of organisations and management practices. A call for action. A threat to organisations’ legitimacy, and therefore their survival.
Organisations are embedded in a broader, political context. Pretending otherwise is “naïve realism” (Hirschheim & Klein, 1989).
And……
‹#›
11
The justification for radical structuralism
‹#›
12
If organisations do not recognise and address problems, they will be exposed in ways that threaten the viability of the organisation.
Social media has redistributed power, to an extent. But social structure is difficult to change.
‹#›
13
‹#›
14
‹#›
15
Let’s revisit functionalism, in light of the preceding…
Organisational ‘truths’ are only partially represented by functionalist tools and thinking, such as process models.
A ‘rational ideal’ that is guided only by a quest for efficiency is lacking in humanity, and is a fallacy, anyway.
The job of analysts is to unmask organisational ‘truths’ and facilitate the establishment of more democratic and egalitarian organisations, and the emancipation of workers.
‹#›
16
Organisations are portrayed as systems of oppression, rather than as systems of order.
Stories emerge of social divisions, power, exploitation, inequality and conflict within organisations.
Social classes in organisations are made visible.
Worker emancipation requires the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian form of organisation.
Systems of production?
Systems of oppression?
Irreconcilable ideologies
“An idea is something you have; an ideology is something that has you.”
Morris Berman, historian
How do analysts unmask organisational truths?
By looking for systemic organisational behaviours that perpetuate inequality and suffering (e.g. machine paced labour?)
By unveiling inequality regimes
By looking for organisational practices that are taken-for-granted but which disadvantage and oppress workers
By analysing the narratives that business and their supporters use to defend their practices and gain more freedom from regulation (discourse analysis)
By materialising the ideology guiding business and critiquing this ideology
By studying historical practices and drawing parallels between the past and present, to show that there are “immutable nature-like laws” in operation (Hirshheim & Klein, 1989: 1207)
‹#›
17
Unequal systems and resistance
How do workers redress the reduction in bargaining power or inequalities?
How is freedom from oppression and exploitation attained?
‹#›
Calls for emancipation: Workers as active agents within organisational relationships
Workers’ resistance to unequal power in the workplace:
Individual action:
Verbal complaints
Go-slows
‘Cheating’
Absenteeism
Looking for other work
Sabotage
Theft
Collective action / Worker coalition:
Strikes
Go-slows
‘Sick-out’
The formation of trade unions
‹#›
19
Seeks to reveal false assumptions about the world and uncover the truth, which will emancipate the oppressed.
Sees resistance and activism as positive, because it is a “sign of labor becoming aware of its collective interest, which in turn is a prerequisite for social progress” (Hirschheim & Klein, 1989: 1207).
BUT….
Radical structuralism: some strengths and cautions
‹#›
20
Organisations are portrayed as systems of oppression, rather than as systems of order.
Stories emerge of social divisions, power, exploitation, inequality and conflict within organisations.
Social classes in organisations are made visible.
Worker emancipation requires the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian form of organisation.
Systems of production?
Systems of oppression?
Irreconcilable ideologies
“An idea is something you have; an ideology is something that has you.”
Morris Berman, historian
How do we unmask organisational truths?
‹#›
21
Organisations are portrayed as systems of oppression, rather than as systems of order.
Stories emerge of social divisions, power, exploitation, inequality and conflict within organisations.
Social classes in organisations are made visible.
Worker emancipation requires the establishment of a more democratic and egalitarian form of organisation.
Systems of production?
Systems of oppression?
Irreconcilable ideologies
“An idea is something you have; an ideology is something that has you.”
Morris Berman, historian
How do we unmask organisational truths?
Whose version of reality is true?
Radical structuralism is not neutral
‹#›
22
Distorted version of truth
Distorted version of truth
If we believe that the truth about economic life and organisational behaviour can be objectively established, but we can only see our own distorted version, how can our views ever be reconciled?
How can this divide be overcome?
Should it be overcome, or will this simply perpetuate unjust arrangements?
‹#›
Radical structuralism: some strengths and cautions
Ignores the problems arising from coalition (e.g. conflict between workers; manipulation and exploitation of members; elevation of leaders into different “spheres”)
Radical structuralism “has a tendency to oversimplify” – are all organisations exploitative? Are there own two broad groups in economic life? (owners & workers)
Engages in trenchant criticism, promotes resistance, and thereby is poor at facilitating understanding and cooperation
‹#›
24
Why should contemporary managers care?
And what might be done?
Radical structuralism
Understand why people resist; understand the power of ideological differences.
Understand your own ideological views – does your ideology “have you”? (Reflexivity).
View organisations from multiple paradigms.
Look at organising processes critically, and from the perspective of the least powerful. Walk in their shoes.
Develop organising processes in collaboration with those who must live with them.
‹#›
25
We explored the roots of dissent and conflict affecting organisations
Dissent and conflict stems from the material conditions of people’s lives and different world-views (ideologies)
Managers must understand the roots of conflict
Some organisational problems are intractable
Be aware of economic decision making (policy) and organising processes that give rise to exploitation and oppression
Summary
‹#›
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Assumptions about our knowledge of society
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Order & regulation
Assumptions about society
Conflict & radical change
Radical structuralism
Social relativism
Neo-humanism
Functionalism
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions, four paradigms
Four radically different ways of seeing organisations
‹#›
27
RMIT University
Burrell & Morgan, 1979: Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Assumptions about our knowledge of society
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Order & regulation
Assumptions about society
Conflict & radical change
Social relativism
Neo-humanism
Functionalism
Multi-paradigmatic perception: two dimensions, four paradigms
Four radically different ways of seeing organisations
‹#›
28
References
Dahl, R. A. (1957). The concept of power. Behavioral science, 2(3), 201-215.
Freund, J. (1969). TheSociology of Max Weber.
Giddens, A. (1985). The nation-state and violence (Vol. 2). Univ of California Press.
Goffman, E. (1959). The presentation of self in everyday life.
Hamilton, P. (Ed.). (1991). Max Weber, Critical Assessments 2 (Vol. 2). Taylor & Francis.
Hatch, M. J., & Cunliffe, A. L. (2012). Organization theory: modern, symbolic and postmodern perspectives. Oxford university press.
Dahrendorf, R. (1959). Class and class conflict in industrial society. Stanford University Press.
Durkheim, E. (2014). The division of labor in society. Simon and Schuster.
Gouldner, A. W. (1954). Patterns of industrial bureaucracy.
Guba, E. G. (Ed.). (1990). The paradigm dialog. Sage Publications.
Mills, C. W. (1999). The power elite. Oxford University Press.
Guy, G. (2011). Language, social class and status. In R. Mesthrie (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of sociolinguistics (1st ed., Vol. 1, pp. 159–185
‹#›
“Good” news from
nowhere
:
imagining utopian sustainable
accounting
Jill Atkins
Henley Business School, University of Reading, Reading, UK
Barry Colin Atkins
Freelance Comic Script Writer, Brecon, UK
Ian Thomson
School of Management & Languages, Heriot-Watt University,
Edinburgh, UK, and
Warren Maroun
School of Accountancy, University of the Witwatersrand,
Johannesburg, South Africa
Abstract
Purpose – The purpose of this paper is to attempt to provide a ray of hope, in the form of a Morris-
style utopian dream of a sustainable world, as a basis for new forms of accounting and accountability
in contemporary society.
Design/methodology/approach – The method is four-fold, weaving together an auto-ethnographic
approach, a contextual dialogue between accounting academics and lobbyists, a Morris-inspired
utopian metaphor and a stakeholder accountability event in the form of oral disclosures written as a
song cycle.
Findings – Current efforts at integrated reporting are unlikely to change how large companies do
business in order to address the risk of climate change in the short term. If the UN reports on climate
change are correct, the authors need to take immediate action. The authors argue that, instead of waiting
for climatic disaster to lead to a paradigm shift in corporate practice, “monetisation” of the costs of climate
change is one way to encourage integrated thinking and sustainable business models. This relies on
existing finance and accounting discourse to create a new “field of environmental visibility” which
engenders environmental awareness on the part of the world’s companies and policy makers.
Practical implications – This utopian image may not appear a practicable, realistic solution to
current problems but represents a starting point for optimism. It provides inspiration for policy makers
to develop better forms of sustainability reporting, more suitable to the accelerating rates of climatic
change.
Originality/value – To the authors’ knowledge this is the first attempt to develop Morris’s News
From Nowhere as a basis for building new forms of accounting and accountability.
Keywords Engagement, Integrated reporting, Sustainability, Stakeholder, Morris, Utopia
Paper type Research paper
Preamble
In the social accounting literature, there have been many attempts to develop alternate
constructions of what has, today, become known as “sustainability reporting” (see, e.g.
Antheaume, 2004; Bebbington et al., 2001; Bent, 2007). There have also been a number of Accounting, Auditing &
Accountability Journal
Vol. 28 No. 5, 2015
pp. 651-
670
© Emerald Group Publishing Limited
0951-3574
DOI 10.1108/AAAJ-09-2013-1485
The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available on Emerald Insight at:
www.emeraldinsight.com/0951-3574.htm
The authors would like to thank Mrs Lelys Maddock for the editorial services and the partici-
pants at the International Corporate Governance (ICG) and Governance, Accountability and
Responsible Investment (GARI) conferences.
651
“Good” news
from
nowhere
reporting “experiments” attempted by various academics, practitioners, policy makers
and lobby groups. These include, for example, full cost accounting, triple-bottom-line
accounting and the idea of a comprehensive reporting framework (see Gray, 1994, 2002,
2010; Boone and Rubenstein, 1997; Gray and Milne 2003; Eccles and Krzus, 2010). Current
experiments with integrated reporting represent the most recent move towards a “new”
version of sustainability reporting where the social and environmental disclosures are
integrated into the annual report (Solomon and Maroun, 2012; International Integrated
Reporting Committee (IIRC), 2013; Solomon, 2013).
This paper acknowledges that, although these approaches may lead to improved
quality and quantity of sustainability disclosures, they do not (at present) satisfy the
needs of broad stakeholder groups (Barone et al., 2013; Jones and Solomon, 2013;
Carels et al., 2014). For many, both integrated and sustainability reporting fail to
discharge adequate accountability for damage to people and the Earth. As a result,
contemporary society is at the crossroads of significantly reforming corporate
governance and business practices or maintaining the status quo and facing the
possibly devastating consequences of climate change (Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change (IPCC), 2013).
Too often, the prior research provides an account of the significant reform to
corporate governance frameworks after modern capital and institutional systems are
beset by crises (e.g. see Canada et al., 2008; Integrated Reporting Committee of South
Africa (IRC), 2011; Malsch and Gendron, 2011). In this research, the intention is to offer
normative recommendations in an effort to stimulate change in existing business
practice and reporting. To do so, we use a Morris-style utopian image of a sustainable
world, “after the change has come” (see Hampton, 1990). We adapt William Morris’s
framework from News from Nowhere in order to build this image, concentrating on
some of the scenes involving a discussion between a visitor and her hosts in a futuristic
sustainable world. As this paper is not intended to be UK specific, no mention is made
of any specific place or person. The research also assumes a futuristic utopian
society – rather than a return to a rural Medieval society as described in Morris (1890) – in
order to appeal to contemporary readers.
William Morris wrote about and lectured widely on the problems of contemporary
society, focusing on a number of themes. Although Morris was faced with the evils
of industrialisation and concerned himself with the fate of the working classes,
he dealt extensively with the need to raise awareness of environmental accountability
(Solomon and Thomson, 2007). The themes present in his diverse writings include
aestheticism, a personal love of nature and reaction to environmental impact
of commercial activity. In his work he developed and articulated a Victorian
definition of “environmental accountability”, based on a duty of care and a call for
organisations to accept responsibility for their impact on the environment. Indeed,
Morris’s letters have been analysed to provide evidence of Victorian accounting for
biodiversity in the form of an early forest audit (Atkins and Thomson, 2014). One of
Morris’s seminal works was the novel News from Nowhere. This work represents
a dream-like journey forward in time to a utopian landscape.
In Morris’s utopian Britain, a Socialist revolution had taken place, leaving people
in a blissful communion with nature. Industry, so invasive in Victorian times, had
become a natural extension of a satisfied society where pollution had been eradicated.
We, however, are dominated by realism, being forced to see things “as they are”
(Hampton, 1990). This was similar to the situation in which Morris found himself in
Victorian Britain which was dominated by technological and industrial advances and
652
AAAJ
28,5
the obsession with shareholder value. This is not to say that imagining an ideal state
of governance and accountability is without purpose:
[…] for [Morris] it could never have been enough to be a realist. Realism on its own, in the
world as he knew it, could lead only to despair. One had to look beyond the present, to ‘the
change beyond the change’. And Morris saw it as his task to create a vision of reality […]
(Hampton, 1990, p. 53).
The method
The method adopted in this paper is four-fold. First, we adopt a type of auto-
ethnographic approach, in conjunction with a story-telling technique, to identify a
number of shortcomings in the integrated and sustainability reporting projects and
offer possibilities for change. Second, the context of the paper is created through
a dialogue between a group of accounting academics, environmentalists and other
lobbyists. Third, we use Morris’s utopian metaphor, describing, not necessarily a
socialist structure, but a futuristic society characterised by accountability, stakeholder
engagement, technological advance and environmental awareness. Fourth, the paper
presents a stakeholder accountability event in the form of an oral account of a day’s
events in the futuristic production processes, written in the form of a song cycle. Our
choice of a utopian method derives from the authors’ interest in this literary genre and
especially in the works of William Morris.
“Autoethnography” has been described as “[…] a genre of qualitative, reflexive,
autobiographical writing and research which uses the researcher as the subject” (Haynes,
2011, p. 135). This approach has been applied in the accounting literature (e.g. in Learmonth
and Humphreys, 2012). In writing this paper, we draw on the authors’ experiences with the
“storyteller” (the sustainability accountant) and song cycle representing a merging of our
autobiographies into one comprehensive, consolidated autobiography. Our song cycle,
the “accountability event”, draws on the skills and experiences of one of the authors as
a comic script writer, song writer (for a rock band) and creative writer in order to create
an imaginary, but hopefully useful, form of sustainability reporting and stakeholder
engagement.
A similar auto-ethnographic approach has been applied in accounting research in
a variety of ways. For example, Haynes (2006) developed an autobiographic methodology
drawing on her experiences of accounting academia and motherhood. She argues for the
use of autobiography as a methodological principle. She also emphasises that narrative is
an important aspect of identity construction within the cultural, social and political
practices of which it is a part. In this paper, we draw on our experiences as accounting
academics, as well as one of the author’s experiences as a script writer for radio and
television, in order to set the context for an exploratory narrative which seeks to create
a sustainable society with genuinely sustainable accounting. Further, accounting
research has experimented with imagination, myth and storytelling as a means of
exploring the meaning and uses of accounting in its broadest forms (Dillard and
Reynolds, 2008, 2011; Vickers, 2002). Similarly, our approach in this paper uses utopian
storytelling as a vehicle for imagining a sustainable and stakeholder-inclusive form of
accounting, based on a song cycle.
The utopian method has been used widely in literature as a device for creating a vision
of a different reality which may engender debate and lead to change. Even if the utopian
image created is not practically achievable in the short term, it provides inspiration
(Hampton, 1990; Solomon and Thomson, 2007). Indeed, utopian writings often seek to
provide an image of a better place which we can seek to attain but which may, given the
653
“Good” news
from
nowhere
present state of technology and society, be unobtainable. The term “utopia” derives from
the Greek language meaning “no place[1]”, although it is commonly used to mean “a place
or state of ideal perfection, especially with regard to laws, government, and social
conditions” (Longman, 1991). This meaning has probably arisen from More’s celebrated
work, Utopia, depicting an imaginary ideal country (More, 1516/2003). Utopian writings
create an account of a society which the writer considers to be in some way better than the
present. Sargent (1979) listed over 3,000 examples of British and American utopian
writing published since 1516. “Utopia” is interpreted as concerning, “[…] what should be
and how we ought to behave, rather than what is”. Utopia is “Nowhere, describing what is
desirable on the basis of speculative insight concerning the past and the future – the past
Nowhere and the future Nowhere” (Zadek, 1993, p. 37).
Utopias and utopianism tend to share certain characteristics. Levitas (2007) describes
them as imaginary reconstitutions of society, driven by the author’s realisation that
“things could be different” and how we “should” live. Utopias stem from discontent and a
subjective attempt to construct something more desirable (from the authors’ perspectives)
which is usually a radically different world (Sargisson, 2007, p. 41). Utopias can allow the
development of counter-narratives articulated with social movements and subaltern
groups (Everett, 2004; Cooper et al., 2005) similar to Everett’s (2004, p. 1079) observation in
relation to accounting that “the voices of those most affected by damaging corporate
activities” have too often been absent from social and environmental accounting. Utopian
accounts are also ways of “talking back”, exposing contradictions, destabilising the status
quo and addressing the silences and absences. In turn, they can be used for critical
reflection, highlighting social and political tensions and contradictions and encouraging
the emergence of new discourses to describe and “normalise” social arrangements.
In this context, the allegorical adaptation of Morris’s utopian world as depicted in News
from Nowhere adopts an auto-ethnographic approach, with recourse to autobiography,
based on the authors’ personal observations, professional publications and dialogue
among conference participants at the International Corporate Governance (ICG) and
Governance, Accountability and Responsible Investment (GARI)[2] Conferences collected
informally (Anderson, 2006; Venter and Villiers, 2013). We appreciate that this approach
is somewhat unconventional. This is in keeping with the normative tone of the paper.
The intention is not to provide a paper grounded heavily in existing theoretical
frameworks (Llewelyn, 2003). Similarly, we do not claim to provide a comprehensive
review of the prior literature or the integrated reporting project. Instead, we hope that the
utopian scene, described in the sections to follow, provides inspiration for academics and
practitioners to imagine and experiment with alternate routes for society’s future,
especially for sustainability reporting and stakeholder accountability, unconstrained by
existing preconceptions.
We are inspired by earlier work which asserts that “[…] stories ask that we see
differently, to be informed differently, engage our minds while stepping outside
accustomed patterns, allowing us to think anew” (Dillard and Reynolds, 2011, p. 493).
Similarly, Dillard and Reynolds (2008) uses storytelling and myth as a method for
developing a holistic model intended to lead to more balanced societal reporting. Our
utopian storytelling method intends to open a space for imagining a new form of
sustainability reporting presenting an accountability event as a song cycle. This is not
unknown in the accounting literature as imaginary dialogue – for example, between
Thought Woman, Green Owl and villagers in Dillard and Reynolds (2011) – produces
an emergent truth. Further, our retelling of News from Nowhere is partly inspired by
other work which recreates earlier stories, for example, the retelling of the Acoma Corn
654
AAAJ
28,5
Maiden in Dillard and Reynolds (2008). We now move to an adaptation of Morris’ News
from Nowhere in order to develop our utopian sustainable dream sequence.
“Good” News From Nowhere
On the brink of climatic disaster
The Sustainable Accountability Group met in a café on the river bank on a winter
night. It consisted of 20 academics and representatives from lobby groups such as
Friends of the Earth, Forum for the Future and Greenpeace. The group was reflecting
on the recently issued findings of the United Nations (UN) IPCC. One academic gave
a short summary of the UN’s report:
The IPCC tells us that human activity is the most likely cause of global warming
characterised by unprecedented environmental changes. Each of the last three decades has
been successively warmer. Over the last two decades, the Greenland and Antarctic ice sheets
have been losing mass and the world’s remaining glaciers continue to shrink. The rate of sea
level rises since the mid-19th century has been higher than the mean increase during the
previous two millennia. Atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide (CO2), methane, and
nitrous oxide have increased to levels unprecedented in at least the last 800,000 years. Forty
percent of this increase can be attributed to the relatively short period of human history
starting with the Industrial Revolution. Thirty percent of the emitted anthropogenic carbon
dioxide has been absorbed by the oceans, causing ocean acidification and massive loss
of marine life.
I do not think that it is a coincidence that most of these problems coincide with a growth in
human populations, and industrial activity. Limiting climate change will require substantial
and sustained reductions of greenhouse gas emissions. I said “limiting” because most of the
negative implications of climate change are inevitable. All that remains to be seen is the extent
of the disaster[3].
What the group found very interesting was the contradiction between the gloomy
outlook of the IPCC and optimistic tone of the annual reports of some of the world’s
most prominent companies (and largest emitters of greenhouse gases):
In general, companies are reporting environmental information but I am not convinced that
this is motivated by a genuine desire to protect the environment. I think that most of the
environmental, social and governance disclosures are window-dressing (said a PhD student).
This sparked a heated debate about how companies could be held more accountable for
their long-term environmental impact. Integrated reporting was discussed at length.
One of the more cynical academics complained:
The efforts of the South African and International Integrated Reporting Committees are a step
in the right direction, in theory. I’m convinced that this is going to become just another
box-ticking exercise which will lead to very little change in corporate mind-sets. Even if
companies do figure out how to produce high quality integrated reports, when you look at the
magnitude of the problems we’re facing, I think it’s too little too late.
An environmentalist agreed that what was needed was a more radical approach for
dealing with climate change:
It’s obvious that the current system is flawed. It’s constrained by the trappings of
industrialised society and the focus on companies, shareholders and profits in spite of the
calls for stakeholder engagement, sustainability and integrated thinking. In my opinion, we
need to go back to formula and rethink completely the role of companies in contemporary
655
“Good” news
from
nowhere
society. If needs be, we must get rid of them and completely reorganise the way we do things[4].
We need drastic change! Currently, all we have done is talk about the problem, to the extent
that most people have become apathetic. A decade of talking with little action has made
some wonder if environmental experts have been exaggerating. Those who do believe that
climate change is a serious threat feel that if governments can’t seem to agree on a plan of
action, they are not in a position to change things on a global level. In any event, most people are
too complacent to concern themselves with their day-to-day challenges. What we need is a
shakeup – a paradigm shift – something that gets people off of their arses!
Not everyone was convinced. One academic felt that:
The idea has some merit and it may make sense on paper but I am not sure if I would have the
guts to implement this. Getting rid of companies and reorganising the economy could lead to
complete chaos. The North Koreans are a good example of a failed “planned” economy. A
more constructive approach is needed and even then, what exactly would we be working
towards? If we eliminated companies and their profit-orientated business models what exactly
would we hope the world would look like after the fact?
Her colleague went on, but she was no longer listening […].
On the sincerity of integrated reporting
Social, environmental, ethical and governance disclosures have been gaining prominence
over the last four decades. This has gone hand-in-hand with the realisation that financial
information alone is insufficient to reach an informed decision on an organisation’s
ability to create and sustain value in the short-, medium- and long run (Solomon, 2010;
IRC, 2011). Sustainability reporting has, however, failed to draw a connection between
key financial and non-financial metrics, a shortcoming highlighted by the global financial
crisis commencing in 2007/2008. According to the International and South African
Integrated Reporting Committees, this weakness has been made all the more apparent by
a growing appreciation of the importance of social and environmental challenges being
faced by organisations (IIRC, 2011; IRC, 2011; IIRC, 2013).
In response, corporate reporting has purportedly begun the “journey towards more
integrated ways of thinking” (King, 2012) with an aim to providing stakeholders with
a “comprehensive picture” of an organisation’s performance (IRC, 2011, p. 1). In South
Africa, there is some evidence to suggest that annual reports are becoming more
“integrated” with a greater range of financial and non-financial information being
included in more sections of the reports (Solomon and Maroun, 2012; Carels et al., 2014).
In Europe there has also been some effort at integrating corporate disclosures with
the release of the Accounting for Sustainability (A4S) Connected Reporting Framework
(Solomon and Maroun, 2012), a process which is likely to be spurred on by the world’s
first framework for integrated reporting (IIRC, 2013).
The integrated reporting journey described by King (2012) has, however, started
off slowly. Both Solomon and Maroun (2012) and Carels et al. (2014) find a considerable
amount of repetition in the “integrated reports” and a persistent lack of integration
between financial and non-financial metrics, even by the largest companies[5]. There
may be some effort at more comprehensive disclosure, but these preliminary studies
confirm that there has been no internalisation of looming social and environmental
crises (see IPCC, 2013) in organisations’ risk assessment and business strategy:
Profits, returns on capital and the expectations of key institutional investors remain the
primary focus of the majority of preparers of these reports with scarcely a mention of climate
change, habitat destruction or growing labour unrest[6] (Retired institutional investor).
656
AAAJ
28,5
As discussed at the GARI Conference in September 2013, sustainability reporting has
been mobilised cleverly to conceal organisations’ motives which, in substance, have
changed little since the Industrial Revolution. Despite references to “stakeholders”, the
“trees and squirrels” and good governance, underlying capitalistic motives remain
the primary concern (GARI conference participant) with an inexorable pursuit of higher
profits (ICG conference participant) neatly decoupled from the image presented in the
“integrated report” (cf. Pesqueux, 2005). As explained by Solomon et al. (2013, p. 195), there
is a very real risk that formal reporting protocols and, by analogy, the integrated reporting
initiative, becomes an exercise in “staged impression management as a means of creating
and disseminating a dual myth of social and environmental accountability”. In other
words, the formal rational structure of the integrated report has, to paraphrase Meyer
and Rowan (1977), more to do with the presentation of a predetermined organisational
identity to secure legitimacy than with a radical change to organisational practice
(cf. Carruthers, 1995; Solomon et al., 2013). Consequently, the IPCC’s account of human
existence at risk due to dramatic climate change is juxtaposed with a slow migration to
“integrated reporting” (King, 2012; Carels et al., 2014) and business strategies which are
more about “paying lip service to environmental and social issues and mainly about
headline earnings per share” (GARI conference participant).
What is needed is a change in mindset where the possibilities of a sustainable world
are explored without the restrictions of existing political, economic and social
structures. Consequently, we now present a utopian dream sequence reflecting a shift
from the status quo to an imaginary society inspired by Morris’ dream sequence.
Through the wormhole
The stakeholder theorist felt suddenly suffocated. She decided to leave the now stuffy
café and take a walk along the bank before retiring for the evening. The air was cold
and damp. Gazing across the river, she could see only chimneys, cars, aeroplanes,
brightly lit offices and a swarm of intensely busy people. There was no indication of
anyone being evenly remotely concerned about the looming environmental catastrophe
detailed in the IPCC (2013). Eventually, she found her way to her apartment. Her paper
on biodiversity accounting was still on the study table. What was the point of finishing
it? She had even read in a newspaper that week that 40 per cent of the population
thought biodiversity was a type of washing powder! The last time she presented
her paper at a conference she had been criticised for not providing a definition
of “biodiversity” and was usually met by the blank or disbelieving expressions of
audiences when she discussed the potentially devastating consequences of climate
change. If even academics were not worried, why should CEO’s and politicians
prioritise environmental issues? She settled down at her desk. It seemed warm to the
touch and felt as if it were vibrating. She looked under the bench to see if she had left
the thermostat on. The last thing she remembered was thinking how hypocritical it was
to be lecturing corporate governance students about climate change when she could not
even remember to turn off the heater ….
It seemed Summer had arrived. The air was humid and the vegetation lush. The
busy city which, only a moment ago, dominated the view from the study window had
given way to enormous trees. Curious buildings integrated naturally with the green
landscape. The river was metamorphasised. The grey slurry had been replaced by deep
blue-green waters and instead of garbage barges, sleek hovercrafts were shuttling
passengers and goods. The roar of aeroplanes and a million cars was gone. Strange
zeppelin-like crafts drifted gracefully overhead. The sounds of bees and birds were
657
“Good” news
from
nowhere
broken by the occasional chatter of passers-by. A young man invited the academic
aboard one of the “river planes”. “Up the river, miss?” he asked kindly.
They pulled away from the landing. Where there was industry in 2014, there was
unusual architecture incorporating beautiful fauna so seamlessly that the buildings
seemed live. Their vehicle made no noise and emitted no fumes. It left the large fish
teeming in the waters completely undisturbed. She pointed to a large complex which
looked more like an enormous tree than a man-made structure. It reminded her of
Avatar. “That organism”, said the “ferryman”, “is a large habitat, grown in 2,270.
About 200 families live in it. It is almost completely self-sustaining. All of its energy is
produced using solar and photosynthesis cells and the integrated tree network recycles
water and eliminates most of the waste products”.
The visitor gulped in surprise at the date. The hovercraft captain kept talking,
presumably under the assumption that his visitor was a tourist from one of the Mars
Colonies. “On the right, you can see the Industrial Museum. Those tall round units used
to hold something called ‘petrol’ which they used to propel their wagons. My
grandfather told me that they never used virtual offices in the 2,000s and that most
people had separate ‘working’ and ‘living’ habitats. The tanks are empty. Crude oil ran
out decades ago. In any event, it’s illegal to burn fossil fuels” her guide informed her.
The birds roosting on the large petrochemical refinery in the middle of a marshland
paid them no attention as they glided past on the hovercraft.
“I suppose you are here for the talk by the Elders?” She nodded and asked: “How
much for the trip?” He laughed. “We don’t use the currency system. I suppose the
Outposts haven’t completed their software uploads. The robots determine the number
of passengers and calculate the fare automatically. The data is fed up to the Matrix”.
“And where do you get money for the rent?” she enquired. He looked at her, puzzled.
On the banks, the peculiar architecture continued. It was obvious that while this was
a highly technologically advanced society, there were fewer people than there had been
almost 300 years ago. Buildings and trees intermingled and vegetation seemed to be
a mix of agricultural plants and other fauna resembling what one would find in a
rainforest. At least the sheep had not changed.
The hovercraft finally arrived at its destination. Passengers disembarked. They did
not appear to be in the tube station rush that the academic was so accustomed to. She
followed the crowd, accompanied by the hovercraft captain, into an ancient building
which she realised was her university’s offices in the middle of the old city-centre. She
found a seat in what could be described as an auditorium except that the walls were a
type of transparent membrane which eliminated the need for man-made lighting.
In the centre of the auditorium, a small group of people took their positions around a
wooden table. The audience greeted the elders. The hovercraft captain explained: “At
the end of each month citizens come to listen to the stories of the grandparents. They
tell us about how things were and why they are as they are now”. Much to the
academic’s delight, one of the grandmothers began with a discussion on currency:
[…] old tradition of giving plastic tokens to pay for goods and services, not according to the
needs of the citizen but in proportion to the citizen’s standing in the community and citizen’s
desires. In most cases, these desires were limitless.
A grandfather went on:
About 300 years ago, the problem started. The world’s population had grown to almost 10
billion. For all of their industries and clever methods of production the nation states could not
658
AAAJ
28,5
feed and clothe their people. Civil unrest grew but cities refused to change. Countries
continued to consume more of the planet’s natural resources only realising the need for
change when it was too late.
Where there is hunger and despair there is also war and disease. Those who did not die in
the rioting when they evacuated the low-lying cities were lost during the Refugee Wars or the
famines that came afterwards. Terrible illnesses and uncontrolled violence left millions dead.
How did the change come?” queries an audience member.
A third elder explained:
The economies of the nation states were destroyed. The ancestors relied on large tribes of men
and their machines to produce all that they needed. These they called “companies”. There was
little concern for their impact on the planet. Citizens focused on amassing more currency than
they expended to produce goods. By the time it was realised that The Warming could not be
stopped, the methods of production and consumption could not be changed.
By now there were only a third of the people left alive. The work done by 10 had to be done by
one. There was no method of transportation. Too few were left to operate the fossil fuel
extraction units. Workers could not even be found to grow food and nothing was left to
salvage from the old cities. New ways had to be found to stay alive.
When order eventually came, the elected Elders decided to rely on new technologies to allocate
resources. The old currency system could not be allowed to re-emerge when rationing was ended.
And so, the Matrix was used to collect data from each citizen. Using algorithms, it determines
each citizen’s food, water and recreational requirements. This information is supplied to the
production centres. They produce what is needed when it is needed. There are no “shareholders”
or “institutional investors” demanding “profits”. Without this need to accumulate more than
expended for processes of production, it is easy to manage the interests of our Colony and
minimise our impact on the environment. Every member of the Colony is a member of the
production centres. Production centres are as accountable to citizens for the quality of life as
citizens are for the quality of their labours. The final result is that each citizen has what he
or she needs to survive and it is for this reason that we no longer die on our 60th name day.
Look at me – I have enjoyed 130 name days and am able to lead this Council with ease!
The congregation rose. One of the elders began singing and was soon joined by the rest
of the community:
We, who produce life’s necessities,
We, offering our liberal labour,
Come together to discuss our facilities,
Come together to meet our neighbour.
We who offer our services cheerfully,
We the purveyors of community needs,
Come together to discuss fully,
Come together to exchange ideas.
This verse was followed by an exchange between citizens from the food production
facility. A young woman rose and sang:
Early this morning, one of our fellows
Tripped and fell in excessive pain
His ankle broken, a colleague sought me
We carried him to our nursing station
The man is reposing in the healing chamber
And will take his rest until fully recovered.
659
“Good” news
from
nowhere
Others who had come to the assembly replied in song:
We, who care for our fellow workers
We, sisters and brothers here
Thank you for your song and verse
And call for any response or query.
A second citizen rose. The academic sat enthralled:
We also have a grave concern
The lake beside the meadow
Our colleagues were mixing herbs for treatments
And spilled a quantity into the water
As a result some fish were lost
We have cleaned the place and buried the fish.3.8pt?>
When she finished, a peer rose and asked:
Did you count the fish that were lost?
Will there still be ample fish for food.
A person who evidently worked in agriculture replied:
Yes, we counted fifty-five fish
Plenty remain for our community’s needs.
One of the elders from the facility then stood, singing:
Of the apprentices we’d like to tell
Our boys and girls, with trades to learn
Our guarantors of prosperity,
Being schooled in productivity,
Our master artisans report
Themselves best pleased with this intake.
A young woman rose, strangely attired, singing:
The delivery shuttles are doubled in number
From this time last year: our production grows,
We reach new space colonies; meet their needs,
But to power these routes we must enlist,
The old fuels to meet the shortfalls of our power cells.
Then another fellow rose, before the subject for discussion moved on:
One matter, my neighbours, I wish to raise
The maintenance crews are working full tilt.
And now some are starting their duties at six,
In manner, as if at the end of a shift.
I fear, their exhaustion may bring to pass,
An error that could cause a shuttle to crash.
Which brought this response. Clearly, this concern had previously been raised, and the matter
was duly in hand:
Thank you, dear brother, for raising this point.
It was mentioned before, you were absent, unwell.
660
AAAJ
28,5
I apologise now, for we did not cascade
This news to your bed, your fears to allay.
At the month’s end, when we all switch our tasks,
There’ll be more supervision and breaks in the shifts.
The elder explained that, at this point each day, there is an update on issues relating to climate,
atmospheric conditions and environmental impacts, clearly of grave concern following the
climate crisis:
A balance, my neighbours, must be sought
Between what we want and what we ought.
Our desires must take full into account
The impact they’d have on the land about.
Take this example, our children need homes,
Now the power of wind we’ve harnessed to drive
But building these houses eats land and trees,
So we must plan well and plan to sustain
Else the future may say, “What damned fools were these?”.
Then an elder explained, the lead singer repeats the opening “chorus” which signals the end of
the day’s disclosures and as soon as he had spoken, the following words were sung:
We, who produce life’s necessities,
We, offering our liberal labour,
Come together to discuss our facilities,
Come together to meet our neighbour.
We who offer our services cheerfully,
We the purveyors of community needs,
Come together to discuss fully,
Come together to exchange ideas.
What the academic had witnessed was a basic but, paradoxically, very advanced form
of stakeholder engagement and disclosure. She wandered away from the scene and
found a sunny spot under a tree, settling for a rest. Her thoughts began to wander and
she contemplated that “at home”, for all the technological developments, the software,
the complex systems of accounting and “accountability” we had lost the basic ability
to communicate in a transparent, genuine and open manner. We had lost the ability to
communicate real events in a “true and fair” way. She drifted in the warmth of the afternoon
and began to doze. When she awoke, her head was resting on her desk and she sat up
slowly to see the usual cold, dank, smoke-filled scene outside. Had those vivid scenes been
simply a dream? Although she knew she must have had a fascinating dream she pondered,
“if others can see it as I have seen it, then it may be called a vision rather than a dream”
(from Morris).
On the need for a paradigm shift in corporate reporting
Traditionally, accounting developments have been described as improvements which
reflect technological changes and resultant economic developments. Organisational
economy, efficiency and effectiveness can be improved by more refined accounting
systems but their essence is not altered by accounting (Watts and Zimmerman, 1983;
Hopwood, 1987). In positivist epistemological terms, accounting serves a rational
technical purpose only, providing financial information to enable the efficient allocation
of capital (Watts and Zimmerman, 1978; Carruthers, 1995; International Accounting
Standards Board (IASB), 2010).
661
“Good” news
from
nowhere
Critical theorists have, however, argued that accounting is more than just
a neutral mechanism for collecting and disseminating financial information
(Hopwood, 2000). This functional view of accounting overlooks how accounting
itself can lead to a dynamic for change and reform. Far from “inert”, it is a “fluent
and emerging craft” which both reflects and influences developments in
organisational governance and management and prevailing social and institutional
perspectives (Burchell et al., 1980; Hoskin and Macve, 1986; Hopwood, 1987;
Quattrone, 2004).
Hopwood (1987), for example, provides an account of the tedious development of
a costing system in a manufacturing environment faced with profitability concerns.
Although “infused by a rhetoric of economic and managerial rationality” (p. 210),
a closer examination of the new accounting system reveals how it engenders new
lines of economic visibility informing production, marketing and selling decisions
(cf. Miller and O’Leary, 1987; Cowton and Dopson, 2002). In this way, changes to
the accounting systems are partially the result of economic pressures but the
development and application of the system, in turn, has a significant impact on
the subsequent operation of the organisation. Whether as a result of, inter alia,
changes in organisational dynamics (Hopwood, 1987) sense of disciplinary power
(Mennicken and Miller, 2012) or the operation of a logic of resistance (Cowton and
Dopson, 2002), accounting and organisations are “dependent” on and “reflective” of
each other (Hopwood, 1987, p. 224) with the former able to communicate a particular
construction of organisational change and be an agent of change at the same
time. The same logic can be applied to social and environmental accounting and
reporting:
There is some evidence to suggest that sound social, environmental and governance
practices are becoming a societal imperative and linked closely with the legitimacy
of organisations. If you ask most investors, they will tell you that there is at least
an awareness of environmental and social concerns. I am not saying that these
are the most important considerations, but they are starting to feature in some of
the assessments that we do on current and prospective investments (Institutional
investor).
In other words, high quality integrated reporting would be an important means
of securing organisational credibility (IRC, 2011; Carels et al., 2014). For the
organisation prepared to invest in developing its reporting systems, there is an
opportunity to offer a meaningful and comprehensive review of its “total economic
cost” and benefit to stakeholders (ICG conference participant). This means that
integrated reporting protocols have the potential to make organisations more aware
of their actual impact on stakeholder groups and the environment and lead to a change
in business practices (King, 2012).
The problem is that the rate of this change may be inadequate to respond to
the risks posed by climate change. Indeed, the prior literature suggests that
most radical corporate governance developments have been in reaction to crises,
rather than the desire to introduce preventative measures (cf. Hopwood, 1987;
Canada et al., 2008; IRC, 2011; Malsch and Gendron, 2011). Participants at the
GARI and ICG Conferences reiterated this view, arguing that, even when
sincere efforts were being made to prepare high quality integrated reports, there
is lack of urgency. The financial reporting framework plays an important role
in this regard.
662
AAAJ
28,5
Presently, International Financial Reporting Standards (IFRS) do not permit
organisations to report the future costs of environmental degradation (IASB, 2010).
By the same token:
[…] there are no formalised means of accounting for loss of biodiversity and CO2
emissions. The only thing, in recent times, which dealt with the problem indirectly, was a
project on carbon trading […] And this was concerned with accounting for the financial
value of the carbon credits being traded, not with providing a comprehensive picture of
the total cost of operations to stakeholders to enable the accounting for loss of biodiversity
(Academic).
This problem is compounded by the fact that the majority of integrated reports fail to
make a strong connection between climate change, environmental management and
financial reporting (Solomon and Maroun, 2012; Carels et al., 2014). GARI and ICG
conference participants stressed that, with the effects of climate change (and associated
costs) not immediately apparent from financial statements and CEO reports, there is
little incentive for companies to alter their business practices. To paraphrase Hopwood
(2000): the accounting for climate change and loss of biodiversity is “out of touch with
the scientific evidence pointing to serious long-term problems” with the result that this
“field of visibility” is obscured and “corporates continue to behave in the same was
as they have for the last 50 years” (GARI participant):
I think that your [the researchers’] utopia sounds like a fantastic place. But I can tell you that
we don’t even have the smallest chance of getting there if all we are going to do is rely on the
King Code and Integrated Reporting. Significant changes require a revolutionary approach to
corporate reporting’ (Professional accountant and auditor).
Imagining a perfect socialist society free from want and in perfect harmony with the
natural world runs the risk of being accused of naivety. Contemporary society
remains dominated by large organisations and a culture of mass production and
consumption (IPCC, 2013). A global environmental disaster would probably result in
rapid change to modern business practice (GARI participant) but, in the absence of
such a catalyst, capitalistic pressures remain a stumbling block (Pesqueux, 2005).
Simply introducing a requirement to prepare integrated reports – without a dedicated
effort to encourage integrated thinking and environmentally friendly business
practice – is likely to amount to little more than a corporate disclosure compliance
exercise (GARI participant). One distinct failure identified within integrated and
sustainability reports is the absence of geographic and site-specific sustainability
disclosures. Examples of such disclosures are rare and focus on showcasing best
practice in occasional locations rather than attempting to provide a full picture
(Mahmud Khalid et al., 2013).
This is not to say that thinking about a futuristic ideal society is pointless.
It provides a frame of reference for highlighting current shortcomings in our corporate
governance paradigms and a basis for offering normative recommendations
(cf. Solomon and Thomson, 2007). Indeed, our cameo on News from Nowhere and the
extension of the utopian dream into a futuristic scenario resonates with Morris body
of writing, as it draws out his aestheticism, his personal love of nature and reaction to
environmental impacts of commercial activity. Our vision of a post-climatic crisis
and the ensuing shift to a sustainable society, we feel, picks up on Morris’ intended
utopian experiment.
663
“Good” news
from
nowhere
Based on the views of GARI and ICG conference participants, as well as the
perspective of the authors, a possible way forward is the “monetisation” of
environmental degradation. At this point, it should be stressed that the authors
are not lobbying for or against employing the existing capitalist framework to
provide meaningful integrated reporting and thinking. What we do acknowledge is
the dominance of finance and economic paradigms in organisations’ decision-
making processes (Pesqueux, 2005; Jones and Solomon, 2013). Rather than wait for
climatic disaster before there is a complete shift in business mind-set, existing
finance and accounting discourse can be mobilised to encourage truly sustainable
business practice in the short term, giving policy makers and academics the time to
explore alternate long-term strategies for tackling climate change and habitat loss.
Biodiversity reporting has recently been the focus of increased research activity (Atkins
et al., 2014). Cuckston (2013), for example, studies rain forest conservation efforts in Kenya.
He finds that using a “calculable good”, traded on over-the-counter carbon markets,
provides one means of including biodiversity measures in the financial reporting system.
Although a number of practical and theoretical difficulties are encountered (cf. Jones and
Solomon, 2013), bringing biodiversity conservation into the financial accounting
calculations of the world’s organisations’ at least “has the potential to alter radically
humankind’s economic relationships with the myriad of species that comprise Earth’s
global ecosystem” (p. 710). Similarly, Freeman and Groom (2013) argue that conventional
use of market-based discount rates (most often AA-rated corporate bonds) for valuing
provisions are inappropriate for measuring biodiversity or other environmentally sensitive
costs and benefits. By using an appropriately adjusted discount rate, “the full social
benefits of retaining a diverse biosphere” can be incorporated, to at least some extent, in the
financial analysis and decision-making process (p. 741).
In other words, providing a basis of accounting for the effects of climate change and
loss of biodiversity by organisations is one means of highlighting the costs (in a broad
sense) of industrial activity and promoting change (Retired institutional investor):
The initial accounting and the allocation of costs would probably be quite crude and appear
very subjective but it would, at least, be a starting point for quantifying the social and
environmental effects which companies are having. It would also provide an initial framework
for truly integrated financial and non-financial measures (Professional accountant).
And I think that that is important because companies think in terms of the numbers. For the
large pension funds, it’s about generating a capital return. We do try to take the “soft issues”
into account but, at the end of the day, it’s a numbers game (Investor).
These sentiments were shared by participants at the GARI and ICG conferences.
As discussed above, the integrated reporting project has not resulted in the change
in mind-set apparent in our utopian vision of a future Earth. Relying on existing
accounting and finance discourse to quantify the full costs and benefits of
contemporary organisations is one way to address this. Even if the initial techniques
are imperfect, having a “crude measure” of the cost of – for instance – biodiversity loss in
the agriculture sector of the global economy, it is better than assuming that the cost is
zero (cf. Cuckston, 2013; Siddiqui, 2013). As one preparer of financial statements also
pointed out:
When we first started with accounting for environmental provisions in the mining industry,
people complained that it was too subjective. But the conclusion was that we needed to make
an estimate of the cost of restoring the site, even if the estimate is not perfect. Today, there is
664
AAAJ
28,5
still a lot of subjectivity in the accounting but environmental rehabilitation provisions are
commonplace. I suspect that some measure of biodiversity costing will be the same. You’ve
got to start somewhere and, with a bit of time and effort, you will probably end up with
a measure that is not perfect but which at least draws your attention to the impact of your
business activities.
The aim of this paper is not to advance a particular method for computing and
reporting the costs of biodiversity loss and CO2 emissions. We do, however, call for a
concerted effort at including some measure of cost in annual reports. This may not
require an immediate revision to IFRS. Statements of social profits, adjusting IFRS
amounts for biodiversity costs and benefits could provide an excellent initial effort at
integrating financial and non-financial information in integrated reports (GARI
participant). A type of balanced-score card which prioritises environmental issues and
attaches a measure of cost and benefit to each performance area could also provide
useful information to stakeholders (GARI participant). Each of these offers a relatively
quick approach for tackling the issue of climate change without having to wait for
a catastrophe to provide a change impetus to contemporary business practice. The
exact means of “quantifying” the cost of climate change and biodiversity loss to be
included in these reports is, at this point, uncertain. What is, however, clear is that:
Through its intertwining with the discursive notions of accountability and responsibility,
accounting can play a role in the reconstitution of organisational agents, enabling different
configurations of organisational arrangements to exist (Hopwood, 1987, p. 229).
Concluding remarks
It is quite clear that the world is facing climatic disaster. If the UN’s reports are correct,
all organisations must make far greater strides in managing climate change risks
and dramatically reducing their carbon footprints. This is especially true for larger
organisations operating in different jurisdictions and enjoying the technological
expertise and resources to address serious social and environmental practices. Rather
than wait for the effects of climate change to be realised fully, new forms of accounting
and accountability have a role to play in altering business behaviour.
It is our view that annual disclosure of social and environmental impacts, associated
risks and risk-management in sustainability and integrated reports is inadequate.
Despite the efforts of the IRC and IIRC, these forms of annual reports suffer from
excessive repetition and a lack of integration between financial and non-financial
metrics. Rather than being drivers of change, they are at risk of becoming yet another
example of a legalistic exercise in corporate disclosure and image management.
We have suggested that a possible way forward is to rely on the prevalence of
finance paradigms at the heart of contemporary businesses. By monetising the costs
of climate change for organisations, accounting and finance discourse can be
successfully mobilised to address significant environmental risks by creating new
“fields of visibility” for boards of directors. Even if existing methods are crude,
a technique for adjusting IFRS-based profits to reflect the costs of, for example,
biodiversity loss and CO2 emissions, can provide a change impetus and lay the
foundation for a truly integrated framework for managing businesses and reporting to
stakeholders. In the medium- to long-run, the notion of oral daily disclosures at the
local, geographic segmental level – as described in this “dream sequence” – should also
be explored by academics and practitioners looking for innovative techniques for
665
“Good” news
from
nowhere
enhanced sustainability accounting and stewardship. For example, starting with
face-to-face oral communication, information could be disseminated through a web
of electronic global communication ensuring that interested parties could access
local, site-specific information on a daily basis. To this end, rather than focusing on
“traditional” research grounded in finance or social science paradigms, normative
“explorations” of alternate mechanisms of accountability and governance are needed
where imagination and creativity are unrestricted by pre-existing conceptions of the
role of accounting. In this context, it is our hope that the imaginings of this cameo paper
provide inspiration for practical change in sustainability reporting.
Notes
1. ‘Utopia from Greek, ou ¼ not, no + topos, place (Longman, 1991).
2. The ICG Conference was held in Johannesburg, South Africa during October 2012. The GARI
Conference took place in Henley on Themes, UK in September 2013.
3. This is taken from the IPCC (2013 and 2007) report.
4. This paper (Bevan and Spence, 2007) was presented at a conference of the British Academy
of Management Special Interest Group in Corporate Social Responsibility, York, April.
5. The authors concentrated on the South African situation because South Africa was the first
country to call explicitly for integrated reporting in its codes on corporate governance,
backed by a requirement from its stock exchange to prepare an integrated report or justify
the reasons for failing to do so (Solomon and Maroun, 2012).
6. The respondent is referring the on-going unrest in the South African mining industry and the
implications which this has for other sectors of the economy.
References
Anderson, L. (2006), “Analytic autoethnography”, Journal of Contemporary Ethnography, Vol. 35
No. 4, pp. 373-3955.
Antheaume, N. (2004), “Valuing internal costs – from theory to practice: implications for
full cost environmental accounting”, European Accounting Review, Vol. 13 No. 3,
pp. 443-464.
Atkins, J. and Thomson, I. (2014), “Accounting for nature in 19th century Britain: William Morris
and the defence of the fairness of the earth”, in Jones, M. (Ed.), Accounting for Biodiversity,
Routledge, London.
Atkins, J., Gräbsch, C. and Jones, M.J. (2014), “Biodiversity reporting: exploring its
anthropocentric nature”, in Jones, M. (Ed.), Accounting for Biodiversity, Routledge,
Abingdon, Oxon, pp. 215-245.
Barone, E., Ranamagar, N. and Solomon, J.F. (2013), “A Habermasian model of stakeholder (non)
engagement and corporate (ir)responsibility reporting”, Accounting Forum, Vol. 37 No. 3,
pp. 163-181.
Bebbington, J., Gray, R., Hibbitt, C. and Kirk, E. (2001), Full Cost Accounting: An Agenda for
Action, ACCA, London.
Bent, D. (2007), “Towards a monetised triple bottom line for an alcohol producer”, Using
Stakeholder Dialogue to Negotiate a ‘Licence to Operate’ by Constructing an Account of
Social Performance, Sustainability, Accounting and Reporting, Vol. 21, pp. 61-82.
Boone, C. and Rubenstein, D.B. (1997), “Natural solution: full cost accounting can help companies
to integrate environmental considerations into decision making”, CA Magazine, Vol. 130
No. 4, pp. 18-22.
666
AAAJ
28,5
Burchell, S., Clubb, C., Hopwood, A., Hughes, J. and Nahapiet, J. (1980), “The roles of accounting in
organizations and society”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 5 No. 1,
pp. 5-27.
Canada, J., Kuhn, J.R. and Sutton, S.G. (2008), “Accidentally in the public interest: the perfect
storm that yielded the Sarbanes-Oxley Act”, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, Vol. 19
No. 7, pp. 987-1003.
Carels, C., Maroun, W. and Padia, N. (2014), “Integrated reporting in the South African mining
sector”, Corporate Ownership and Control, Vol. 11 No. 1, pp. 991-1005.
Carruthers, B.G. (1995), “Accounting, ambiguity, and the new institutionalism”, Accounting,
Organizations and Society, Vol. 20 No. 4, pp. 313-328.
Cooper, C., Taylor, P., Smith, N. and Catchpowle, L. (2005), “A discussion of the political
potential of social accounting”, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, Vol. 16 No. 7,
pp. 951-974.
Cowton, C.J. and Dopson, S. (2002), “Foucault’s prison? Management control in an automotive
distributor”, Management Accounting Research, Vol. 13 No. 2, pp. 191-213.
Cuckston, T. (2013), “Bringing tropical forest biodiversity conservation into financial
accounting calculation”, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 26 No. 5,
pp. 688-714.
Dillard, J. and Reynolds, M. (2008), “Green Owl and the Corn Maiden”, Accounting, Auditing &
Accountability Journal, Vol. 21 No. 4, pp. 556-579.
Dillard, J. and Reynolds, M. (2011), “Re-stor(y)ing social change”, Critical Perspectives on
Accounting, Vol. 22 No. 5, pp. 492-499.
Eccles, R.G. and Krzus, M.P. (2010), One Report: Integrated Reporting for a Sustainable Strategy,
John Wiley & Sons Inc., Hoboken, NJ.
Everett, J. (2004), “Exploring (false) dualisms for environmental accounting praxis”, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, Vol. 15 No. 8, pp. 1061-1084.
Freeman, M.C. and Groom, B. (2013), “Biodiversity valuation and the discount rate problem”,
Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 26 No. 5, pp. 715-745.
Gray, R. (1994), “Corporate reporting for sustainable development: accounting for sustainability
in 2000 AD”, Environmental Values, Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 17-45.
Gray, R. (2002), “The social accounting project and accounting, organisations and society:
privileging engagement, imaginings, new accountings and pragmatism over critique?”,
Accounting, Organisations and Society, Vol. 27 No. 7, pp. 687-708.
Gray, R. (2010), “Is accounting for sustainability actually accounting for sustainability […]. And
how would we know? An exploration of narratives of organisations and the planet”,
Accounting, Organisations and Society, Vol. 35 No. 1, pp. 47-62.
Gray, R. and Milne, M. (2003), “Towards reporting on the TBL: mirages, methods and
myths”, in Henriques, A. and Richardson, J. (Eds), The Triple Bottom Line, Does
it All Add Up?: Assessing the Sustainability of Business and CSR, Earthscan, London,
pp. 70-81.
Hampton, C. (1990), “The feast’s beginning: news from nowhere and the utopian tradition”,
in Coleman, S. and O’Sullivan, P. (Eds), William Morris & News From Nowhere: A Vision of
our Time, Green Books, Devon, pp. 43-76.
Haynes, K. (2006), “Linking narrative and identity construction: using autobiography in
accounting research”, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, Vol. 17 No. 4, pp. 399-418.
Haynes, K. (2011), “Tensions in (re)presenting the self in reflexive autoethnographical research”,
Qualitative Research in Organizations and Management, Vol. 6 No. 2, pp. 134-149.
667
“Good” news
from
nowhere
Hopwood, A.G. (1987), “The archaeology of accounting systems”, Accounting, Organizations and
Society, Vol. 12 No. 3, pp. 207-234.
Hopwood, A.G. (2000), “Understanding financial accounting practice”, Accounting, Organizations
and Society, Vol. 25 No. 8, pp. 763-766.
Hoskin, K.W. and Macve, R.H. (1986), “Accounting and the examination: a genealogy of
disciplinary power”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 11 No. 2, pp. 105-136.
Integrated Reporting Committee of South Africa (IRC) (2011), “Framework for integrated
reporting and the integrated report”, available at: www.sustainabilitysa.org (accessed
5 June 2012).
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2007), “Climate change 2007: impact,
adaptation and vulnerability”, available at: ipcc.ch/pdf/assessment-report/ar4/wg2/
ar4_wg2_full_report (accessed 1 June 2015).
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2013), “Climate change 2013: the physical
science basis”, available at: www.ipcc.ch/report/ar5/wg1/ (accessed 1 June 2015).
International Accounting Standards Board (IASB) (2010), The Conceptual Framework for
Financial Reporting, LexisNexus (International Accounting Standards Committee
Foundation Publications Department), Pietermaritzburg.
International Integrated Reporting Committee (IIRC) (2011), “Towards integrated reporting:
communicating value in the 21st century”, available at: http://theiirc.org/wp-content/
uploads/2012/06/Discussion-Paper-Summary1 (accessed 5 June 2012).
International Integrated Reporting Committee (IIRC) (2013), “The international framework:
integrated reporting”, available at: www.theiirc.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/13-12-08-
THE-INTERNATIONAL-IR-FRAMEWORK-2-1 (accessed 1 October 2013).
Jones, M.J. and Solomon, J.F. (2013), “Problematising accounting for biodiversity”, Accounting,
Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 26 No. 5, pp. 668-687.
King, M.E. (2012), “Comments on: integrated reporting and the integrated report. Public lecture”,
International Corporate Governance Conference, Johannesburg, 23 October.
Learmonth, M. and Humphreys, C. (2012), “Autoethnography and academic identity; glimpsing
business school doppelgangers”, Organizations, Vol. 19 No. 1, pp. 99-117.
Levitas, R. (2007), “The imaginary reconstitution of society. Utopia as a method”, in Moylan, T.
and Baccolini, R. (Eds), Utopian Dream Vision. The Use Value of Social Dreaming,
International Academic Publishers, Bern, pp. 47-69.
Llewelyn, S. (2003), “What counts as “theory” om qualitative management and accounting
research?”, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 16 No. 4, pp. 662-708.
Longman (1991) Longman Dictionary of the English Language, Longman Group UK Ltd, Essex.
Mahmud Khalid, S., Atkins, J. and Hennell, A. (2013), “Site-specific and geographical
segmental social, environmental and ethical disclosures by the mining sector”,
paper presented at the Financial Reporting and Business Communications Conference,
Bristol, 3 July.
Malsch, B. and Gendron, Y. (2011), “Reining in auditors: on the dynamics of power surrounding
an ‘innovation’ in the regulatory space”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 36
No. 7, pp. 456-476.
Mennicken, A. and Miller, P. (2012), “Accounting, territorialization and power”, Foucault Studies,
Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 4-24.
Meyer, J.W. and Rowan, B. (1977), “Institutionalized organizations: formal structure as myth and
ceremony”, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 83 No. 2, pp. 340-363.
668
AAAJ
28,5
www.sustainabilitysa.org
ipcc.ch/pdf/assessment-report/ar4/wg2/ar4_wg2_full_report
ipcc.ch/pdf/assessment-report/ar4/wg2/ar4_wg2_full_report
www.ipcc.ch/report/ar5/wg1/
http://theiirc.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/06/Discussion-Paper-Summary1
http://theiirc.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/06/Discussion-Paper-Summary1
www.theiirc.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/13-12-08-THE-INTERNATIONAL-IR-FRAMEWORK-2-1
www.theiirc.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/13-12-08-THE-INTERNATIONAL-IR-FRAMEWORK-2-1
Miller, P. and O’Leary, T. (1987), “Accounting and the construction of the governable person”,
Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 12 No. 3, pp. 235-265.
More, T. (1516/2003), Thomas More’s Utopia, Penguin Classics, London, reprinted.
Morris, W. (1890), “News From Nowhere” , Reprinted in The Collected Works of William Morris),
Vol. XVI, Longmans Green and Company, Cambridge University Press, London,
pp. 373-395.
Pesqueux, Y. (2005), “Corporate governance and accounting systems: a critical perspective”,
Critical Perspectives on Accounting, Vol. 16 No. 6, pp. 797-823.
Quattrone, P. (2004), “Accounting for god: accounting and accountability practices in the society
of Jesus (Italy, XVI-XVII centuries)”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 29 No. 7,
pp. 647-683.
Sargent, L.T. (1979), British and American Utopian Literature, Garland Publishing, G. K. Hall,
Boston, MA.
Sargisson, L. (2007), “The curious relationship between politics and utopia”, in Moylan, T. and
Baccolini, R. (Eds), Utopian Dream Vision. The Use Value of Social Dreaming, International
Academic Publishers, Bern, pp. 25-47.
Sharp, D. (2005), The Thames Path, Aurum Press, London.
Siddiqui, J. (2013), “Mainstreaming biodiversity accounting: potential implications for a
developing economy”, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 26 No. 5,
pp. 779-805.
Solomon, J. (2010), Corporate Governance and Accountability, 3rd ed., John Wiley and Sons Ltd,
West Susex.
Solomon, J. and Maroun, W. (2012), Integrated Reporting: The New Face of Social, Ethical and
Environmental Reporting in South Africa?, The Association of Chartered Certified
Accountants (ACCA), London.
Solomon, J.F. and Maroun, W. (2012), “Integrated reporting: the influence of King III on social,
ethical and environmental reporting”, research report, ACCA, London, August.
Solomon, J.F. and Thomson, I. (2007), “Calling the ‘stink-and-pest breeders’ to account: William
Morris’ role in sowing the seeds of environmental accountability”, paper presented
at the British Accounting Association Annual Conference, Royal Holloway,
London, 7 April.
Solomon, J.F., Solomon, A., Joseph, N.L. and Norton, S.D. (2013), “Impression management,
myth creation and fabrication in private social and environmental reporting: insights
from Erving Goffman”, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 38 No. 3,
pp. 195-213.
Venter, E.R. and Villiers, C.D. (2013), “The accounting profession’s influence on academe: South
African evidence”, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, Vol. 26 No. 8,
pp. 1246-1278.
Vickers, M.H. (2002), “Researchers as storytellers: writing on the edge – without a safety net”,
Qualitative Inquiry, Vol. 8 No. 5, pp. 608-621.
Watts, R.L. and Zimmerman, J.L. (1978), “Towards a positive theory of the determination of
accounting standards”, The Accounting Review, Vol. 53 No. 1, pp. 112-134.
Watts, R.L. and Zimmerman, J.L. (1983), “Agency problems, auditing, and the theory of the firm:
some evidence”, Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 26 No. 3, pp. 613-633.
Zadek, S. (1993), “An economics of Utopia: democratising scarcity”, in Zadek, S. (2004)(Ed.),
Tomorrow’s History: Selected Writings of Simon Zadek 1993-2003, Greenleaf Publishing
Ltd, Sheffield.
669
“Good” news
from
nowhere
Further reading
Baccolini, R. (Ed.) (2007), Utopian Dream Vision. The Use Value of Social Dreaming, International
Academic Publishers, Bern.
Bent, D. and Richardson, J. (2003), “The Sigma guidelines – sustainability accounting guide”,
available at:www.projectsigma.co.uk/toolkit/sigmasustainabilityaccounting (accessed
1 June 2012).
Gray, R. (1992), “Accounting and environmentalism: an exploration of the challenge of gently
accounting for accountability, transparency and sustainability”, Accounting,
Organisations and Society, Vol. 17 No. 5, pp. 399-425.
Gray, R., Bebbington, J. and Walters, D. (1993), Accounting for the Environment, Paul Chapman,
London.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2013), “Climate change 2013: the physical
science basis”, IPCC.
Corresponding author
Professor Jill Atkins can be contacted at: J.F.atkins@henley.ac.uk
For instructions on how to order reprints of this article, please visit our website:
www.emeraldgrouppublishing.com/licensing/reprints.htm
Or contact us for further details: permissions@emeraldinsight.com
670
AAAJ
28,5
www.projectsigma.co.uk/toolkit/sigmasustainabilityaccounting
mailto:J.F.atkins@henley.ac.uk
Sociological Paradigms
and Organisational
Analysis
Elcmellls of the So(‘iolo~-:y of Corporate Life
Gibson Burrell
Lecturer in the Department of Behaviour in Organisations,
University of Lancaster, England
Gareth Morgan
Associate Professor of Organisational Behaviour and
Industrial Relations, York University, Toronto
First published 1979 by Heinemann Educational Books
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Burrell, Gibson
Sociological paradigms and organisational
analysis : elements of the sociology of corporate
life.
I. Organisation
I. Title II. Morgan. Gareth
302.3’5 HM131
Copyright © 1979 Gibson Burrell and Gareth Morgan
Published 2016 by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group,
an informa business
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced
any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means,
now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording,
or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission
in writing from the publishers.
Notice:
Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks,
and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
or utilised in
ISBN 9780566051487 (hbk)
ISBN 9781857421149 (pbk)
Publisher’s Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this book
but points out that some imperfections from the original may be apparent.
Contents
List of Figures
List of Tables
Acknowledgements
Introduction
PART I: IN SEARCH OF A FRAMEWORK
1 Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science
The Strands of Debate
Analy.sing Assumptions about the Nature of Social
Sci.ence
2 Assumptions about the Nature ol Society
The Order-Conflict Debate
•Regulation· and ·Radical Change•
3 Two Dimensions: Four Paradigms
The Nature and Uses of the Four Paradigms
The Functionalist Paradigm
The Interpretive Paradigm
The Radical Humanist Paradigm
The Radical Structuralist Paradigm
Exploring Social Theory
PART II: THE PARADIGMS EXPLORED
4 Functionalist Sociology
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The Structure of the Paradigm
Social System Theory
Interactionism and Social Action Theory
Integrative Theory
Objectivism
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
5 Functionalist Organisation Theory
Theories of Organisation within the Functionalist
Paradigm
Social System Theory and Objectivism
Theories of Bureaucratic Dysfunctions
page
v
v
vi
viii
1
4
7
10
10
16
21
23
25
28
32
33
35
41
41
48
49
68
87
102
106
118
121
123
184
iv Contents
The Action Frame of Reference 189
Pluralist Theory 202
Debate within the Functionalist Paradigm 217
6 Interpretive Sociology 227
Origins and Intellectual Tradition 227
The Structure of the Paradigm 234
Hermeneutics 235
Solipsism 238
Phenomenology 240
Phenomenological Sociology 247
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm 253
7 111e Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of
Organisations 260
Ethnomethodological Approaches to the Study of
Organisational Activities 261
Phenomenological Symbolic lnteractionism and the
Study of Organisational Activities 270
The Phenomenological Challenge to Contemporary
Organisation Theory 273
Phenomenological Approaches to the Study of
Organisational Situations: Problems and Dilemmas 275
8 Radical Humanism 279
Origins and Intellectual Tradition 279
The Structure of the Paradigm 282
Critical Theory 283
Anarchistic Individualism 299
French Existentialism 302
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm 306
9 Anti-Organisation 111eory 310
Towards Alternative Realities 313
Towards an Anti-Organisation Theory 319
10 Radical Structuralism 326
Origins and Intellectual Tradition 326
The Structure of the Paradigm 333
Russian Social Theory 334
Contemporary Mediterranean Marxism 341
Conflict Theory 349
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm 357
II Radical Organisation 111eory 365
Radical Weberian Approaches to a Radical
Organisation Theory 371
Marxian Structuralist Approaches to a Radical
Organisation Theory 3n
Contents v
Towards the Further Development of Radical
Organisation Theory 385
PART III: CONCLUSIONS
1l Future Directions: Theory and Research 395
Bibliography 403
Index 427
List of Figures
pa~te
1.1 A scheme for analysing assumptions about the nature
of social science 3
3.1 Four paradigms for the analysis of social theory 22
3.2 Intellectual influences upon the functionalist paradigm 27
3.3 The four sociological paradigms 29
3.4 The main schools of organisational analysis 30
4.1 Some possible types of system models 67
5.1 Functionalist approaches to the study of organisations 121
5.2 The development of social system theory and objectivism 124
5.3 Scheme for interpreting complaints and reduced work
effectiveness 135
5.4 Scheme for interpreting complaints involving soci~ inter-
relationships of employees 137
5.5 A contingency model for organisational analysis 177
List of Tables
2.1 Two theories of society: ‘order· and ‘conflict’
2.2 The regulation- radical change dimension
5.1 The unitary and pluralist views of interests, conflict and
power
8. I Critical theory: central concepts and orientations
9.1 Key dimensions of alternative realities
9.2 Towards the definition of anti-organisation theory
II. 1 The unity of the radical structuralist attack upon organi-
sation theory
11.2 Some differences in emphasis between Marxian struc-
turalist and radical Weberian approaches to radical
organisation theory
11.3 The radical Weberian view of interests, conflict and
power
pa~te
13
18
204
298-9
318
322-3
366-7
385
388
Acknowledgements
We have worked on this book at a pace which has varied from the
intense to the intolerable, and as a consequence we have asked and
received a great deal of our families and friends. We owe to them
all a great debt of thanks. In particular we wish to thank Christine
Burrell for her considerable patience, help and encouragement,
which were stretched up to and sometimes beyond the limits. Our
work owes much to our colleagues and students at Lancaster,
particularly those in the Department of Behaviour in
Organisations, where the stimulating and convivial combination of
critical enquiry, friendship and debate has been a major feature of
our enterprise.
The ideas expressed in the book are the product of extensive
discussion and as such are to be seen as shared. However, the
responsibility for the production of the manuscript in its present
form has fallen largely upon Gareth Morgan, who has undertaken
the task of converting early drafts into a finished text and of
imposing stylistic unity on the work as a whole. Needless to say, in
the spirit of our endeavour, responsibility, credit and blame are
jointly assumed.
Thanks are due to Jean Atkinson, Janet Fisher, Joy Howson,
Sue Lawrence and Lynne Rymarz for typing various sections of
the manuscript. The assistance of the Social Science Research
Council, in sponsoring field research which contributed to many of
the ideas presented here, is gratefully acknowledged.
Gibson Burrell would like to register his gratitude to his mother
and family, especially to Christine who, while the book was being
written, carried twins in and ex utero while he merely carried
books in and ex libris.
Gareth Morgan wishes to extend special thanks and
appreciation to his parents, ldris and Rachel Morgan, for all that
they have given.
We also wish to thank the following publishers for permission
to reproduce extracts from their books on the pages indicated:
Harvard University Press: F.J. Roethlisberger and W.J.
Dickson, Management and the Worker (1939), on pp. 134,
136-7. 137-8. and Figs. 5.3 and 5.4 on pp. 135 and 137.
Houghton Mifflin Company: A. Rose. Human Behavior and
Social Processes (1962). on pp. 79-80.
John Wiley & Sons. Inc.: P.M. Blau. Exchange and Power in
Social Life (1964). on pp. 89, 90.
Merlin Press Ltd.: P. Thevenaz, What is Phenomenology?
(1962), on p. 241.
Methuen and Co Ltd.: Jean-Paul Sartre,Being and Nothingness
(1966). on p. 305.
Penguin Books Ltd.: Steven Lukes, Emile Durkheim: His Life
and Work: A Historical and Critical Study (1973), on pp.
45-6.
Prentice-Hall, Inc.: L.A. Coser, Georg Simmel (1965), on pp.
70, 71, 72.
Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd.: John Rex, Key Problems in
Sociological Theory (1961), on pp. 353-4.
University of Chicago Press: H. Blumer. The Sociological
Implications of the Thought ofG.H. Mead (1966). on pp. 78,
81.
Gibson Burrell, Gareth Morgan
Lancaster, December 1978
Introduction
This book, which has devoured the last two years of our lives, is
the product of a friendship and intellectual partnership. It began as
an innocuous idea which grew with such strength that it developed
into a ·way of seeing’. It has changed the ways in which we think
about social theory, and we hope that it will do the same for others.
The book is intended to clarify and help overcome what seem to
be some of the major sources of confusion within the social
sciences at the present time. Initially it had a fairly specific objec-
tive: to attempt to relate theories of organisation to their wider
sociological context. In the course of development, however, this
endeavour widened in scope and evolved into an enterprise
embracing many aspects of philosophy and social theory in gen-
eral. As such it now stands as a discourse in social theory of
relevance to many social science disciplines, of which those in the
general area of organisation studies – industrial sociology, organ-
isation theory, organisational psychology and industrial relations
– are but special cases by which we illustrate our general themes.
Our proposition is that social theory can usefully be conceived in
terms of four key paradigms based upon different sets of
metatheoretical assumptions about the nature of social science and
the nature of society. The four paradigms are founded upon mutu-
ally exclusive views of the social world. Each stands in its own
right and generates its own distinctive analyses of social life. With
regard to the study of organisations, for example, each paradigm
generates theories and perspectives which are in fundamental
opposition to those generated in other paradigms.
Such an analysis of social theory brings us face to face with the
nature of the assumptions which underwrite different approaches
to social science. It cuts through the surface detail which dresses
many social theories to what is fundamental in determining the
way in which we see the world which we are purporting to analyse.
It stresses the crucial role played by the scientist’s frame of refer-
ence in the generation of social theory and research.
The situation with regard to the field of organisation studies at
the present time, as in other social science disciplines, is that a vast
Introduction ix
proportion of theory and research is located within the bounds of
just one of the four paradigms to be considered here. Indeed, the
bulk of it is located within the context of a relatively narrow range
oftheoretical possibilities which define that one paradigm.lt is no
exaggeration, therefore, to suggest that the social-scientific enter-
prise in general is built upon an extremely narrow set of
metatheoretical assumptions. This concentration of effort in a
relatively narrow area defines what is usually regarded as the
dominant orthodoxy within a subject. Because this orthodoxy is so
dominant and strong, its adherents often take it for granted as right
and self-evident. Rival perspectives within the same paradigm or
outside its bounds appear as satellites defining alternative points of
view. Their impact upon the orthodoxy, however, is rarely very
significant. They are seldom strong enough to establish themselves
as anything more than a somewhat deviant set of approaches. As a
result the possibilities which they offer are rarely explored, let
alone understood.
In order to understand alternative points of view it is important
that a theorist be fully aware of the assumptions upon which his
own perspective is based. Such an appreciation involves an intel-
lectual journey which takes him outside the realm of his own
familiar domain. It requires that he become aware of the bound-
aries which define his perspective. It requires that he journey into
the unexplored. It requires that he become familiar with paradigms
which are not his own. Only then can he look back and appreciate
in full measure the precise nature of his starting point.
The work presented here is an attempt to take the student of
organisations into realms which he has probably not explored
before. It is a journey upon which we, the authors, unwittingly
embarked as a result of certain nagging doubts and uncertainties
about the utility and validity of much contemporary theory and
research in our subject. We were concerned about the way in
which studies of organisational activities had generated mountains
of theory and research which seemed to have no obvious links
outside narrow discipline areas. We were concerned about the
essentially ephemeral nature of our subject. We were concerned
about the academic sectarianism reflected at various times in open
hostility, ostrich-like indifference and generally poor-quality
dialogue and debate between essentially related schools of
thought. In short, we felt that our subject area called for a close
examination of the assumptions upon which it is based with a view
to seeing it in a new, and hopefully refreshing, light. Our book in
essence presents an account of our journey and a record of the
x ‘ntroduction
conclusions and insights which have emerged.
We began our enterprise by considering how we could dis-
tinguish between different approaches to the study of
organisations. The view that ‘all theories of organisation are based
upon a philosophy of science and a theory of society’ seemed to
recur time and again in our conversations and· we soon found it
defining two major dimensions of analysis. Although organisation
theorists are not always very explicit about the basic assumptions
which inform their point of view, it is clear that they all take a stand
on each of these issues. Whettter they are aware of it or not, they
bring to their subject of study a frame of reference which reflects a
whole series of assumptions about the nature of the social world
and the way in which it might be investigated.
Our attempt to explore these assumptions led us into the realm
of social philosophy. We were confronted with problems of ontol-
ogy and epistemology and other issues which rarely receive con-
sideration within the field of organisation studies. As we
investigated these issues we found that they underpinned the great
philosophical debates between social theorists from rival
intellectual traditions. We realised that the orthodoxy in our sub-
ject was based in essence upon just one of these traditions, and that
the satellite perspectives which we had observed as surrounding
the orthodoxy were, in fact, derived from quite a separate
intellectual source. We realised that they were attempting to
articulate points of view which derived from diametrically
opposed assumptions about the basic nature of the social world;
accordingly they subscribed to quite different assumptions about
the very nature of the social-scientific enterprise itself.
In investigating assumptions with regard to the nature of society
we were, at first, able to operate on firmer ground. The sociology
of the 1960s had focused upon the ·order-conflict debate’ –
whether sociology emphasises the ‘problem of order’ or the
·problem of conflict and change’. By the late 1960s the debate had
been pronounced dead, and these two views of society were seen
merely as two aspects of the same problematic. In reviewing the
literature relevant to this debate we became increasingly con-
vinced that it had met a premature death. Whilst it was clear that
academic sociologists had convinced themselves that the ‘problem
of conflict’ could be subsumed under the ‘problem of order’,
theorists outside this tradition, particularly those interested in
Marxist theory, were actively engaged in the development of
social theories which placed the problems of conflict and change at
the forefront of their analysis. Although academic sociologists and
Introduction xi
Marxist social theorists appeared content to work in isolation,
ignoring the contradictory perspectives which they presented, it
seemed that any adequate analysis of theories of society must take
these rival perspectives into account.
Our journey into Marxist literature took us into yet another new
realm as far as our initial interests were concerned. We were
surprised to find striking parallels between intellectual
developments within Marxist theory and academic sociology. We
found that the assumptions about the nature of social science
which had divided academic sociologists into different schools of
thought also divided Marxist theorists. In that realm, too, the
dominant theoretical framework was surrounded by satellite
schools of thought offering rival explanations. Pursuing these tra-
ditions to their source, we found that they emerged from precisely
the same bounds of social philosophy which had underwritten
divergent elements within sociology itself. It became clear that the
rival traditions emphasising ‘order’ as opposed to ·conflict’ shared
the same pedigree as far as their roots in social philosophy were
concerned. Deriving from similar assumptions about the
ontological and epistemological status of social science, they had
been wedded to fundamentally different frames of reference with
regard to the nature of society.
Given these cross linkages between rival intellectual traditions,
it became clear to us that our two sets of assumptions could be
counter-posed to produce an analytical scheme for studying social
theories in general: the two sets of assumptions defined four basic
paradigms reflecting quite separate views of social reality. On
attempting to relate this scheme to the social science literature we
found that we possessed an extremely powerful tool for negotiating
our way through different subject areas, and one which made sense
of a great deal of the confusion which characterises much con-
temporary debate within the social sciences. The scheme offered
itself as a form of intellectual map upon which social theories could
be located according to their source and tradition. Theories rarely
if ever appear out of thin air; they usually have a well established
history behind them. We found that our intellectual map allowed
us to trace their evolution. Theories fell into place according to
their origins. Where rival intellectual traditions had been fused,
distinctive hybrid versions seemed to appear. What had first
offered itself as a simple classificatory device for organising the
literature now presented itself as an analytical tool. It pointed us
towards new areas of investigation. It allowed us to appraise and
evaluate theories against the backcloth of the intellectual tradition
xii Introduction
which they sought to emulate. It allowed us to identify embryonic
theories and anticipate potential lines of development. It allowed
us to write this book.
In the following chapters we seek to present our analytical
scheme and to use it to negotiate a way through the literature on
social theory and organisational analysis. We have aimed to pre-
sent it as clearly and directly as we can whilst avoiding the pitfalls
of oversimplification. But the concepts of one paradigm cannot
easily be interpreted in terms of those of another. To understand
a new paradigm one has to explore it from the inside, in terms of
its own distinctive problematic. Thus, whilst we have made every
effort to present our account as plainly as possible as far as the use
of the English language is concerned, we have necessarily had to
draw upon concepts which may at times be unfamiliar.
The remaining chapters in Part I define the nature of our two key
dimensions of analysis and the paradigms which arise within their
bounds. In this analysis we polarise a number of issues and make
much use of rough dichotomisations as a means of presenting our
case. We do so not merely for the purposes of classification. but to
forge a working tool. We advocate our scheme as a heuristic device
rather than as a set of rigid definitions.
In Part II we put our analytical framework into operation. For
each of our four paradigms we conduct an analysis of relevant
social theory and then proceed to relate theories of organisation to
this wider background. Each of the paradigms is treated in terms
consistent with its own distinctive frame of reference. No attempt
is made to criticise and evaluate from a perspective outside the
paradigm. Such criticism is all too easy but self-defeating, since it
is usually directed at the foundations of the paradigm itself. All
four paradigms can successfully be demolished in these terms.
What we seek to do is to develop the perspective characteristic of
the paradigm and draw out some of its implications for social
analysis. In so doing we have found that we are frequently able to
strengthen the conceptualisations which each paradigm generates
as far as the study of organisations is concerned. Our guiding rule
has been to seek to offer something to each paradigm within the
terms of its own problematic. The chapters in Part II, therefore,
are essentially expository in nature. They seek to provide a
detailed framework upon which future debate might fruitfully be
based.
Part Ill presents a short conclusion which focuses upon some of
the principal issues which emerge from our analysis.
PART 1: IN SEARCH OF A FRAMEWORK
1. Assumptions about the
Nature of Social Science
Central to our thesis is the idea that ‘all theories of organisation are
based upon a philosophy of science and a theory of society’. In this
chapter we wish to address ourselves to the first aspect of this
thesis and to examine some of the philosophical assumptions
which underwrite different approaches to social science. We shall
argue that it is convenient to conceptualise social science in terms
of four sets of assumptions related to ontology, epistemology,
human nature and methodology.
All social scientists approach their subject via explicit or implicit
assumptions about the nature of the social world and the way in
which it may be investigated. First, there are assumptions of an
ontological nature – assumptions which concern the very essence
of the phenomena under investigation. Social scientists, for
example, are faced with a basic ontological question: whether the
·reality’ to be investigated is external to the individual – imposing
itself on individual consciousness from without – or the product of
individual consciousness; whether ‘reality’ is of an ‘objective’
nature, or the product of individual cognition; whether ‘reality’ is a
given ·out there’ in the world, or the product of one’s mind.
Associated with this ontological issue, is a second set of
assumptions of an epistemological nature. These are assumptions
about the grounds of knowledge – about how one might begin to
understand the world and communicate this as knowledge to
fellow human beings. These assumptions entail ideas. for example,
about what forms of knowledge can be obtained, and how one can
sort out what is to be regarded as ‘true’ from what is to be regarded
as ‘false·. Indeed, this dichotomy of ‘true’ and ‘false’ itself pre-
supposes a certain epistemological stance. It is predicated upon a
view of the nature of knowledge itself: whether, for example, it is
possible to identify and communicate the nature of knowledge as
being hard, real and capable of being transmitted in tangible form,
or whether ‘knowledge’ is of a softer, more subjective. spiritual or
even transcendental kind, based on experience and insight of a
2 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
unique and essentially personal nature. The epistemological
assumptions in these instances determine extreme positions on the
issue of whether knowledge is something which can be acquired on
the one hand, or is something which has to be personally exper-
ienced on the other.
Associated with the ontological and epistemological issues, but
conceptually separate from them, is a third set of assumptions
concerning human nature and, in particular, the relationship
between human beings and their environment, All social science,
clearly, must be predicated upon this type of assumption, since
human life is essentially the subject and object of enquiry. Thus,
we can identify perspectives in social science which entail a view
of human beings responding in a mechanistic or even deterministic
fashion to the situations encountered in their external world. This
view tends to be one in which human beings and their experiences
are regarded as products of the environment~ one in which humans
are conditioned by their external circumstances. This extreme
perspective can be contrasted with one which attributes to human
beings a much more creative role: with a perspective where ‘free
will’ occupies the centre of the stage; where man is regarded as the
creator of his environment, the controller as opposed to the con-
trolled, the master rather than the marionette. In these two
extreme views of the relationship between human beings and their
environment we are identifying a great philosophical debate
between the advocates of determinism on the one hand and
voluntarism on the other. Whilst there are social theories which
adhere to each of these extremes, as we shall see, the assumptions
of many social scientists are pitched somewhere in the range
between.
The three sets of assumptions outlined above have direct
implications of a methodological nature. Each one has important
consequences for the way in which one attempts to investigate and
obtain ‘knowledge’ about the social world. Different ontologies,
epistemologies and models of human nature are likely to incline
social scientists towards different methodologies. The possible
range of choice is indeed so large that what is regarded as science
by the traditional ·natural scientist’ covers but a small range of
options. It is possible, for example, to identify methodologies
employed in social science research which treat the social world
like the natural world, as being hard, real and external to the
individual, and others which view it as being of a much softer,
personal and more subjective quality.
If one subscribes to a view of the former kind, which treats the
Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science 3
social world as if it were a hard, external. objective reality, then the
scientific endeavour is likely to focus upon an analysis of relation-
ships and regularities between the various elements which it com-
prises. The concern, therefore, is with the identification and defini-
tion of these elements and with the discovery of ways in which
these relationships can be expressed. The methodological issues of
importance are thus the concepts themselves, their measurement
and the identification of underlying themes. This perspective
expresses itself most forcefully in a search for universal laws
which explain and govern the reality which is being observed.
If one subscribes to the alternative view of social reality, which
stresses the importance of the subjective experience of individuals
in the creation of the social world, then the search for understand-
ing focuses upon different issues and approaches them in different
ways. The principal concern is with an understanding of the way in
which the individual creates, modifies and interprets the world in
which he or she finds himself. The emphasis in extreme cases tends
to be placed upon the explanation and understanding of what is
unique and particular to the individual rather than of what is
general and universal. This approach questions whether there
exists an external reality worthy ofstudy.ln methodological terms
it is an approach which emphasises the relativistic nature of the
social world to such an extent that it may be perceived as ·anti-
scientific’ by reference to the ground rules commonly applied in
the natural sciences.
The subjective-objective dimension
The sub~ctivist The objectivist
approac to approach to
social science social science
Nominalism I . ontology . I Realism
Anti-positivism I· epistemology . I Positivism
Voluntarism I· human nature ·I Determinism
ldeograph•C I I methodology I I Nomothetic
Figure 1.1 A scheme for analysina assumptions about the nature fl social science
4 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
In this brief sketch of various ontological, epistemological,
human and methodological standpoints which characterise
approaches to social sciences, we have sought to illustrate two
broad and somewhat polarised perspectives. Figure 1.1 seeks to
depict these in a more rigorous fashion in terms of what we shall
describe as the subjective-objective dimension. It identifies the
four sets of assumptions relevant to our understanding of social
science, characterising each by the descriptive labels under which
they have been debated in the literature on social philosophy. In
the following section ofthis chapter we will review each of the four
debates in necessarily brief but more systematic terms.
The Strands of Debate
Nominalism-realism: the ontological debate 1
These terms have been the subject of much discussion in the
literature and there are great areas of controversy surrounding
them. The nominalist position revolves around the assumption
that the social world external to individual cognition is made up of
nothing more than names, concepts and labels which are used to
structure reality. The nominalist does not admit to there being any
·rear structure to the world which these concepts are used to
describe. The ‘names’ used are regarded as artificial creations
whose utility is based upon their convenience as tools for describ-
ing, making sense of and negotiating the external world. Nominal-
ism is often equated with conventionalism, and we will make no
distinction between them. 2
Realism, on the other hand. postulates that the social world
external to individual cognition is a real world made up of hard,
tangible and relatively immutable structures. Whether or not we
label and perceive these structures,the realists maintain, they still
exist as empirical entities. We may not even be aware of the
existence of certain crucial structures and therefore have no
·names’ or concepts to articulate them. For the realist, the social
world exists independently of an individual’s appreciation of it.
The individual is seen as being born into and living within a social
world which has a reality of its own. It is not something which the
individual creates-it exists ‘out there’; ontologically it is prior to
the existence and consciousness of any single human being. For
the realist, the social world has an existence which is as hard and
concrete as the natural world. 3
Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science S
Anti-positivism-positivism: the
epistemological debate 4
It has been maintained that ‘the word “positivist .. like the word
“bourgeois” has become more of a derogatory epithet than a
useful descriptive concept’ .s We intend to use it here in the latter
sense, as a descriptive concept which can be used to characterise a
particular type of epistemology. Most of the descriptions of
positivism in current usage refer to one or more ofthe ontological,
epistemological and methodological dimensions of our scheme for
analysing assumptions with regard to social science. It is also
sometimes mistakenly equated with empiricism. Such conflations
cloud basic issues and contribute to the use of the term in a
derogatory sense.
We use ·positivist’ here to characterise epistemologies which
seek to explain and predict what happens in the social world by
searching for regularities and causal relationships between its con-
stituent elements. Positivist epistemology is in essence based upon
the traditional approaches which dominate the natural sciences.
Positivists may differ in terms of detailed approach. Some would
claim, for example, that hypothesised regularities can be verified
by an adequate experimental research programme. Others would
maintain that hypotheses can only be falsified and never demon-
strated to be ‘true’ .6 However, both ·verificationists’ and ‘fal-
sificationists’ would accept that the growth of knowledge is essen-
tially a cumulative process in which new insights are added to the
existing stock of knowledge and false hypotheses eliminated.
The epistemology of anti-positivism may take various forms but
is firmly set against the utility of a search for Jaws or underlying
regularities in the world ofsocial affairs. For the anti-positivist, the
social world is essentially relativistic and can only be understood
from the point ofview ofthe individuals who are directly involved
in the activities which are to be studied. Anti-positivists reject the
standpoint of the ‘observer’, which characterises positivist
epistemology, as a valid vantage point for understanding human
activities. They maintain that one can only ·understand’ by
occupying the frame of reference of the participant in action. One
has to understand from the inside rather than the outside. From
this point of view social science is seen as being essentially a
subjective rather than an objective enterprise. Anti-positivists
tend to reject the notion that science can generate objective
knowledge of any kind. 7
6 Soc·iological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Voluntarism-determinism: the ‘human nature’
debate
This debate revolves around the issue of what model of man is
reflected in any given social-scientific theory. At one extreme we
can identify a determinist view which regards man and his
activities as being completely determined by the situation or
·environment’ in which he is located. At another extreme we can
identify the voluntarist view that man is completely autonomous
and free-willed. Insofar as social science theories are concerned to
understand human activities, they must incline implicitly or
explicitly to one or other of these points of view, or adopt an
intermediate standpoint which allows for the influence of both
situational and voluntary factors in accounting for the activities of
human beings. Such assumptions are essential elements in social-
scientific theories, since they define in broad terms the nature of
the relationships between man and the society in which he lives.•
Ideographic-nomothetic theory: the method-
ological debate
The ideographic approach to social science is based on the view
that one can only understand the social world by obtaining first-
hand knowledge of the subject under investigation. It thus places
considerable stress upon getting close to one’s subject and
exploring its detailed background and life history. The ideographic
approach emphasises the analysis of the subjective accounts
which one generates by ‘getting inside’ situations and involving
oneself in the everyday flow of life – the detailed analysis of the
insights generated by such encounters with one’s subject and the
insights revealed in impressionistic accounts found in diaries,
biographies and journalistic records. The ideographic method
stresses the importance of letting one’s subject unfold its nature
and characteristics during the process of investigation.’
The nomothetic approach to social science lays emphasis on the
importance of basing research upon systematic protocol and
technique. It is epitomised in the approach and methods employed
in the natural sciences, which focus upon the process of testing
hypotheses in accordance with the canons of scientific rigour.lt is
preoccupied with the construction of scientific tests and the use of
Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science 7
quantitative techniques for the analysis of data. Surveys,
questionnaires, personality tests and standardised research
instruments of all kinds are prominent among the tools which
comprise nomothetic methodology . 10
Analysing Assumptions about the Nature of
Social Science
These four sets of assumptions with regard to the nature of social
science provide an extremely powerful tool for the analysis of
social theory. In much of the literature there is a tendency to
conflate the issues which are involved. We wish to argue here that
considerable advantages accrue from treating these four strands of
social-scientific debate as analytically distinct. While in practice
there is often a strong relationship between the positions adopted
on each of the four strands, assumptions about each can in fact
vary quite considerably. It is worth examining this point in more
detail.
The extreme positions on each of the four strands are reflected in
the two major intellectual traditions which have dominated social
science over the last two hundred years. The first of these is
usually described as •sociological positivism’. In essence this
reflects the attempt to apply models and methods derived from the
natural sciences to the study of human affairs. It treats the social
world as if it were the natural world, adopting a ‘realist’ approach
to ontology. This is backed up by a ·positivist’ epistemology,
relatively ‘deterministic’ views of human nature and the use of
•nomothetic’ methodologies. The second intellectual tradition,
that of •German idealism’, stands in complete opposition to this. In
essence it is based upon the premise that the ultimate reali”ty of the
universe lies in ‘spirit’ or ‘idea’ rather than in the data of sense
perception. It is essentially ‘nominalist’ in its approach to social
reality. In contrast to the natural sciences, it stresses the
essentially subjective nature of human affairs, denying the utility
and relevance of the models and methods of natural science to
studies in this realm. It is ‘anti-positivist’ in epistemology,
·voluntarist’ with regard to human nature and it favours ideo-
graphic methods as a foundation for social analysis. Sociological
positivism and German idealism thus define the objective and
subjective extremes of our model.
Many sociologists and organisation theorists have been brought
up within the tradition of sociological positivism, without
8 Sociolopiml Paradipms and Orpanisational Analysi.’l
exposure to the basic tenets of German idealism. Social science for
them is seen as consonant with the configuration of assumptions
which characterise the objective extreme of our model. However,
over the last seventy years or so there has been an increasing
interaction between these two traditions, particularly at a socio-
philosophical level. As a result intermediate points of view have
emerged, each with its own distinctive configural’ion of
assumptions about the nature of social science. They have all
spawned theories, ideas and approaches characteristic of their
intermediate position. As we shall argue in later chapters,
developments in phenomenology, ethnomethodology and the
action frame of reference are to be understood in these terms.
These perspectives, whilst offering their own special brand of
insight, have also often been used as launching pads for attacks on
sociological positivism and have generated a considerable amount
of debate between rival schools of thought. The nature of this
debate can only be fully understood by grasping and appreciating
the different assumptions which underwrite the competing points
of view.
It is our contention that the analytical scheme offered here
enables one to do precisely this. It is offered not as a mere
classificatory device, but as an important tool for negotiating
social theory. It draws attention to key assumptions. It allows one
to focus on precise issues which differentiate socio-scientific
approaches. It draws attention to the degree of congruency
between the four sets of assumptions about social science which
characterise any given theorist’s point of view. We offer it here as
the first principal dimension of our theoretical scheme for
analysing theory in general and organisational theory in particular.
For the sake of convenience we shall normally refer to it as the
·subjective-objective’ dimension, two descriptive labels which
perhaps capture the points of commonality between the four
analytical strands.
Notes and References
I. For a further discussion of the nominalism-realism debate,
see Kolakowski (1972). pp. 15-16.
2. Kolakowski ( 1972), pp. 158-9. In its most extreme form
nominalism does not recognise the existence of any world
outside the realm of individual consciousness. This is the
solipsist position, which we discuss in more detail in Chapter
6.
A:uumption.~ about the Nature of Social Science 9
3. For a comprehensive review of ‘realism’, see Keat and Urry
(1975), pp. 27-45. They make much of the distinction
between ‘positivism’ and ‘realism’ but, as they admit, these
terms are used in a somewhat unconventional way.
4. For a further discussion of the positivism-anti-positivism
debate, see, for example, Giddens (1974) and Walsh ( 1972).
5. Giddens (1974). p. I.
6. See, for example, Popper (1963).
7. For a good illustration of an anti-positivist view of science,
see Douglas (1970b), pp. 3-44.
8. The human nature debate in its widest sense involves many
other issues which we have not referred to here. The precise
model of man to be employed in any analytical scheme,
however, is underwritten by assumptions which reflect the
voluntarism-determinism issue in one way or another. We
have isolated this element of the debate here as a way of
treating at its most basic level a necessary assumption of all
social-scientific theories which purport to account for human
activities. Detailed propositions with regard to the precise
explanation of human activities elaborate in one way or
another this basic theme.
9. For an excellent discussion of the nature of the ideographic
approach to social science, see Blumer (1969), ch. I.
10. It is important to emphasise here that both nomothetic and
ideographic methodologies can be employed in a deductive
and inductive sense. Whilst the inductive-deductive debate
in science is a subject of considerable interest and
importance, we do not see it as being central to the four
dimensions suggested here as a means of distinguishing
between the nature of social science theories. That notwith-
standing, it remains an important methodological issue, of
relevance to both sociology and organisational analysis,
within the context of the assumptions explored here.
2. Assumptions about the Nature
of Society
All approaches to the study of society are located in a frame of
reference of one kind or another. Different theories tend to reflect
different perspectives, issues and problems worthy of study. and
are generally based upon a whole set of assumptions which reflect
a particular view of the nature of the subject under investigation.
The last twenty years or so have witnessed a number of attempts
on the part of sociologists to delineate the differences which
separate various schools of thought and the meta-sociological
assumptions which they reflect.
The Order-Conflict Debate
Dahrendorf (1959) and Lockwood (1956), for example, have
sought to distinguish between those approaches to sociology
which concentrated upon explaining the nature of social order and
equilibrium on the one hand, and those which were more con-
cerned with problems of change, conflict and coercion in social
structures on the other. This distinction has received a great deal of
attention and has come to be known as the ·order-conflict
debate’. The •order theorists’ have greatly outnumbered the ·con-
flict theorists’. and as Dawe has observed, ‘the thesis that socio-
logy is centrally concerned with the problem of social order has
become one of the discipline’s few orthodoxies. It is common as a
basic premise to many accounts of sociological theory which
otherwise differ considerably in purpose and perspective’ (Dawe,
1970, p. 207). 1
Many sociologists now regard this debate as dead or as having
been a somewhat spurious non-debate in the first place (Cohen,
1968: Silverman, 1970: van den Berghe, 1969). Influenced by the
work of writers such as Coser ( 1956), who pointed to the functional
aspects of social conflict, sociologists have been able to incorpor-
ate conflict as a variable within the bounds of theories which are
Assumptions about the Nature of Society II
primarily geared towards an explanation of social order. The
approach advocated by Cohen, for example, clearly illustrates
this. He takes his point of departure from the work of Dahrendorf
and elaborates some of the central ideas in the order-conflict
debate to present two models of society, which are characterised
in terms of competing sets of assumptions which attribute to social
systems the characteristics of commitment, cohesion, solidarity,
consensus, reciprocity, ccroperation, integration, stability and
persistence on the one hand, and the characteristics of coercion,
division, hostility, dissensus, conflict, malintegration and change
on the other (Cohen, 1968, pp. 166-7).
Cohen’s central criticism is that Dahrendorfis mistaken in treat-
ing the order and conflict models as being entirely separate. He in
effect suggests that it is possible for theories to involve elements of
both models and that one need not necessarily incline to one or the
other. From this point of view, the order and conflict views of
society are but two sides of the same coin; they are not mutually
exclusive and thus do not need to be reconciled. The force of this
sort of argument has been very powerful in diverting attention
away from the order-conflict debate.ln the wake of the so-called
counter-culture movement of the late 1960s and the failure of the
1968 revolution in France, orthodox sociologists have become
much more interested in and concerned with the problems of the
‘individual’ as opposed to those of the •structure’ of society in
general. The influence of ·subjectivist’ movements such as
phenomenology, ethnomethodology and action theory. which we
referred to in passing in the previous chapter, have tended to
become much more attractive and more worthy of attention. As a
result, interest in continuing the conflict-order debate has sub-
sided under the iQfluence of issues relating to the philosophy and
methods of social science.
Our contention here is that if one reviews the intellectual source
and foundations of the order-conflict debate, one is forced to
conclude that it has met a premature death. Dahrendorf and
Lockwood sought to revitalise the work of Marx through their
writings and to restore it to a central place in sociological theory.
For the most part Marx had been largely ignored by leading
sociologists, the influence of theorists such as Durkheim, Weber
and Pareto having been paramount. Interestingly enough, these
latter three sociologists are all very much concerned with the
problem of social order; it is Marx who is preoccupied with the role
of conflict as the driving force behind social change. Stated in this
way, therefore, the order-conflict debate is underwritten by a
12 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
difference between the perspectives and concerns ofleading social
theorists of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Modern
sociology has done little more than articulate and develop the basic
themes initiated by these pioneers of social analysis. To state that
the order-conflict debate is ·dead’ or a ‘non-debate’ is thus to
underplay, if not ignore, substantial differences between the work
of Marx and, for example, Durkheim, Weber and Pareto. Anyone
familiar with the work of these theorists and aware of the deep
division which exists between Marxism and sociology is forced to
admit that there are fundamental differences, which are far from
being reconciled. 2 In this chapter therefore, we wish to re-evaluate
the order-conflict issue with a view to identifying a key dimen-
sion for analysing the assumptions about the nature of society
reflected in different social theories.ln order to do so,let us return
to the work of Dahrendorf, who seeks to set out the opposing
issues in the following terms:
The integration theory of society, as displayed by the work of Parsons
and other structural-functionalists, is founded on a number of assump-
tions of the following type:
(I) Every society is a relatively persistent, stable structure of ele-
ments.
(2) Every society is a well integrated structure of elements.
(3) Every element in a society has a function, i.e .• renders a con-
tribution to its maintenance as a system.
(4) Every functioning social structure is based on a consensus of
values among its members ….
. . . What I have called the coercion theory of society can also be
reduced to a small number of basic tenets, although here again these
assumptions oversimplify and overstate the case:
(I) Every society is at every point subject to processes of change;
social change is ubiquitous.
(2) Every society displays at every point dissensus and conflict;
social conflict is ubiquitous.
(3) Every element in a society renders a contribution to its disin-
tegration and change.
(4) Every society is based on the coercion of some of its members by
others. (Dahrendorf, 1959, pp. 160-2)
The opposing adjectives which Dahrendorf’s schema suggests for
distinguishing approaches to the study of society can be conve-
niently brought together in the form of a table, as follows:
Assumptions about the Nature of Society 13
Table l.l
Two theories of society: ‘order• and •conOid’
The ‘order’ or ‘inugrationist’
”iew of society emphasises:
Stability
Integration
Functional co-ordination
Consensus
The ‘conflict’ or ‘coercion’
view of society empha.tises:
Change
Conflict
Disintegration
Coercion
As Dahrendorf admits, this conceptualisation is something of an
oversimplification, and whilst providing a very useful tool for
coming to grips with the differences between the two standpoints,
it is open to the possibility of misinterpretation, in that the different
adjectives mean different things to different people. Nowhere is
this more evident than in the way in which the notion of conflict
has been treated in the sociological literature. Since Coser’s
demonstration of the functions of social conflict, for example, the
role of conflict as an integrating mechanism has received a great
deal of attention. In effect, the whole notion of •conflict’ bas often
been incorporated within the notion of integration. Dahrendorf’s
integration/conflict dimension has been conveniently telescoped
so that it is brought within the bounds of sociology’s traditional
concern for the explanation of order. The fallacy of this position
becomes clear if one considers certain extreme forms of conflict,
such as class conflict, revolution and war, which can only be
incorporated in the integrationist model by the wildest stretch of
one’s imagination. Examples such as these suggest that it is mis-
leading to equate this type of macrostructural conflict with the
functional conflict identified by Coser. There is an important
question of degree involved here, which emphasises the dangers of
the dichotomisation of integration and conflict; realistically the
distinction between the two is much more of a continuum than the
majority of writers have recognised.
Another strand of the Dahrendorf scheme which can be
regarded as somewhat problematic lies in the distinction between
consensus and coercion. At first sight the distinction appears
obvious and clear-cut, focusing upon shared values on the one
hand and the imposition of some sort of force on the other. On
closer inspection there is a certain ambiguity. Where do the shared
values come from? Are they acquired autonomously or imposed
on some members of society by others? This question identifies the
14 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
possibility that consensus may be the product of the use of some
form of coercive force. For example, as C. Wright Mills has
pointed out, ·What Parsons and other grand theorists call ••value
orientations” and ••normative structure” has mainly to do with
master symbols of legitimation’ (1959, p. 46).
A normative structure here – what Dahrendorf would view as
consensus – is treated as a system legitimising the power
structure. From Mills’s point of view, it reflects the fact of
domination. In other words, shared values may be regarded not so
much as an index ofthe degree of integration which characterises a
society as one which reflects the success of the forces of
domination in a society prone to disintegration. From one point of
view, extant shared ideas, values and norms are something to be
preserved; from another, they represent a mode of domination
from which man needs to be released. The consensus/ coercion
dimension can thus be seen as focusing upon the issue of social
control. Consensus – however it may arise – is identified in
Dahrendorf’s scheme as something independent of coercion. This
we believe to be a mistaken view since, as suggested above, it
ignores the possibility of a form of coercion which arises through
the control of value systems.
In distinguishing between stability and change as respective
features of the order and conflict models Dahrendorfis again open
to misinterpretation, even though he explicitly states that he does
not intend to imply that the theory of order assumes that societies
are static. His concern is to show how functional theories are
essentially concerned with those processes which serve to
maintain the patterns of the system as a whole. In other words,
functional theories are regarded as static in the sense that they are
concerned with explaining the status quo. In this respect conflict
theories are clearly of a different nature; they are committed to,
and seek to explain, the process and nature of deep-seated
structural change in society as opposed to change of a more
superficial and ephemeral kind. The fact that all functional theories
recognise change, and that change is an obvious empirical reality
in everyday life, has led Dahrendorf’s categorisation in relation to
stability and change to lose its potential radical force and influ-
ence. It can be argued that different labels are required to identify
Dahrendorf’s two paramount concerns: first, that the order view of
society is primarily status quo orientated; second, that it deals
with change of a fundamentally different nature from that with
which conflict theorists are concerned. 3
Dahrendorf’s notions of functional co-ordination and disin·
Assumptions about th~ Natur~ of Soci~ty 15
t~gration can be seen as constituting one of the most powerful
strands of thought which distinguish the order and conflict per-
spectives. Here again, however, there is room for misinterpreta-
tion. The concept of integration in Dahrendorf’s work derives from
the functionalists’ concern with the contribution which constituent
elements of a system make to the whole. In many respects this is an
oversimplification. Merton ( 1948) introduced the idea of manifest
and latent functions, some of which may be dysfunctional for the
integration of society.4 Again, Gouldner (1959), writing shortly
after the publication of the German edition of Dahrendorf’s work,
suggests that various parts of a system may have a high degree of
autonomy and may contribute very little by way of integration to
the system as a whole. The term ‘functional co-ordination’ is thus
something of an oversimplification and, given the existence of the
points of view expressed above within the functionalist camp
itself, it is not surprising that the concept of ‘disintegration’ should
be seen as relevant and capable of being used from a functional
standpoint. •Disintegration’ can be very easily viewed as an inte-
grationist concept and, as with other aspects of Dahrendorf’s
scheme, this dimension has often been telescoped and brought
within the bounds of the theories of order. For this reason it may
well have been clearer if the position of conflict theory on this
dimension had been presented in more radical and distinctive
terms. There is much in Marxian theory, for example, which refers
to the notion of ‘contradiction’ and the basic incompatibility be-
tween different elements of social structure. Contradiction implies
heterogeneity, imbalance and essentially antagonistic and
divergent social forces. It thus stands at the opposite pole to the
concept of ‘functional co-ordination’, which must presuppose a
basic compatibility between the elements of any given system. To
argue that the concept of contradiction can be embraced within
functional analysis requires either an act of faith or at least a
considerable leap of imagination.
Dahrendorf’s work has clearly served a very useful purpose in
identifying a number of important strands of thought distinguishing
theorists of order from theorists of conflict. However, as will be
apparent from the above discussion, in many respects the dis-
tinctions which have been drawn between the two meta-theories do
not go far enough. In particular, the insights of some twenty years
of debate suggest that the characterisation of the conflict
perspective has not been sufficiently radical to avoid confusion
with the ‘integrationist’ perspective. This has allowed theorists of
order to meet the challenge which Dahrendorf’s scheme presents
16 Sociological Paradigms and Organisalional Analysis
to their frame of reference within the context of their order-
orientated mode of thought. In order to illustrate this point, let us
return to the work of Cohen (1968) referred to earlier.
In advocating his viewpoint Cohen appears to be misinterpreting
the distinction between the two models. His interpretation of
concepts telescopes the different variables into a form in which
they can be seen as consistent with each other. In effect his whole
analysis reflects an attempt to incorporate the conflict model
within the bounds of the contemporary theory of order. He thus
loses the radical essence of the conflict perspective and is able to
conclude that the two models are not mutually exclusive and do
not need to be reconciled. He argues that the two models are not
genuine alternatives and in effect suggests that each is no more
than the reciprocal of the other. He is therefore able to leave
Dahrendorf’s analysis with the central concern of his book – the
problem of order – largely intact. The incorporation of conflict
into the bounds of the model of order de-emphasise~ its
importance. s
In line with the analysis which we presented earlier, we argue
that the attempt to reduce the two models to a common base ignores
the fundamental differences which exist between them. A conflict
theory based on deep-seated structural conflict and concerned
with radical transformations of society is not consistent with a
functionalist perspective. The differences between them,
therefore, are important and worthy of distinction in any attempt
to analyse social theory. With the benefit of hindsight, it is possible
to see that many of the misinterpretations which have arisen have
done so because the models in Dahrendorf’s analysis were not
sufficiently differentiated. We wish to propose, therefore, that
certain modifications be made in order to articulate the differences
in a more explicit and radical form. Since much of the confusion
has arisen because of the ambiguity of the descriptions associated
with the two models we wish to suggest the use of a somewhat
different terminology.
‘Regulation’ and ‘Radical Change’
Our analysis has shown that the order-conflict distinction is in
many senses the most problematic. We suggest, therefore, that it
should be replaced as a central theme by the notions of •regulation’
and ‘radical change’.
Assumptions about the Nature of Society 17
We introduce the term ‘sociology of regulation’ to refer to the
writings of theorists who are primarily concerned to provide
explanations of society in terms which emphasise its underlying
unity and cohesiveness. It is a sociology which is essentially con-
cerned with the need for regulation in human affairs; the basic
questions which it asks tend to focus upon the need to understand
why society is maintained as an entity. It attempts to explain why
society tends to hold together rather than fall apart. It is interested
in understanding the social forces which prevent the Hobbesian
vision of ‘war of all against all’ becoming a reality. The work of
Durkheim with its emphasis upon the nature of social cohesion and
solidarity, for example, provides a clear and comprehensive
illustration of a concern for the sociology of regulation.
The ‘sociology of radical change • stands in stark contrast to the
‘sociology of regulation’. in that its basic concern is to find
explanations for the radical change, deep-seated structural con-
flict, modes of domination and structural contradiction which its
theorists see as characterising modem society. It is a sociology
which is essentially concerned with man’s emancipation from the
structures which limit and stunt his potential for development. The
basic questions which it asks focus upon the deprivation of man,
both material and psychic.lt is often visionary and Utopian, in that
it looks towards potentiality as much as actuality; it is concerned
with what is possible rather than with what is; with alternatives
rather than with acceptance of the status quo. In these respects it is
as widely separate and distant from the sociology of regulation as
the sociology of Marx is separated and distant from the sociology
of Durkheim.
The distinction between these two sociologies can perhaps be
best illustrated in schematic form; extreme points of view are
counter-posed in order to highlight the essential differences
between them. Table 2.2 summarises the situation.
We offer this regulation-radical change distinction as the
second principal dimension of our scheme for analysing social
theories. Along with the subjective-objective dimension
developed in the previous chapter, we present it as a powerful
means for identifying and analysing the assumptions which under-
lie social theories in general.
The notions of ·regulation’ and ‘radical change’ have thus far
been presented in a very rough and extreme form. The two models
illustrated in Table 2.2 should be regarded as ideal-typical
formulations. The seven elements which we have identified lend
themselves to a much more rigorous and systematic treatment in
18 Soc:ioloRical ParadiRms and OrRanisational Analysis
which their overall form and nature is spell out in detail. We delay
this task until later chapters. Here, we wish to address ourselves to
the broad relationships which exist between the sociologies of
regulation and radical change. We maintain that they present
fundamentally different views and interpretations of the nature of
society. They reflect fundamentally different frames of reference.
They present themselves, therefore, as alternative models for the
analysis of social processes.
To present the models in this way is to invite criticism along the
lines of that levelled at Dahrendorf’s work. For example, it could
be suggested that the two models are the reciprocals of each other
-no more than two sides of the same coin- and that relationships
Table l.l
The regulation-radical change dimension
Thr socioiORY of REGULATION
is concrrnrd with:
(a) The status quo
(b) Social order
(c) Consensus•
(d) Social integration and
cohesion
(e) Solidarity
(f) Need satisfactiont
(&) Actuality
Notes
Thr socioiORY of RADICAL CHANGE
is concrrnrd with:
(a) Radical change
(b) Structural conflict
(c) Modes of domination
(d) Contradiction
(e) Emancipation
(f) Deprivation
(g) Potentiality
• By ‘consensus’ we mean voluntary and ·spontaneous’ agree-
ment of opinion.
t The term ·need satisfaction’ is used to refer to the focus upon
satisfaction of individual or system ‘needs’. The sociology of
regulation tends to presume that various social characteristics can
be explained in relation to these needs. It presumes that it is
possible to identify and satisfy human needs within the context of
existing social systems, and that society reflects these needs. The
concept of ‘deprivation’, on the other hand, is rooted in the notion
that the social ·system’ prevents human fulfilment; indeed that
‘deprivation’ is created as the result of the status quo. The social
‘system’ is not seen as satisfying needs but as eroding the
possibilities for human fulfilment. It is rooted in the notion that
society has resulted in deprivation rather than in gain.
A.uumptions about the Nature of Society 19
between the sub-elements of each model need not be congruent,
that is, an analysis may pay attention to elements of both.
The answer to both criticisms follows our defence of
Dahrendorfs work. To conflate the two models and treat them as
variations on a single theme is to ignore or at least to underplay the
fundamental differences which exist between them. Whilst it may
be possible to use each model in a diluted form and thus obtain two
analyses of the middle ground which approximate each other, they
must remain essentially separate, since they are based upon oppos-
ing assumptions. Thus, as we have illustrated, to discuss the
‘functions’ of social conflict is to commit oneself to the sociology
of regulation as opposed to that of radical change. However close
one’s position might be to the middle ground, it would seem that
one must always be committed to one side more than another. The
fundamental distinctions between the sociologies of regulation and
radical change will become clear from our analysis of their
intellectual development and constituent schools of thought in
later chapters. We conceptualise these two broad sociological
perspectives in the form of a polarised dimension, recognising that
while variations within the context of each are possible, the
perspectives are necessarily separate and distinct from each other.
Notes and References
1. Among the numerous theorists primarily concerned with the
problem of order, Dawe cites Parsons (1949), Nisbet (1967),
Bramson (1961), Cohen (1968), and Aron (1968).
2. For a discussion of the Marxism versus social science
debate, see Shaw (1975). The division between Marxist
theorists and orthodox sociologists is now so deep that they
either ignore each other completely. or indulge in an
exchange of abuse and accusation regarding the political
conservatism or subversiveness commonly associated with
their respective points of view. Debate about the intellectual
strengths and weaknesses of their opposing standpoints is
conspicuous by its absence.
3. Later in this chapter we suggest that the descriptions of
·concern with the status quo’ and ‘concern for radical
change’ provide more accurate views of the issues involved
here.
20 Socitllogic.·ol Pt~rtldigms tlnd Or:ganisatioNC~I AnoiJisis
4. Dahrendorf acknowledges. Merton’s distinction between
Jlatent and manifest functions but does not pursue th·e con-
sequence of ·dysfun,ctions· for the concept of integration
(Dahf”endorf, 1959,. pp. 171-9).
S. Other ‘order’ theorists who have addressed themselves to
Dahrendorf”s model tend to follow a similar path in the
attempt to embrace conflict theory within their perspective.
See. for example. van den Berghe (1969).
3. Two Dimensions:
Four Paradigms
In the previous two chapters we have focused upon some of the
key assumptions which characterise different approaches to social
theory. We have argued that it is possible to analyse these
approaches in terms of two key dimensions of analysis. each of
which subsumes a series of related themes. It has been suggested
that assumptions about the nature of science can be thought of in
terms of what we call the subjective-objective dimension. and
assumptions about the nature of society in terms of a regulatio(}-
radical change dimension. In this chapter we wish to discuss the
relationships between the two dimensions and to develop a coher-
ent scheme for the analysis of social theory.
We have already noted how sociological debate since the late
1960s has tended to ignore the distinctions between the two dimen-
sions – in particular. how there has been a tendency to focus upon
issues concerned with the subjective-objective dimension and to
ignore those concerned with the regulation-radical change
dimension. Interestingly enough. this focus of attention has
characterised sociological thought associated with both regulation
and radical change. The subjective-objective debate has been
conducted independently within both sociological camps.
Within the sociology of regulation it has assumed the form of a
debate between interpretive sociology and functionalism. In the
wake of Berger and Luckmann’ s treatise on the sociology of know-
ledge (1966). Garfinkel’s work on ethnomethodology (1967) and a
general resurgence of interest in phenomenology. the questionable
status of the ontological and epistemological assumptions of the
functionalist perspective have become increasingly exposed. The
debate has often led to a polarisation between the two schools of
thought.
Similarly. within the context of the sociology of radical change
there has been a division between theorists subscribing to ·subjec-
tive’ and ‘objective’ views of society. The debate in many respects
takes its lead from the publication in France in 1966 and Britain in
22 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
1969 of Louis Althusser’s work For Marx. This presented the
notion of an •epistemological break’ in Marx’s work and emphas-
ised the polarisation of Marxist theorists into two camps: those
emphasising the •subjective’ aspects of Marxism (Lukacs and the
Frankfurt School, for example) and those advocating more ·objec-
tive’ approaches, such as that associated with Althusserian struc-
turalism.
Within the context of the sociologies both of regulation and
radical change, therefore, the middle to late 1960s witnessed a
distinct switch in the focus of attention. The debate between these
two sociologies which had characterised the early 1960s disap-
peared and was replaced by an introverted dialogue within the
conte”‘.t of each of the separate schools of thought. Instead of
•speaking’ to each other they turned inwards and addressed their
remarks to themselves. The concern to sort out their position with
regard to what we call the subjectiv~objective dimension, a
complicated process in view of all the interrelated strands, Jed to a
neglect of the regulation-radical change dimension.
As a consequence of these developments, recent debate has
often been confused. Sociological thought has tended to be charac-
terised by a narrow sectarianism, from which an overall perspec-
tive and grasp of basic issues are conspicuously absent. The time is
ripe for consideration of the way ahead, and we submit that the two
key dimensions of analysis which we have identified define critical
parameters within which this can take place. We present them as
THE SOCIOLOGY OF RADICAL CHANGE r———- ———–,
I I
1 I
1 I
1 “Radical ‘Radical 1
1 humanist’ structuralist• 1
I I
I I
I I
SUBJECTIVE 1 I OBJECTIVE
I I
I I
II I 1nterpretive” “Functionalist”
I I
I I
I I
I I
‘———– __________ J
THE SOCIOLOGY OF REGULATION
F”•re 1.1 Four paradipls for lhe ualysis ~ soa.llheory
Two Dimensions: Four ParadiRms 23
two independent dimensions which resurrect the sociological
issues of the early 1960s and place them alongside those of the late
1960s and early 1970s. Taken together, they define four distinct
sociological paradigms which can be utilised for the analysis of a
wide range of social theories. The relationship between these
paradigms, which we label ‘radical humanist’, ‘radical structural-
ist’, •interpretive’ and •functionalist’, is illustrated in Figure 3.1.
It will be clear from the diagram that each of the paradigms
shares a common set of features with its neighbours on the hori-
zontal and vertical axes in terms of one of the two dimensions but is
differentiated on the other dimension. For this reason they should
be viewed as contiguous but separate- contiguous because of the
shared characteristics, but separate because the differentiation is,
as we shall demonstrate later, of sufficient importance to warrant
treatment of the paradigms as four distinct entities. The four para-
digms define fundamentally different perspectives for the analysis
of social phenomena. They approach this endeavour from con-
trasting standpoints and generate quite different concepts and
analytical tools.
The Nature and Uses of the Four Paradigms
Before going on to discuss the substantive nature of each of the
paradigms, it will be as well to pay some attention to the way in
which we intend the notion of •paradigm’ to be used. 1 We regard
our four paradigms as being defined by very basic meta-theoretical
assumptions which underwrite the frame of reference, mode of
theorising and modus operandi of the social theorists who operate
within them. It is a term which is intended to emphasise the
commonality of perspective which binds the work of a group of
theorists together in such a way that they can be usefully regarded
as approaching social theory within the bounds of the same
problematic.
This definition does not imply complete unity of thought. It
allows for the fact that within the context of any given paradigm
there will be much debate between theorists who adopt different
standpoints. The paradigm does, however, have an underlying
unity in terms of its basic and often •taken for granted’ assump-
tions, which separate a group of theorists in a very fundamental
way from theorists located in other paradigms. The ·unity’ of the
paradigm thus derives from reference to alternative views of real-
24 SocioloRica/ ParadiRms and OrRanisational Ana/ysi.f
ity which lie outside its boundaries and which may not necessarily
even be recognised as existing.
In identifying four paradigms in social theory we are in essence
suggesting that it is meaningful to examine work in the subject area
in terms of four sets of basic assumptions. Each set identifies a
quite separate social-scientific reality. To be located in a particular
paradigm is to view the world in a particular way. The four para-
digms thus define four views of the social world based upon differ-
ent meta-theoretical assumptions with regard to the nature of
science and of society.
It is our contention that all social theorists can be located within
the context of these four paradigms according to the meta-
theoretical assumptions reflected in their work. The four para-
digms taken together provide a map for negotiating the subject
area, which offers a convenient means of identifying the basic
similarities and differences between the work of various theorists
and, in particular, the underlying frame of reference which they
adopt. It also provides a convenient way of locating one’s own
personal frame of reference with regard to social theory, and thus a
means of understanding why certain theories and perspectives
may have more personal appeal than others. Like any other-map, it
provides a tool for establishing where you are, where you have
been and where it is possible to go in the future. It provides a tool
for mapping intellectual journeys in social theory -one’s own and
those of the theorists who have contributed to the subject area.
In this work we intend to make much use of the map-like qual-
ities of the four paradigms. Each defines a range of intellectual
territory. Given the overall meta-theoretical assumptions which
distinguish one paradigm from another, there is room for much
variation within them. Within the context of the ‘functionalist’
paradigm, for example, certain theorists adopt more extreme posi-
tions in terms of one or both of the two dimensions than others.
Such differences often account for the internal debate which goes
on between theorists engaged in the activities of ‘normal science’
within the context of the same paradigm. 2 The remaining chapters
of this work examine each of the four paradigms in some detail and
attempt to locate their principal theorists in these terms.
Our research suggests that whilst the activity within the context
of each paradigm is often considerable, inter-paradigmatic
‘journeys’ are much rarer. This is in keeping with Kuhn’s (1970)
notion of ·revolutionary science’. For a theorist to switch para-
digms calls for a change in meta-theoretical assumptions, some-
thing which, although manifestly possible, is not often achieved in
Two Dimensions: Four ParadiRmS 25
practice. As Keat and Urry put it, ‘For individual scientists, the
change of allegiance from one paradigm to another is often a
.. conversion experience”, akin to Gestalt-switches or changes of
religious faith’ ( 1975, p. SS). When a theorist does shift his position
in this way, it stands out very clearly as a major break with his
intellectual tradition and is heralded as being so in the literature, in
that the theorist is usually welcomed by those whom he has joined
and often disowned by his former ‘paradigm colleagues’. Thus we
witness what is known as the ‘epistemological break’ between the
work of the young Marx and the mature Marx – what we would
identify as a shift from the radical humanist paradigm to the radical
structuralist paradigm. At the level of organisational analysis, a
distinct paradigm shift can be detected in the work of Silverman –
a shift from the functionalist paradigm to the interpretive para-
digm. We will analyse such intellectual journeys in more detail in
later chapters.
Before we progress to a review ofthe four paradigms, one point
is worthy offurther emphasis. This relates to the fact that the four
paradigms are mutually exclusive. They offer alternative views of
social reality, and to understand the nature of all four is to under-
stand four different views of society. They offer different ways of
seeing. A synthesis is not possible, since in their pure forms they
are contradictory, being based on at least one set of opposing
meta-theoretical assumptions. They are alternatives, in the sense
that one can operate in different paradigms sequentially over time,
but mutually exclusive, in the sense that one cannot operate in
more than one paradigm at any given point in time, since in accept-
ing the assumptions of one, we defy the assumptions of all the
others.
We offer the four paradigms for consideration in these terms, in
the hope that knowledge of the competing points of view will at
least make us aware of the boundaries within which we approach
our subject.
The Functionalist Paradigm
This paradigm has provided the dominant framework for the con-
duct of academic sociology and the study of organisations. It
represents a perspective which is firmly rooted in the sociology of
regulation and approaches its subject matter from an objectivist
point of view. Functionalist theorists have been at the forefront of
26 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
the order-conflict debate, and the concepts which we have used
to categorise the sociology of regulation apply in varying degrees
to all schools of thought within the paradigm.lt is characterised by
a concern for providing explanations of the status quo, social
order, consensus, social integration, solidarity, need satisfaction
and actuality. It approaches these general sociological concerns
from a standpoint which tends to be realist, positivist, determinist
and nomothetic.
The functionalist paradigm generates regulative sociology in its
most fully developed form. In its overall approach it seeks to
provide essentially rational explanations of social affairs. It is a
perspective which is highly pragmatic in orientation, concerned to
understand society in a way which generates knowledge which can
be put to use. It is often problem-orientated in approach, con-
cerned to provide practical solutions to practical problems. It is
usually firmly committed to a philosophy of social engineering as a
basis of social change and emphasises the importance of under-
standing order. equilibrium and stability in society and the way in
which these can be maintained. It is concerned with the effective
·regulation· and control of social affairs.
As will be apparent from our discussion in Chapter I the
approach to social science characteristic of the functionalist para-
digm is rooted in the tradition of sociological positivism. This
reflects the attempt, par excellence, to apply the models and
methods of the natural sciences to the study of human affairs.
Originating in France in the early decades of the nineteenth
century. its major influence upon the paradigm has been through
the work of social theorists such as Auguste Comte. Herbert
Spencer. Emile Durkheim and Vilfredo Pareto. The functionalist
approach to social science tends to assume that the social world is
composed of relatively concrete empirical artefacts and relation-
ships which can be identified. studied and measured through
approaches derived from the natural sciences. The use of mechan-
ical and biological analogies as a means of modelling and under-
standing the social world is particularly favoured in many
functionalist theories. By way of illustration consider. for exam-
ple. the work of Durkheim. Central to his position was the idea that
•social facts’ exist outside of men’s consciousness and restrain
men in their everyday activities. The aim was to understand the
relationships between these ‘objective’ social facts and to articu-
late the sociology which explained the types of ·solidarity’ provid-
ing the ‘social cement’ which holds society together. The stability
and ordered nature of the natural world was viewed as characteris-
Two Dimensions: Four Paradigms 27
ing the world of human affairs. For Durkheim. the task of
sociology was to understand the nature of this regulated order.
Since the early decades of the twentieth century. however. the
functionalist paradigm has been increasingly influenced by ele-
ments from the German idealist tradition of social thought. As will
be recalled from our discussion in Chapter I, this approach reflects
assumptions about the nature of social science which stand in
opposition to those of sociological positivism. As a result of the
work of such theorists as Max Weber, George Simmel and George
Herbert Mead. elements of this idealist approach have been util-
ised within the context of social theories which have attempted to
bridge the gulf between the two traditions. In so doing they have
forged theoretical perspectives characteristic of the least objectiv-
ist region of the paradigm, at its junction with the interpretive
paradigm. Such theories have rejected the use of mechanical and
biological analogies for studying the social world and have
introduced ideas which place emphasis upon the importance of
understanding society from the point of view of the actors who are
actually engaged in the performance of social activities.
Since the 1940s there has been also an infusion of certain Marxist
influences characteristic of the sociology of radical change. These
have been incorporated within the paradigm in an attempt to
·radicalise’ functionalist theory and rebuff the general charge that
L———–THE SOCIOLOGY OF
REGULATION Sociological
positivism
Figure 3.2 Intellectual influences upon the functionalist paradigm
28 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
functionalism is essentially conservative and unable to provide
explanations for social change. These attempts underwrite the
debate examined in the previous chapter as to whether a theory of
·conflict’ can be incorporated within the bounds of a theory of
‘order’ to provide adequate explanations of social affairs.
Put very crudely, therefore, the formation of the functionalist
paradigm can be understood in terms of the interaction of three
sets of intellectual forces, as illustrated in Figure 3.2. Of these,
sociological positivism has been the most influential. The compet-
ing traditions have been sucked in and used within the context of
the functionalist problematic, which emphasises the essentially
objectivist nature of the social world and a concern for explana-
tions which emphasise ‘regulation’ in social affairs. These cross-
currents of thought have given rise to a number of distinctive
schools of thought within the paradigm, which is characterised by
a wide range of theory and internal debate. By way of overview,
again somewhat crudely, Figures 3.3 and 3.4 illustrate the four
paradigms in terms of the constituent schools of sociological and
organisational theory which we shall be exploring later on. As will
be apparent, most organisation theorists, industrial sociologists,
psychologists and industrial relations theorists approach their sub-
ject from within the bounds of the functionalist paradigm.
The Interpretive Paradigm
Theorists located within the context of the interpretive paradigm
adopt an approach consonant with the tenets of what we have
described as the sociology of regulation, though its subjectivist
approach to the analysis of the social world makes its links with
this sociology often implicit rather than explicit. The interpretive
paradigm is informed by a concern to understand the world as it is,
to understand the fundamental nature of the social world at the
level of subjective experience. It seeks explanation within the
realm of individual consciousness and subjectivity, within the
frame of reference of the participant as opposed to the observer of
action.
In its approach to social science it tends to be nominalist, anti-
po.’iitil•ist, volunwrist and ideographic. It sees the social world as
an emergent social process which is created by the individuals
concerned. Social reality. insofar as it is recognised to have any
existence outside the consciousness of any single individual, is
regarded as being little more than a network of assumptions and
S
U
B
JE
C
T
I\
/!
:L
..
._
_
m
T
H
E
S
O
C
IO
LO
G
Y
O
F
R
A
D
IC
A
L
C
H
A
N
G
E
P
he
no
m
en
ol
og
y
H
er
m
en
eu
tic
s
P
he
no
m
en
o-
lo
gi
ca
l
so
ci
ol
og
y
In
te
gr
at
iv
e
th
eo
ry
I n
te
ra
ct
io
ni
sm
an
d
so
ci
al
ac
tio
n
th
eo
ry
O
F
R
E
G
U
L
A
T
IO
N
R
us
si
an
so
ci
a
l
th
eo
ry
,,
,.
.
O
B
JE
C
T
IV
E
sy
st
em
th
e
o
ry
O
bj
ec
tiv
is
m
S
U
B
JE
C
TI
V
E
F
..
.
—
TH
E
S
O
C
IO
LO
G
Y
O
F
R
A
D
IC
A
L
C
H
A
N
G
E
R
ad
ic
al
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
n
th
e
o
ry
~
“-‘
_,_
,_”_
_
I ..
..
.,. .
~
–
….. _
·. ·.· ..
.. I
OBJ
E
C
TI
V
E
~
t
!
l
k
~
t
fi!J
7tf5
ti
:’l<
f'
''
vt
:~
;;
;~
:-
~
~W
''
''
""
t~
·
~
TH
E
.S
O
C
IO
LO
G
Y
O
F
R
E
G
U
LA
TI
O
N
P
lu
ra
lis
m
T
he
or
ie
s
S
oc
ia
l
o
f
sy
st
em
bu
re
au
cr
at
ic
th
eo
ry
dy
sf
un
ct
io
ns
O
bj
ec
tiv
is
m
Two Dimensions: Four Paradigms 31
intersubjectively shared meanings. The ontological status of the
social world is viewed as extremely questionable and problematic
as far as theorists located within the interpretive paradigm are
concerned. Everyday life is accorded the status of a miraculous
achievement. Interpretive philosophers and sociologists seek to
understand the very basis and source of social reality. They often
delve into the depths of human consciousness and subjectivity in
their quest for the fundamental meanings which underlie social
life.
Given this view of social reality, it is hardly surprising that the
commitment of the interpretive sociologists to the sociology of
regulation is implicit rather than explicit. Their ontological
assumptions rule out a direct interest in the issues involved in the
order-conflict debate as such. However, their standpoint is
underwritten by the assumption that the world of human affairs is
cohesive, ordered and integrated. The problems of conflict,
domination, contradiction, potentiality and change play no part in
their theoretical framework. They are much more orientated
towards obtaining an understanding of the subjectively created
social world •as it is • in terms of an ongoing process.
Interpretive sociology is concerned with understanding the
essence of the everyday world. In terms of our analytical schema it
is underwritten by an involvement with issues relating to the
nature of the status quo, social order, consensus, social integra-
tion and cohesion, solidarity and actuality. 3
The interpretive paradigm is the direct product of the German
idealist tradition of social thought. Its foundations were laid in the
work of Kant and reflect a social philosophy which emphasises the
essentially spiritual nature of the social world. The idealist tradi-
tion was paramount in Germanic thought from the mid-eighteentlt
century onwards and was closely linked with the romantic move-
ment in literature and the arts. Outside this realm, however, it was
of limited interest, until revived in the late 1890s and early years of
this century under the influence of the so-called neo-idealist
movement. Theorists such as Dilthey, Weber. Husser! and Schutz
have made a major contribution towards establishing it as a
framework for social analysis, though with varying degrees of
commitment to its underlying problematic.
Figures 3.3 and 3.4 illustrate the manner in which the paradigm
has been explored as far as our present interest in social theory and
the study of organisations is concerned. Whilst there have been a
small number of attempts to study organisational concepts and
situations from this point of view. the paradigm has not generated
32 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
much organisation theory as such. As will become clear from our
analysis. there are good reasons for this. The premises of the
interpretive paradigm question whether organisations exist in any-
thing but a conceptual sense. Its significance for the study of
organisations. therefore. is of the most fundamental kind. It
challenges the validity of the ontological assumptions which
underwrite functionalist approaches to sociology in general and
the study of organisations in particular.
The Radical Humanist Paradigm
The radical humanist paradigm is defined by its concern to develop
a sociology of radical change from a subjectivist standpoint. Its
approach to social science has much in common with that of the
interpretive paradigm. in that it views the social world from a
perspective which tends to be nominalist. anti-positivist, voluntar-
ist and ideographic. However. its frame of reference is committed
to a view of society which emphasises the importance of over-
throwing or transcending the limitations of existing social
arrangements.
One of the most basic notions underlying the whole of this
paradigm is that the consciousness of man is dominated by the
ideological superstructures with which he interacts. and that these
drive a cognitive wedge between himself and his true conscious-
ness. This wedge is the wedge of 'alienation' or 'false conscious-
ness', which inhibits or prevents true human fulfilment. The major
concern for theorists approaching the human predicament in these
terms is with release from the constraints which existing social
arrangements place upon human development. It is a brand of
social theorising designed to provide a critique of the status quo. It
tends to view society as anti-human and it is concerned to articu-
late ways in which human beings can transcend the spiritual bonds
and fetters which tie them into existing social patterns and thus
realise their full potential.
In terms of the elements with which we have sought to concep-
tualise the sociology of radical change, the radical humanist places
most emphasis upon radical change, modes of domination, eman-
cipation, deprivation and potentiality. The concepts of structural
conflict and contradiction do not figure prominently within this
perspective, since they are characteristic of more objectivist views
of the social world, such as those presented within the context of
the radical structuralist paradigm.
Two Dimensions: Four Paradigms 33
In keeping with its subjectivist approach to social science, the
radical humanist perspective places central emphasis upon human
consciousness. Its intellectual foundations can be traced to the
same source as that of the interpretive paradigm. It derives from
the German idealist tradition, particularly as expressed in the work
of Kant and Hegel (though as reinterpreted in the writings of the
young Marx).lt is through Marx that the idealist tradition was first
utilised as a basis for a radical social philosophy, and many radical
humanists have derived their inspiration from this source. In
essence Marx inverted the frame of reference reflected in Hegelian
idealism and thus forged the basis for radical humanism. The
paradigm has also been much influenced by an infusion of the
phenomenological perspective deriving from Husser).
As we shall illustrate in our detailed discussion of this paradigm,
apart from the early work of Marx, interest remained dormant until
the 1920s, when Lukacs and Gramsci revived interest in subjectiv-
ist interpretations of Marxist theory. This interest was taken on by
members of the so-called Frankfurt School, which has generated a
great deal of debate, particularly through the writings of Habermas
and Marcuse. The existentialist philosophy of Sartre also belongs
to this paradigm, as do the writings of a group of social theorists as
widely diverse as lllich, Castaneda and Laing. All in their various
ways share a common concern for the release of consciousness
and experience from domination by various aspects of the ideolog-
ical superstructure of the social world within which men live out
their lives. They seek to change the social world through a change
in modes of cognition and consciousness.
Figures 3.3 and 3.4 again provide a somewhat rough and ready
summary of the manner in which this paradigm has been explored
in terms of social theory and the study of organisations. As we shall
argue in Chapter 9. the writers who have something to say on
organisations from this perspective have laid the basis of a nascent
anti-organisation theory. The radical humanist paradigm in
essence is based upon an inversion of the assumptions which
define the functionalist paradigm. It should be no surprise, there-
fore, that anti-organisation theory inverts the problematic which
defines functionalist organisation theory on almost every count.
The Radical Structuralist Paradigm
Theorists located within this paradigm advocate a sociology of
radical change from an objectivist standpoint. Whilst sharing an
34 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
approach to science which has many similarities with that of func-
tionalist theory, it is directed at fundamentally different ends.
Radical structuralism is committed to radical change, emancipa-
tion, and potentiality, in an analysis which emphasises structural
co'fflict, modes of domination, contradiction and deprivation. It
approaches these general concerns from a standpoint which tends
to be realist. positivist. determinist and nomothetic.
Whereas the radical humanists forge their perspective by focus-
ing upon ·consciousness' as the basis for a radical critique of
society, the radical structuralists concentrate upon structural rela-
tionships within a realist social world. They emphasise the fact that
radical change is built into the very nature and structure of con-
temporary society, and they seek to provide explanations of the
basic interrelationships within the context of total social forma-
tions. There is a wide range of debate within the paradigm, and
different theorists stress the role of different social forces as a
means of explaining social change. Whilst some focus directly
upon the deep-seated internal contradictions, others focus upon
the structure and analysis of power relationships. Common to all
theorists is the view that contemporary society is characterised by
fundamental conflicts which generate radical change through
political and economic crises. It is through such conflict and
change that the emancipation of men from the social structures in
which they live is seen as coming about.
This paradigm owes its major intellectual debt to the work of the
mature Marx, after the s~called ·epistemological break' in his
work. It is the paradigm to which Marx turned after a decade of
active political involvement and as a result of his increasing inter-
est in Darwinian theories of evolution and in political economy.
Marx's basic ideas have been subject to a wide range of interpreta-
tions in the hands of theorists who have sought to follow his lead.
Among these Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin and Bukharin have been
particularly influential. Among the leading exponents of the radi-
cal structuralist position outside the realm of Russian social
theory, the names of Althusser. Poulantzas, Colletti and various
Marxist sociologists of the New Left come to mind. Whilst the
influence of Marx upon the radical structuralist paradigm is
undoubtedly dominant, it is also possible to identify a strong
Weberian influence. As we shall argue in later chapters, in recent
years a group of social theorists have sought to explore the inter-
face between the thought of Marx and Weber and have generated a
distinctive perspective which we describe as ·conflict theory'. It is
to this radical structuralist perspective that the work of Dahren-
Two Dimensions: Four ParadiRms 3S
dorf belongs, along with that of other theorists such as Rex and
Miliband.
Figures 3.3 and 3.4 again provide a general overview of the
schools of thought located within the paradigm, which we shall be
examining in some detail in Chapters 10 and II. In British and
American sociology the radical structuralist view has received
relatively little attention outside the realm of conflict theory. This
paradigm. located as it is within a realist view of the social world,
has many significant implications for the study of organisations,
but they have only been developed in the barest forms. In Chapter
11 we review the work which has been done and the embryonic
radical orKanisation theory which it reflects.
Exploring Social Theory
So much, then. for our overview of the four paradigms. Sub-
sequent chapters seek to place flesh upon the bones of this analyti-
caJ scheme and attempt to demonstrate its power as a tool for
exploring social theory. 4 Hopefully. our discussion will do justice
to the essentially complex nature of the paradigms and the network
of assumptions which they reflect, and will establish the relation-
ships and links between the various perspectives dominating social
analysis at the present time. Whilst the focus in Chapters s. 7. 9and
11 is upon organisational analysis, the general principles and ideas
discussed in the work as a whole clearly have relevance for the
exploration of a wide variety of other social science disciplines.
The scope for applying the analytical scheme to other fields of
study is enormous but unfortunately lies beyond the scope of our
present enquiry. However, readers interested in applying the
scheme in this way should find little difficulty in proceeding from
the sociological analyses presented in Chapters4, 6, 8, and 10 to an
analysis of the literature in their own sphere of specialised interest.
Notes and References
1. For a full discussion of the role of paradigms in scientific
development, see Kuhn ( 1970).1n his analysis, paradigms are
defined as •universally recognised scientific achievements
that for a time provide model problems and solutions to a
36 Soc-iological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
community of practitioners' (p. viii). Paradigms are regarded
as governing the progress of what is called 'normal science·,
in which 'the scientist's work is devoted to the articulation
and wider application of the accepted paradigm, which is not
itself questioned or criticised. Scientific problems are
regarded as puzzles, as problems which are known to have a
solution within the framework of assumptions implicitly or
explicitly embodied in the paradigm. If a puzzle is not solved,
the fault lies in the scientist, and not in the paradigm· (Keat
and Urry 1975, p. 55). 'Normal science' contrasts with rela-
tively brief periods of 'revolutionary science', in which 'the
scientist is confronted by increasingly perplexing anomalies,
which call into question the paradigm itself. Scientific revolu-
tion occurs when a new paradigm emerges, and becomes
accepted by the scientific community' (ibid., p. 55).
We are using the term ·paradigm' in a broader sense than
that intended by Kuhn. Within the context of the present
work we are arguing that social theory can be conveniently
understood in terms of the co-existence of four distinct and
rival paradigms defined by very basic meta-theoretical
assumptions in relation to the nature of science and society.
'Paradigms', 'problematics', 'alternative realities'. 'frames
of reference'. 'forms of life' and ·universe of discourse' are
all related conceptualisations although of course they are not
synonymous.
2. Some inter-paradigm debate is also possible. Giddens main-
tains 'that all paradigms ... are mediated by others' and that
within 'normal science' scientists are aware of other para-
digms. He posits that: 'The process of learning a para-
digm ... is also the process of learning what that paradigm is
not' (1976, pp. 142-4).
Interestingly, he confines his discussion to the mediation
of one paradigm by another one. We believe that a model of
four conflicting paradigms within sociology is more accurate
and that academics' knowledge of 'scientists' within the
other three paradigms is likely to be very sketchy in some
cases. Relations between paradigms are perhaps better
described in terms of 'disinterested hostility' rather than
'debate'.
3. The notion of need satisfaction derives from the use of a
biological analogy of an organism and plays no part in
interpretive sociology.
4. The sociological concerns of recent years have resulted in a
Two Dimensions: Four ParadiRms 37
number of works which have aimed to chart a path through
the social science literature by reducing the variables of
sociological analysis to a number of key dimensions. Those
of Dahrendorf (1959), Wallace (1969}, Gouldner (1970),
Friedrichs (1970), Dawe ( 1970), Robertson ( 1974), Keat and
Urry (1975), Strasser (1976) and Benton (1977) all readily
come to mind. In a sense our work adds to this literature. Had
space permitted, we would have liked to demonstrate the
precise way in which the schemes proposed by these various
authors all fall, in a partial way, within the bounds of the
scheme developed here.
http://taylorandfrancis.com
Part II
The Paradigms Explore~d
http://taylorandfrancis.com
4. Functionalist Sociology
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The mode of social theorising which characterises this paradigm
has a long history. Indeed. its pedigree can be traced back to the
very roots of sociology as a discipline, and the early attempts of
social philosophers to apply the ideas and methods of natural
science to the realm of social affairs. It is a paradigm which, in
many respects, has developed as a branch of the natural sciences
and, to this day, in disciplines as avowedly ·social' as sociology,
psychology, economics, anthropology and the like, natural sci-
ence models and methods reign supreme in various areas of
enquiry.
Given such an extensive history, it is difficult to locate a precise
starting point. Elements of the paradigm can be traced back to the
political and social thought of the ancient Greeks but, for conveni-
ence, we shall commence our analysis with the work of Auguste
Comte ( 1798 -1857), commonly regarded as the founding father of
·sociology' - in name if not entirely in substance.
As Raymond Aron has suggested, Comte may be regarded, first
and foremost, as 'the sociologist of human and social unity' (Aron,
1965, p. 59). He believed that knowledge and society was in a
process of evolutionary transition, and that the function of socio-
logy was to understand the necessary, indispensable and inevit-
able course of history in such a way as to promote the realisation of
a new social order. From Comte's point of view this evolution
passed through three stages of development - 'the Theological, or
fictitious; the Metaphysical, or abstract; and the Scientific, or
positive'. He defined the positive mode of thought in the following
terms: 'In the final, the positive state, the mind has given over the
vain search after absolute notions, the origin and destination of the
universe and the causes of phenomena, and applies itself to the
study of their laws, i.e. their invariable relations of succession and
resemblance. Reasoning and observation duly combined are the
means ofthis knowledge' (Comte, 1853, vol.l, pp. 1-2). Comte's
vision was of a world in which scientific 'rationality' was in the
42 Sodologkul Paradigml· and Organisational Analysis
ascendancy, underlying the basis of a well regulated social order.
For Comte the ·positive' approach provided the key to man's
destiny or, as Aron has put it, the ·one type of society which is
absolutely valid' and at which 'all mankind must arrive' (Aron,
1965, p. 59).
Comte believed that all sciences passed through his three phases
of development but did so at different times according to their
complexity. He felt that the 'positive' method which had already
triumphed in mathematics, astronomy, physics and biology would
eventually prevail in politics and culminate in the founding of a
positive science of society, which is called sociology. His vision
was of a sociology based on the models and methods employed in
the natural sciences, addressing itself to the discovery of scientific
laws which explain the relationships between various parts of
society - 'social statics' - and the way in which they change over
time- ·social dynamics'. In his writings Comte made much of the
link between biology and social science. He saw biology as mark-
ing a decisive point of transition between sciences, in that it
marked a distinction between the 'organic' and 'inorganic' and
placed emphasis upon understanding and explanation within the
totality of the living whole (Comte, 1853, vol. II, pp. 111-26).
Comte thus laid the foundations for the mode of social theorising
characteristic of the functionalist paradigm. Based upon the 'posi-
tive' model of the natural sciences, utilising mechanical and
organic analogies, distinguishing between statics (structure) and
dynamics (process), and advocating methodological holism,
Comte initiated important ground rules for a sociological
enterprise geared to an explanation of social order and
regulation.
Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) had a m~or influence on
developments in sociology in the 1870s and 1880s. A 'positivist' in
the Comtian tradition, his principal contribution was to develop in
a more detailed and extensive manner the implications of the
biological analogy for sociology. Influenced by the work of
Darwin, he saw the study of sociology as the study of evolution in
its most complex form. Whilst regarding society as a son of organ-
ism, he used the analogy flexibly, as an explanatory instrument
yielding, in his words, a 'treasure of insights and hypotheses'. His
work did much to lay the foundations for the analysis of social
phenomena in terms of 'structure' and 'function', elaborating
Comte's notion of totality and the need to understand the parts in
the context of the whole. In this respect, however, he was more of
a methodological individualist than Comte, maintaining that the
Functionalist Sociology 43
properties of the aggregate are determined by the properties of its
units.
Many of the notions underpinning what we now know as
structural functionalism derive from Spencer's work. In particular
the parallels which he drew between societies and organisms, and
the view that the parts of society function in ways which contribute
to the maintenance of the whole, have been highly influential.
Spencer's view of society was that of a self-regulating system
which could be understood through study of its various elements
or organs and the manner in which they are interrelated. He saw
society as being set on an evolutionary course of development in
which changes of structure were characterised by a process of
increasing differentiation and increasing integration. The highly
developed social form was, for him, characterised by both
diversity and integration. The idea of evolution had universal
applicability and was the key to the understanding of both the
social and the natural world.
It is a point of considerable importance that in developing the
analogy between the biological and social, Spencer's focus of
attention was primarily, though not exclusively, directed at the
level of the organism rather than the species. Societies were seen
as ·super-organisms'. This organismic frame of reference emphas-
ises the unity, interdependence and ordered nature of constituent
relationships. A somewhat different view emerges from an
analysis conducted at the level of the species. As Buckley has
noted, 'the particular level of biological organisation that is chosen
as the basis for a model of society determines (or may be
determined by) whether we see society as pre-eminently co-
operative or basically conflictual. If society is like an organism,
then its parts co-operate and do not compete in a struggle for
survival, but if society is like an ecological aggregate, then the
Darwinian (or Hobbesian) model of competitive struggle is more
applicable' (Buckley, 1967, pp. 12-13). Whilst Spencer did draw
parallels between the evolution of societies and the evolution of
species - emphasising the role of conflict, including warfare, as a
force for social change - it was within the context of a theoretical
perspective which emphasised the inevitable march towards more
complex and integrated social systems. Industrial society was
viewed at its most advanced form. As Parsons has commented,
'Spencer's god was Evolution, sometimes also called Progress.
Spencer was one of the most vociferous in his devotions to this
god, but by no means alone among the faithful. With many other
social thinkers he believed that man stood near the culminating
44 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
point of a long linear process extending back unbroken, without
essential changes of direction, to the dawn of primitive man'
(Parsons, 1949, p. 4).
Emile Durkheim (1858-1917) explicitly recognised the
influence of Comte and Spencer upon his sociological thought, but
he approached their work in a critical vein. As Lukes ( 1973) has
noted, Comte' s influence on Durkheim was a formative rather than
a continuing one, the extension of the ·positive·, or scientific
attitude to the study of society probably being most important.
Although Durkheim specifically dissociated himself from many of
Comte's beliefs, he was firmly influenced by the Comtian notion of
a concrete social reality capable of rational scientific investigation.
This is reflected in the Durkheimian notion of the objective reality
of ·social facts'. Durkheim recognised that Comte had oversim-
plified this reality, ignoring the way in which ·society' comprised
different 'types' and 'species'. In this respect Durkheim found
Spencer's analysis more acceptable, and he incorporated many of
Spencer's insights, derived from the use of the organic analogy,
into his analysis of social institutions.
For Durkheim, however, sociology had to go much further. He
did not believe that an analysis of the parts which existed in the
social organism and the role they performed was adequate as an
end of sociological analysis. In particular, he criticised those
sociologists who 'think they have accounted for a phenomenon
once they have shown how they are useful, what role they play,
reasoning as if facts existed only from the point of view of this role
and with no other determining cause than the sentiment, clear or
confused, of the services they are called to render· (Durkheim,
1938. p. 89). Durkheim believed that causal analysis was required
in addition to what we would now call functional analysis: 'To
show how a fact is useful is not to explain how it originated or why
it is what it is. The uses which it serves pre-suppose the specific
properties characterising it but do not create them ... When, then,
the explanation of a social phenomenon is undertaken, we must
seek separately the efficient cause which piOduces it and the
function it fulfills' (Durkheim, 1938, p. 89). In terms of method,
therefore, Durkheim, following Comte and Spencer, borrowed
freely from the natural sciences. A methodological holist, distingu-
ishing between causes, functions and structures, he added much in
terms of sophistication to the thought of these earlier theorists and,
as will become apparent later, provided a firm foundation for
subsequent work within the context of the functionalist paradigm.
In terms of the nature of his social theorising, Durkheim is firmly
Functionali.ft Socioloxy 4S
located within the context of the sociology of regulation. From the
early 1880s Durkheim addressed himself to the study of the rela-
tions between the individual and society and the relations between
individual personality and social solidarity. He was concerned
with nothing less than the nature of social solidarity itself- with
the nature of the bonds which unite men. As Lukes has noted,
This, indeed, was the problem that remained central to the whole of
Durkheim"s life work: as he was to write in a letter to Bougie, 'the
object of sociology as a whole is to determine the conditions for the
conservation of societies'. At this early period the problem posed itself
as a question of determining the nature of social solidarity in industrial
societies. as opposed to that in traditional or pre-industrial societies,
and of accounting for the historical transition from the latter to the
former. Later he was to turn to the study of 'elementary' or tribal
societies, and in particular. primitive religion, in order to determine the
nature of social solidarity in general. (Lukes, 1973, p. 139)
Durkheim saw, 'traditional societies' as being held together on the
basis of a ·mechanical solidarity' deriving from similarity of parts,
with the individual's ·conscience' a 'simple appendage ofthe col-
lective type, following it [the collective conscience] in all its
movements' (Durkheim, 1938, p. 148). The 'conscience collective'
was based on a system of shared values, norms and beliefs. In the
'industrial' society, with its extensive system of "division of
labour' and functional differentiation, he saw an ·organic solidar-
ity' arising from the interdependence of parts. It was a solidarity
based upon a normative system of values, beliefs and sentiments.
Durkheim recognised that in the process of transition from 'tradi-
tional' to 'industrial' societies solidarity could break down, creat-
ing a state of 'anomie' or normlessness. However, he saw this as an
abnormal state of affairs, a 'pathological' deviation from the
natural course of development. As Lukes notes, a major problem
with Durkheim's account of anomie was that
although it pinpointed the central ills of capitalism - unregulated
competition: class conflict; routinised, degrading, meaningless work -
it characterised them all as "abnormal'. This procedure tended to
hinder any full-scale investigation oftheircauses (which were assumed
not to be endemic), especially given the evolutionary optimism Durk-
heim espoused at this stage. They were to be explained by the tempor-
ary and transitional lack of the appropriate economic controls, the
appropriate norms governing industrial relations and the appropriate
forms for work organisation - a lack that would in due course be
46 Sociologic·a/ Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
remedied by allowing the operation of interdependent functions to
produce its natural consequences. (Lukes, 1973, p. 174)
Durkheim's sociology thus reflects a powerful predilection for
·order' as the predominant force in social affairs. Judged by the
yardstick by which we have defined the 'sociology of regulation' (a
concern for 'the .<;talus quo', 'social order'. 'consensus', 'social
integration and cohesion', 'solidarity', 'need satisfaction' and
'activity'), Durkheim emerges as a sociologist of 'order' and 'regu-
lation' par excellence.
A fuller account of the origins of the functionalist paradigm
would call for the analysis of the thought of a number of other
social theorists. Alfred Marshall, Max Weber, Vilfredo Pareto,
John Stuart Mill, Georg Simmel, George Herbert Mead and
William James, among others, all have a strong claim to be consi-
dered here along with the founding fathers. To pursue such a task,
however, would convert this work into a historical treatise well
beyond the requirements of its present purpose. We will give
specific consideration to the work of Simmel and Mead later in the
chapter, since their ideas are of direct relevance to an understand-
ing of the schools of sociological thought which are located in the
least objectivist regions of the functionalist paradigm. The work of
Weber is of similar importance, but we shall delay a full discussion
of this until Chapter 6. Weber's work can only be adequately
understood against the detailed background of German idealism,
which provided the foundations for the development of the
interpretive paradigm. Thus, although Weber's work belongs
within the functionalist paradigm, we also discuss it in our chapter
on the interpretive paradigm, to aid the presentation and intelligi-
bility of our analysis as a whole. Readers who are unfamiliar with
Weber's sociology are invited to consult Chapter 6 at appropriate
points of discussion in this and the next chapter.
We conclude our discussion of the foundations of the functional-
ist paradigm here with a discussion of certain aspects of the work
of Pareto.' It can be argued that the attention which he is often
given in reviews of the development of social theory perhaps
inflates his true importance in terms of the originality and sophisti-
cation of his ideas. His significance derives mainly from the con-
siderable impact which his work has had upon the development of
twentieth-century sociological thought, particularly through L. J.
Henderson and the Harvard School of sociologists, who fostered
what came to be known as the 'Pareto cult' during the 1930s at a
particularly important and formative stage in the history of socio-
Functionalist Sociology 41
logy. As will become apparent from our discussion in this and the
next chapter, for this reason alone Pareto's influence calls for
consideration in any review of the background to the functionalist
paradigm.
Vilfredo Pareto ( 1848-1923) came to sociology from economics,
with a view to supplementing the scientific theories of economics,
based on their assumptions of logical and rational conduct, with a
scientific theory of non-logical or non-rational conduct. The object
of his main sociological work A Treatise on General Sociology,
first published in 1916, was toconstructarigoroussociology which
gave due recognition to the irrational elements in human behaviour.
In his words. its sole purpose was •to seek experimental reality.
by the application to the social sciences ofthe methods which have
proved themselves in physics, in chemistry, in astronomy, in
biology, and in other such sciences' (Pureto, 1934, p. 291).
Among the main features of his work which are relevant for
comment here are the fact that after establishing the extent and
significance of the non-logical in social affairs, he proceeded to
explain it in terms of a social systems model based upon the notion
of equilibrium. His view of society was that of a system of interre-
lated parts which, though in a continual state of surface flux, were
also in a state of unchanging equilibrium, in that movements away
from the equilibrium position were counterbalanced by changes
tending to restore it. Pareto saw in the concept of equilibrium a
useful tool for understanding the complexities of social life. In the
physical sciences it had provided a means of analysing the rela-
tionship between variables in a state of mutual dependence, and it
had been used successfully in the field of economics. Pareto
extended it to the social sphere, viewing society as determined by
the forces acting upon it.
Pareto's equilibrium model of society was thus based upon a
mechanical as opposed to a biological analogy. In contrast to the
theories of Spencer and Durkheim, he took his main point of
reference from the physical sciences. This is not to say that Pareto
saw the physical and social worlds as being identical in nature;
rather, he saw models derived from the former as having heuristic
utility for the analysis of the latter. This is the role which the notion
of equilibrium played in his scheme.lt was a scientific construct to
be used for the analysis of social reality. This distinction between
equilibrium as an analytical construct and equilibrium as an empir-
ical reality was by no means always spelt out as clearly as it might
have been, and subsequent social theorists who followed Pareto's
lead often adopted the equilibrium notion in its entirety.
48 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
As far as the development of the functionalist paradigm is con-
cerned, it is through the notion of equilibrium that Pareto has had
most influence. Whereas it was implicit in many earlier social
theories, after Pareto it became much more explicit as a guiding
principle. The distinction which he drew between the logical and
non-logical elements in human conduct has, as we shall see, also
been of some importance.
The Structure of the Paradigm
The functionalist paradigm has provided the dominant framework
for academic sociology in the twentieth century and accounts for
by far the largest proportion of theory and research in the field of
organisation studies.
Its structure reflects the dominant influence of sociological
positivism, as described in the previous section, fused at its junc-
tion with the interpretive paradigm with elements of German ideal-
ism. It contains many separate schools ofthought, each occupying
a distinctive relationship one with another. Our task in the remain-
der of this chapter is to trace these relationships in terms of the two
dimensions which define the paradigm.
To facilitate this task, we identify four broad categories offunc-
tionalist thought and address each in turn. We describe them as: (a)
social system theory, (b) interactionism and social action theory,
(c) integrative theory, (d) objectivism.
Each of these broad categories occupies a distinctive position
within the paradigm, as illustrated in Figure 3.3 Social system
theory represents a direct development of sociological positivism
in its most pure form. Adopting mechanical and biological
analogies for the study of social affairs, it is most clearly re-
presented in the schools of thought described as structural
functionalism and systems theory.
lnteractionism and social action theory is the category of
thought which directly combines elements of sociological positiv-
ism and German idealism and, as such, can be considered as
defining the most subjectivist boundary of the paradigm.
Integrative theory occupies a central location within the para-
digm, seeking to bridge the gap between social system theory and
interactionism. It is not fully committed to either of these two
categories: it takes something from both and contributes some-
thing to both. It is truly a brand of theory characteristic of the
middle ground, and is reflected in the schools of thought which we
Functionalist Sociology 49
des.cribe as conflict functionalism. morphogenic systems theory,
Blau's theory of exchange and power, and Mertonian theory of
social and cultural structure.
The category ofthought which we describe as objectivism (com-
prising behaviourism and abstracted empiricism) is very closely
related to social system theory, in that it again is firmly committed
to the tradition of sociological positivism. We identify it as a
separate category, in recognition of the fact that it reflects a par-
ticularly extreme form of commitment to the models and methods
of the natural sciences. Behaviourism, for example, derives from
physiological models employed in psychology. Abstracted empiri-
cism is dominated by quantitative methodologies which often have
no distinctly social qualities.
We commence our analysis with a consideration of social sys-
tem theory.
Social System Theory
Under this heading we consider two schools of thought which, in
many respects, have provided the dominant framework for
analysis in contemporary sociology - structural functionalism and
systems theory. Both have had a particularly important impact
upon the field of organisational analysis.
The terms 'structural functionalism· and 'systems theory' are
often seen as interchangeable. Whilst there is some measure of
justification in equating the two as far as the majority of current
systems applications are concerned, to do so represents an over-
simplification, since systems theory is consistent with theoretical
perspectives which extend beyond the confines of the functionalist
paradigm. However, these remain largely undeveloped at the pre-
sent time. In the following sections we trace the development of
the two perspectives and the relationships which exist between
them, arguing that the similarities only exist if they draw upon a
similar analogy, that of the biological organism. Whereas struc-
tural functionalism inevitably draws upon this analogy, systems
theory is in principle consistent with the use of many others.
Structural functionalism
It is through the notion of structural functionalism that the use of
the biological analogy in the tradition ofComte, Spencer and Otuk-
SO Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
heim has had its major impact upon sociological thought. Building
upon the concepts of holism, interrelationship between parts,
structure, functions and needs, the biological analogy has been
developed in diverse ways to produce a social science perspective
firmly rooted in the sociology of regulation. Treating the external
social world as a concrete reality, governed by observable func-
tional relations amenable to scientific investigation through
nomothetic methods, structural functionalism developed as the
dominant paradigm for sociological analysis during the first half of
the twentieth century. Indeed, by the 1950s its influence was so
pervasive that in certain quarters functional analysis was equated
with sociological analysis per se (Davis, 1959).
Significantly, it was not within sociology itself that structural
functionalism received its first coherent expression as a theory and
method of analysis. This took place within the realm of social
anthropology, an area of enquiry which, in addressing itself
primarily to the study of small-scale societies, provided an ideal
situation for the application of holistic views of society in a man-
ageable empirical context. Two names stand out as particularly
influential in this endeavour - those of Malinowski and
Radcliffe-Brown. 2
Malinowski's overriding contribution was to establish the
importance of field-work. Surprising as it may now seem, social
anthropology was predominantly an 'armchair' discipline. As Jar-
vie notes, 'with the exception of Morgan's study of the Iroquois
(1851), not a single anthropologist conducted field studies till the
end of the nineteenth century' (Jarvie, 1964, p. 2). Malinowski's
call was in effect to ·get off the verandah' and get involved in
field-work and direct observation. In opposition to the ·evolution-
ist' and 'diffusionist' explanations of primitive society prevalent in
the early 1920s, Malinowski advocated a 'functionalist' explana-
tion, which argued that the unusual or special characteristics of
primitive social systems could be understood in terms ofthefunc-
tions which they performed. His view was that society or ·culture'
should be regarded as a complex whole and understood in terms of
the relationships between its various parts and their ecological
surroundings. Social organisation, religion, language, economy,
political organisation, etc., were to be understood not so much as
reflecting a primitive mentality or stage of ·underdevelopment'
but in terms of the functions performed. In Malinowski's own
words, the functional analysis of culture.
aims at the explanation of anthropological facts at all levels of
development by their function, by the part which they play within the
Functionalist Sociology 51
integral system of culture, by the manner in which they are related to
each other within the system, and by the manner in which this system is
related to the physical surroundings. It aims at the understanding of the
nature of culture, rather than at conjectural reconstructions of its
evolution or of past historical events. (Malinowski, 1936, p. 132)
Malinowski developed the notion of functional analysis against the
prevailing orthodoxy in anthropology but without specifically
grounding it within the context of earlier social theory. Radcliffe-
Brown, on the other hand, was much more systematic in this
respect. He specifically recognised that the concept offunction, as
applied to human societies, was based upon an analogy between
social life and organic life,and that it had already received a certain
amount of consideration in philosophy and sociology. He took his
own particular starting point from the work of Durkheim and
sought to elaborate the parallels which existed between biological
organisms and human societies. 1
Radcliffe-Brown's analysis was a sophisticated one. He argued
that the concept of function in social science involved the assump-
tion that there are necessary conditions of existence for human
societies. Developing the analogy with animal organisms, he
argued that societies could be conceptualised as networks of rela-
tions between constituent parts - 'social structures' - which had
a certain continuity. In animal organisms the process by which this
structural continuity is maintained is called life. The same applies
in societies. Whilst recognising that societies in normal circum-
stances do not die in the manner of organisms, Radcliffe-Brown
argued that the ongoing life of a society could be conceived in
terms of the functioning of its structure - hence the notion of
'structural functionalism'. He illustrates his position as follows:
To turn from organic life to social life, if we examine such a community
as an African or Australian tribe we can recognise the existence of a
social structure. Individual human beings, the essential units in this
instance, are connected by a definite set of social relations into an
integrated whole. The continuity of the social structure,Jike that of our
organic structure, is not destroyed by changes in the units. Individuals
may leave the society, by death of otherwise; others may enter it. The
continuity of structure is maintained by the process of social life, which
consists of the activities and interactions of the individual human
beings and of the organised groups into which they are united. The
social life of the community is here defined as the functioning of the
social structure. The function of any recurrent activity, such as the
punishment of a crime, or a funeral ceremony, is the part it plays in the
52 Socio/of?ical ParadiF?ms and OrF?anisational Analysis
social life as a whole and therefore the contribution it makes to the
maintenance of the structural continuity.
The concept offunction as here defined thus involves the notion of a
structure consisting of a .~et of relations amongst unit entities. the
mntinuity of the structure being maintained by a /ife-proce.u made up
of the aC'li1·ities of the constituent unite;. (Radcliffe-Brown, 1952, p.
180)
Radcliffe-Brown saw this type of analysis as focusing attention
upon three sets of problems relevant to the investigation of human
society and of social life:
(a) The problems of social morphology - what kinds of social
structure are there? What are their similarities and differ-
ences? How are they to be classified?
(b) The problems of social physiology - how do social
structures function?
(c) The problems of development - how do new types of
social structure come into existence?
In specifying these problem areas, however, he was careful to
recognise that the organismic analogy had a number of limitations
as far as the study of society was concerned. First, whereas in the
case of organisms it was possible to study organic structure inde-
pendently of its functioning, in the case of societies it was not. As
he put it, 'in human society the social structure as a whole can only
be obsera•ed in its functioning' (Radcliffe-Brown, 1952, p. 181). In
other words, he placed emphasis upon the essentially processual
nature of social life, arguing that a social morphology could not be
established independently ofa social physiology. Second, he drew
attention to the problem of morphogenesis. Societies are able to
change and elaborate their structural types without any breach of
continuity; organisms cannot. As he put it, 'a pig does not become
a hippopotamus' ( 1952, p. 181). Third, he drew attention to the fact
that the functional analysis of society, with its emphasis upon the
contribution which the part makes to the continued existence and
functioning of the whole, is based upon the hypothesis of func-
tional unity .It implies that society has a 'functional unity' in which
'all parts of the social system work together with a sufficient
degree of harmony or internal consistency, i.e. without producing
persistent conflicts which can neither be resolved or regulated'
( 1952, p. 181). Radcliffe-Brown argued that functionalists should
test this hypothesis by systematic examination of the facts.
Functionalist Sociology 53
With Radcliffe-Brown, therefore, we arrive at a quite sophisti-
cated statement of the nature and limitations of the structural
functionalist perspective. It is a point of view which recognises the
processual relationship of mutual influence between structure and
its functioning, and the dangers involved in pursuing the analogy
between societies and organisms to an extreme. Not all functional-
ists were in complete agreement with Radcliffe-Brown, notably
Malinowski, and it is as well to draw attention to some of the
differences in points of view. Malinowski, for example, tended to
seek explanations of society in terms of basic human needs. His
version of functionalism tended to pursue the organismic analogy
to an extreme and often resulted in teleological explanations. This
was something Radcliffe-Brown consciously sought to avoid. He
recognised the self-fulfilling nature of explanations based on
·needs' at both the individual and social level, and preferred to talk
in terms of 'necessary conditions of existence'. This allowed for
the possibility of the existence of some social phenomena which
did not necessarily have a function to perform. Radcliffe-Brown
had a preference for explaining social phenomena in terms of their
·survival value' to the society. He saw social institutions as con-
tributing to the 'integration', 'stability' and ·maintenance' of the
social system as a whole. He explained the nature of society in
'social' terms above and beyond the needs of its individual mem-
bers. Though avoiding the problem of teleology, he ran danger-
ously close to the problem of reification. 4
Subsequent developments in the functionalist tradition have
drawn heavily upon the work of Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown
and have fanned out in many directions. Indeed, there has been
considerable debate over whether functionalism or structural
functionalism can be regarded as a unified approach, and a number
of varieties of functionalism have, in fact, been identified
(Demerath, 1966). The major distinction commonly drawn be-
tween approaches revolves around the issue of level of analysis:
whether the focus in functional analysis is on the part or the whole,
on the individual institution or the social system. In addition to this
distinction, however, it is also desirable to draw attention to at
least two other lines of development. The first follows on from
Radcliffe-Brown's focus on structure in the tradition of ·social
morphology' .In defiance (or at least ignorance) of his warning that
'the social structure as a whole can only be observed in its func-
tioning', the notion of structure has become increasingly reified as
some social theorists sought to identify its key elements. The
'search for structure' has led to an increasingly hard and indis-
.54 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
criminate application of the models and methods of the natural
sciences to the study of social phenomena. In an extreme though
pervasive form, much of contemporary structural functionalism
manifests itself in terms of a host of empirical snapshots of reified
social structures.s In the attempt to focus upon, define and meas-
ure 'structures', the notion of functional process - so central to
the conceptualisations of both Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown-
has been lost. There has been a swing towards a highly objectified
and static view of social reality - towards a positivism of an
extreme, narrowly empirical and, indeed, atheoretical form. We
shall pursue this in our discussion of abstracted empiricism later in
this chapter.
The second line of development has focused upon what
Radcliffe-Brown called the ·problems of social physiology', that
is, upon explaining the way in which social systems function. For
the most part these studies have drawn heavily upon the
organismic analogy, attempting to understand the functioning of
social systems in terms of system needs or conditions of existence.
This is particularly evident, for example, in the work of Talcott
Parsons and his analysis of the social system ( 1951). 6 Parsons takes
as his point of departure the system as a whole and analyses the
conditions necessary for its survival, functioning, evolution and
change. As Rocher notes, in Parsons' perspective 'the term func-
tion refers to various solutions to a particular complex of problems
that a system can adopt in order to survive, and 'survival' here
includes persistence, evolution and transmutation. So for Parsons,
functional analysis consists in establishing a classification of the
problems which every system must resolve in order to exist and
keep itself going' (Rocher, 1974, p. 155). This leads Parsons to the
notion of what are called 'functional prerequisites' or 'functional
imperatives' - the functions which must be performed if a society
is to survive. As Parsons has put it, ·any social system is subject to
four independent functional imperatives or "problems" which
must be met adequately if equilibrium and/or continuing existence
of the system is to be maintained' (Parsons, 1959, p. 16). These are
most clearly illustrated in his so-called AGIL scheme, which
identifies the four basic functional imperatives which Parsons
regards as being relevant to the analysis of all social systems. 7
Simply put, these are:
Adaption the complex of unit acts which serve to establish
relations between the system and its external
environment.
Functionalist Sociolol(y 55
Goal attainment
the actions which serve to define the goals ofthe
system and to mobilise and manage resources and
effort to attain goals and gratification.
Integration ~he unit acts which establish control, inhibit
deviancy, and maintain co-ordination between
parts, thus avoiding serious disturbance.
Latency or pattern maintenance
the unit acts which supply actors with necessary
motivation.
As Radcliffe-Brown noted, the notion of needs or conditions of
existence is implicit in the use of the analogy of a biological
organism for social analysis. In placing them at the centre of
analysis, however, Parsons ignores the limitations of this analogy
for the study of society which Radcliffe-Brown was so careful to
specify and redirects the main thrust of functionalist enquiry. Both
Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown had assumed that social
'structures' were implicit in the operation of social systems, and
that the problem of empirically based social analysis was to
identify the functions which the various elements of structure
performed. Parsons in effect inverts this problematic: starting with
the functions which must be performed, the problem of empirical
social science becomes that of identifying the structures or ele-
ments of social systems which serve given imperative functions.•
As David Lockwood (1956) has observed, Parsons' approach to
the analysis of the social system has been heavily weighted by
assumptions and categories which relate to the role of normative
elements in social action, and especially to the processes whereby
motives are structured normatively to ensure social stability. This
normative orientation has attracted the charge that Parsons'
scheme is inherently conservative, geared to a reaffirmation of the
status quo and unable to deal with change. 9 Parsons, in the tradi-
tion of Comte. Spencer and Durkheim, has underwritten his
approach by the implicit assumption that modern industrial society
rests at the pinnacle of human achievement, and that the pre-
dominant problem is that of regulation. As Lockwood notes, one
of the central themes emerging from Parsons' classic early work
The Structure of Social Action is that ·order is possible through the
existence of common norms which regulate .. the war of all against
all" • (Lockwood, 1956, p. 137). Parsons' later work strongly
reflects this basic orientation, though he has in fact been aware of
56 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
the need to make his model a dynamic one capable of accommodat-
ing and explaining change.
Valid as the charge of a normative orientation in Parsons' work
might be, it is also important to recognise that a certain degree of
conservatism is imposed by adherence to the organismic analogy
itself. 10 This is a point of particular significance in view of the fact
that many structural functionalists do not specifically follow Par-
sons' normative orientation. Although the Parsonian model is often
seen as dominating the contemporary structural functionalist
perspective, there are other models which have developed inde-
pendently. These other models also encounter difficulty in hand-
ling high degrees of change. As Radcliffe-Brown noted, this is a
limitation inherent in the use of the organismic analogy.
Radcliffe-Brown identified as his third set of problems those of
development - that is, how do new types of social structure come
into existence? It is of great significance that the structural
functionalists have had the most difficulty with this issue and that it
remains the least well explored.
Interestingly enough, the principal contributions to this problem
area have come from theorists who have sought to provide a
critique of structural functionalism as a whole or to provide alter-
native methods of analysis. Merton's contribution, for example,
provides a good illustration of the former and Buckley's mor-
phogenic systems theory an example of the latter. We will examine
both later in this chapter under the broad heading of integrative
theory. The positions which they develop represent a move away
from the dominant perspectives which characterise social system
theory; it takes these theorists to a different location within the
functionalist paradigm.
By way of summary, therefore, we conclude our discussion of
structural functionalism with the observation that from its start it
has been dominated by the use of biological analogy for the study
of society. Different varieties can be observed in practice. There
are those approaches which focus upon system parts rather than
upon systems as a whole. There are approaches in the tradition of
Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown which are most concerned with
establishing the functions which various elements of society per-
form. There are those which focus upon •social morphology' and
often result as abstracted empiricism. There are those which focus
upon functional imperatives or system needs and which seek to
analyse society in whole or part with this perspective in mind. All
these approaches adopt an approach to social science characteris-
tic of the objectivist region of the functionalist paradigm. Ontolog-
Functionalist SocioiOKY S1
ically, epistemologically and methodologically, structural func-
tionalism has been based upon models derived from the natural
sciences. For the most part, this has carried with it a relatively
determinist view with regard to human nature. In terms of its
characterisation of society, the overriding fact that the ·needs' or
·necessary conditions of existence' of social systems underwrite
the very notion of function has inevitably committed structural
functionalism to a perspective located within the sociology of
regulation.
The current state of structural functionalism ranges from ·grand
theory' to 'abstracted empiricism' with a general emphasis in the
latter upon structure rather than function. The notion of functional
process which was so important to its founding fathers has, for the
most part, either been ignored or lost. The qualifications which
were identified in drawing analogies between biological and social
phenomena seem largely to have gone astray. Fostered by
utilitarian demands for pragmatic theory and research geared to
piecemeal social engineering - political, managerial,.and the like
-theoretical insights have been largely submerged under a deluge
of empirical research. Indeed, structural functionalism as re-
presented in the work of Radcliffe-Brown has proved a rare and
transient phenomenon.
Systems theory
Since the early 1950s the 'systems approach' has assumed increas-
ing importance in various branches of social analysis. ! n sociology,
psychology, anthropology, archaeology, linguistics, organisation
theory, industrial relations and many other social science subjects,
systems theory has become established as an important method of
analysis. Among the more prominent studies, it is worth citing by
the way of illustration the work of Parsons (The Social System,
1951), Homans (The Human Group, 1950), Katz and Kahn (The
Social PsychoiOKY of Organisations, 1966), Easton (The Political
System, 1953) Dunlop (Industrial Relations Systems, 1958) and
Buckley (SocioiOKY and Modern Systems Theory, 1961).
Despite its popularity, however, the notion of •system' is an
elusive one. Many books on systems theory do not offer a formal
definition of the systems concept, and where a definition is attempt-
ed, it is usually one of considerable generality. 11 For example,
Angyal suggests that •there is a logical genus suitable to the treat-
S8 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
ment of wholes. We propose to call it system· (Angyal, 1941, p.
243). Again, in the words of von Bertalanffy, the founding father of
general systems theory, 'there are corresponoences in the princi-
ples which govern the behaviour of entities that are intrinsically,
widely different. This correspondence is due to the fact that they
all can be considered, in certain respects, as .. systems .. , that is,
complexes of elements standing in interaction' (von Bertalanffy,
1956, pp. 1-2).
The notions of 'holism' and 'interaction • of parts are not exclu-
sive to systems theory, and skeletal definitions such as these have
led many social scientists to the view that systems theory often
represents little more than old conceptualisations dressed up in
new and needlessly complex jargon. For many, it is another case of
the emperor having no clothes.
However, the situation is, in fact, much more sophisticated than
this. Von Bertalanffy wishes to use the notioo of ·system' as a
means of cutting through the substantive differences which exist
between different academic disciplines. The subject matter of
chemistry, physics, biology, sociology, etc., are linked in his view
by the fact that they study 'complexes of elements standing in
interaction', that is, ·systems'. The task of his general systems
theory is to discover the principles of organisation which underlie
such systems. One of his general aims is to achieve a ·unity of
science' based upon 'the isomorphy oflaws in different fields • (von
Bertalanffy, 1956, p. 8).
In many respects von Bertalanffy's aim can be regarded as
archetypical of the positivist perspective: it is based upon epis-
temological assumptions dominated by a concern to search for and
explain the underlying regularities and structural uniformities
which characterise the world in general. However, his perspective
differs from that of most positivists, in that he does not take his
point of departure from the traditions of conventional science.
Indeed, the contrary is true. Von Bertalanffy is firmly set against
the reductionism which characterises most areas of scientific
endeavour, with its emphasis upon modes of enquiry based upon
the methods and principles of conventional physics. He views his
general systems theory as providing an alternative to this; instead
of reducing all phenomena of study to physical events, he advo-
cates that we study them as systems. His positivism is thus of a
non-traditional kind and is dominated by the metaphor of 'system·
as an organising concept.
Von Bertalanffy makes much use of 'the limitations of conven-
tional physics' as a means of advocating his general systems
Functionalist SocioiOI~'V S9
approach. In this the difference between 'closed' and 'open' sys-
tems plays a very important part. Von Bertalanffy argues that
conventional physics deals mainly with closed systems, that is.
systems which are considered to be isolated from their environ-
ment. The method of the controlled experiment, in which the
subject of study is taken out of its environment and subjected to
various tests, provides a very good example of this. Such closed
systems are characterised by equilibrium. As von Bertalanffy puts
it, ·a closed system must, according to the second law of ther-
modynamics, eventually attain a time independent equilibrium
state, with maximum entropy and minimum free energy. where the
ratio between its phases remains constant' (von Bertalanffy. 1950).
Open systems are quite different, in that they are characterised
by an exchange with their environment. They engage in transac-
tions with their environment, 'importing' and •exporting' and
changing themselves in the process. 12 A living organism provides a
good example of an open system, since it maintains itself through a
process of exchange with its environment. during the course of
which there is a continuous building up and breaking down of
component parts. The concept of an open system is thus essen-
tially processual. Whilst a closed system must eventually obtain an
equilibrium state, an opens ystem will not. Given certain conditions,
an open system may achieve a steady state, homeostasis, in which
the system remains constant as a whole and in its phases. though
there is a constant flow of the component materials. However, such
a steady state is not a necessary condition of open systems.
This is a point of the utmost importance. and it needs to be
emphasised. An open system can take a wide variety of forms.
There are no general laws which dictate that it must achieve a
steady state, be goal directed, evolve. regress or disintegrate. In
theory. anything can happen. One of the purposes of open systems
theory is to study the pattern of relationships which characterise a
system and its relationship to its environment in order to under-
stand the way in which it operates. The open systems approach
does not carry with it the implication that any one particular kind of
analogy is appropriate for studying all systems. since it is possible
to discern different types of open system in practice.
The above point has not been clearly articulated and stressed in
the literature on systems theory, at least not in the systems litera-
ture most often read by social scientists. As far as most social
scientists are concerned, there are two types of system perspec-
tives - open and closed. The fact that the former encompasses a
whole range of possibilities is hardly ever recognised.
60 Sociological Paradigms and Organi.wtional Analysi.~
As a theoretical perspective in social science, the notion of a
closed system tends to be avoided like a dreaded disease. Von
Bertalanffy's argument that closed systems are characterised by
isolation from their environment has proved overwhelmingly suc-
cessful in persuading social theorists that the closed systems
approach is inappropriate as a guiding principle for the concep-
tualisation of social phenomena. Indeed, it has become almost
obligatory for social systems theorists to decry the inadequacies of
closed system theorising, and the sport of attacking exponents of
this now redundant perspective has become an extremely popular
one. In the field of organisation studies, for example, an attack
upon the closed system thinking implicit in Weber's model of
bureaucracy or classical management theory provides a conve-
nient springboard for lauding the praises of the contemporary
perspective of open systems theory.
Paradoxically, however, as a method of analysis the notion of a
closed system is still dominant in many areas of social enquiry. The
use of controlled experiments and interview programmes, and the
attempt to measure social phenomena through attitude ques-
tionnaires, all provide examples of closed system methodologies
based upon the assumption that the environment generated by the
investigation has no impact upon the subject of study. The paradox
is compounded by the fact that such dosed system methodologies
are often employed within the context of theoretical perspectives
which emphasise the importance of an open systems approach.
This link between theory and method is an extremely problematic
one in many areas of social science.
Despite the widely recognised deficiencies of the closed system
as a theoretical construct in social science, the full implications of
an open systems approach have not been pursued in any real
depth. The concept has been adopted in a very partial and often
misleading way. For many theorists, the adoption of an open
systems perspective has been a very limited venture, confined to
recognising and emphasising the environment as ani nfluence upon
the subject of study and reformulating traditional models in terms
of systems concepts. More than anything, the call to adopt an open
systems approach has been interpreted as a call to take heed of the
environment and often little else. As Buckley has noted, 'though
there is a fair amount of superficial (and often incorrect) use of the
newer terminology (it is almost de rigueur to mention
''boundary-maintenance", input-output, "cybernetic control"
(sic), feedback and the like), the underlying conceptions show little
advance over the mechanical equilibrium model of earlier
Functionalist Sociology 61
centuries' (Buckley, 1967, p. 7). As we will argue below, the
openness of the majority of systems models has been fundamen-
tally constrained by the nature of the analogy used as a basis of
analysis.
The majority of systems models used in the social sciences tend
to be based upon mechanical and biological analogies, though in
recent years increasing attention has been paid to cybernetic mod-
els as a basis of analysis. 13 The mechanical models have been
derived directly from the physical sciences and tend to be under-
written by the assumption that the system has a tendency to
achieve an equilibrium state. Since, as we have already noted,
equilibrium is only possible in closed systems, does this imply that
all those theorists using mechanical models are working upon
closed system principles? To the extent that most of these theorists
recognise the influence of the environment, the answer is no.
Though adhering to the underlying concept of equilibrium - albeit
mistakenly in theoretical terms - they modify their analysis to
allow for the fact that disequilibrium is a very common feature of
the system; or that the situation is one of dynamic equilibrium,
with the system moving from one equilibrium state to another; or
that the system is characterised by homeostasis. All these three
strategies can be understood as attempts to save the notion of
equilibrium as an organising concept in open system situations
where it is fundamentally inappropriate. Homeostasis is an
acceptable open systems concept, but it implies an organismic as
opposed to a mechanical analogy as an organising principle.
Mechanical models of social systems, therefore, tend to be
characterised by a number of theoretical contradictions and are
thus of very limited value as methods of analysis in situations
where the environment of the subject of study is of any real
significance.
Among the most sophisticated and systematically developed
mechanical equilibrium models in social science are those
developed by the Harvard School of sociologists, who took their
lead from Pareto and L. J. Henderson. Of these the models of
Parsons ( 1951), Homans ( 1950), Barnard (1938), Mayo (1933) and
Roethlisberger and Dickson ( 1939), are perhaps the best known
and most readily recognised. It will be recalled from our discussion
earlier in this chapter that Pareto saw society as a system of
interrelated parts which, though in a continual state of surface flux,
were also in a state of underlying equilibrium. His notions were
avidly received by Henderson at Harvard and, through him, by the
whole generation of social theorists who came under his strong
62 Sociological Paradigms and Organi.tational Analysis
influence during the 1920s and t930s.• 4 Henderson was a
biochemist who, through the now famous Fatigue Laboratory,
developed his contact with the Business School and with social
theory. He was particularly interested in the potential contribution
which Pareto's equilibrium systems analysis could make to socio-
logy, particularly as a means of studying. complex social
phenomena comprising many variables in a state of mutual
dependence. The notion of equilibrium had provided a powerful
analytical tool for research in the physical sciences, and its exten-
sion to the social sciences appeared a natural and logical develop-
ment. Cannon's use of the notion of homeostasis to describe
equilibrium in the blood, also developed at Harvard, was seen as
extending the power and relevance of the equilibrium notion.
As we noted earlier, in Pareto's work the concept of equilibrium
had an ambiguous status, in that it is not always entirely clear
whether he intended it to serve as an analytical tool or as a descrip-
tion of reality.' In the work of the Harvard Group this ambiguity
disappears, and the concept is used to serve both purposes.
Mayo's analysis of industrial problems, Homans' study of the
human group, Barnard's study of the organisation, and Parsons'
study of the social system all reflect the assumption that their
subject of study has a tendency to achieve a state of equilibrium.
Given that the notion of equilibrium plays such a central role in
their analysis, the influence of the environment, whilst recognised
as important, is necessarily reduced to a secondary and very
limited role. Environmental change is of principal significance as a
source of disequilibrium. The possibility that environmental
change may influence the very structure and essential nature of the
system is negated to some extent by assumptions that equilibrium
will eventually be restored. The use of a mechanical equilibrium
analogy thus severe:y constrains the openness of the system under
investigation.
Similar problems relate to the use of biological analogies in
systems analysis. Since von Bertalanffy's advocacy of the merits
of an open systems approach, the choice of a biological organism
as a model for systems analysis has proved increasingly popular
and has more or less replaced the older mechanical analogies.
Indeed, the biological analogy of an organism - with its emphasis
upon characteristic features such as energic input, throughput and
output, homeostasis, negative entropy, differentiation, and.equi-
finality15 - has often been equated with the open systems
approach per se. Von Bertalanffy's enthusiasm for illustrating the
open systems notion with analogies drawn from biology, his former
Functionalist Sociology 63
discipline, has led many social systems theorists to confuse what
was intended as an illustration with a point of principle. For many,
the adoption of an open systems approach has been equated with
the adoption of an organismic analogy as a basis of analysis. As we
are arguing here, this represents but one of a number of possible
open systems analogies.
As noted earlier, the organismic analogy is built into Parsons'
(1951) analysis of the social system.'" It is also found in the work of
Katz and Kahn (1966). the Tavistock group of researchers, for
example, Miller and Rice (1967), and countless other systems
theorists, particularly those who have addressed themselves to the
study of organisations.
Such analyses are usually organised around general principles
such as the following:
(a) that the system can be identified by some sort of boundary
which differentiates it from its environment;
(b) that the system is essentially processual in nature;
(c) that this process can be conceptualised in terms of a basic
model which focuses upon input, throughput, output and
feedback;
(d) that the overall operation of the system can be understood
in terms of the satisfaction of system needs geared to
survival or the achievement of homeostasis;
(e) that the system is composed of subsystems which contri-
bute to the satisfaction of the system's overall needs;
(0 that these subsystems, which themselves have identifiable
boundaries, are in a state of mutual interdependence. both
internally and in relation to their environment;
(g) that the operation of the system can be observed in terms
of the behaviour of its constituent elements;
(h) that the critical activities within the context of system
operation are those which involve boundary transactions,
both internally between subsystems and externally in rela-
tion to the environment.
Most of these general principles apply to open systems of all
kinds. Of particular importance as far as the organismic analogy is
concerned are those which imply that the system has ·needs'; that
these are necessarily geared to survival or homeostasis; and that
the subsystems contribute to the well-being of the system as a
whole. As will be recalled from our discussion of the structural
functionalism of Radcliffe-Brown, the notion that a system has
needs which must be fulfilled and the notion of functional unity
both derive directly from the use of the analogy of the biological
64 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
organism for the study of society. The notions of homeostasis and
survival are characteristic of biological analogies at the level both
of the organism and of the species.
As in the case of the mechanical equilibrium systems model, the
use of the organismic analogy constrains the manner in which the
system is viewed in relation to its environment. First, the system,
like an organism, is cast in a responding role. Despite the fact that
the relationship between system and environment is seen in theory
as one of mutual influence, the organismic analogy encourages the
view that it is the environment which influences and the system
which responds. The emphasis is upon the environment acting
upon the system rather than the other way around. Secondly, the
organismic analogy tends to presume a relatively stable system
structure. The system responds through recognisable channels,
the constituent elements of which have a function to perform
within the context of the system as a whole. Third, the general
nature of the response is seen as being determined by the 'needs· of
the system. These needs act as a reference point for interpreting
the activities of the system as a whole. Full openness. however,
requires that the system be allowed to act unfettered by such
assumptions.
There are thus many points of similarity between the perspec-
tive of the systems theorist who adopts the organismic analogy as a
basis for analysis and that of the structural functionalist. The
models of Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown, for example. are very
similar to the notion of a homeostatic open-systems model. Both
emphasise the processual nature of social affairs. 'structure' being
a very transient phenomenon, temporarily expressing a relation-
ship between system parts and their ·ecological' context. Whilst
some systems models perhaps provide a more rigorous statement
of the implications of the biological analogy -for example. with
regard to concepts such as input, throughput, output,
homeostasis, negative entropy, equifinality. etc. - at a conceptual
level they usually add little to the structural functionalist's insight
with regard to the essence of social affairs. Radcliffe-Brown's view
that 'the social structure as a whole can only be observed in its
functioning' well anticipates the essential nature of the systems
view. Indeed. the parallels between the two perspectives can be
seen as being even closer than this. As in the case of the structural
functionalists, social systems theorists have largely restricted
themselves to two of the problem areas identified by Radcliffe-
Brown. those of social morphology and social physiology. Many
theorists working under the banner of systems theory, for exam-
Functionalist SociolORY 6S
pie, have concerned themselves with the measurement of
structures, with the social morphology of systems. There are many
prominent examples within the field of organisation studies. The
work of the Aston group of researchers, for example, Pugh and
Hickson (1976), Richard Hall (1972) and almost any issue of
Administrative Science Quarterly present excellent illustrations.
Their systems models are constructed around .ftructural notions
such as size, configuration. centralisation. technology.
environmental domain, etc. Systems theorists who have con-
cerned themselves with the problem of social physiology have
usually followed Parsons • lead and have focused upon the notion
of functional imperatives in one form or another. Examples
reflected in the work of Katz and Kahn ( 1966), and the notion of the
socio-technical system (for example, Trist and Bamforth, 1951;
Rice, 1958). among others. will be discussed in some detail in the
next chapter. Both these lines of development are open to the same
sort of evaluation and criticism which we have discussed in rela-
tion to structural functionalists who have focused upon social
morphology and social physiology. The social morphologists have
tended to emphasise structure at the expense of process and. along
with the social physiologists. have tended to provide explanations
of social affairs which are geared to providing explanations of the
status quo. Both have largely ignored or underplayed the third set
of problems identified by Radcliffe-Brown - those of social
development. Systems theorists who base their work upon
mechanical and organismic models are not well equipped to
explain situations in which the elaboration and change of basic
structure are the essential features of the phenomena under
investigation. They find difficulty in handling the problem of
morphogenesis and discontinuous forms of change which lead to
system disintegration. disappearance or destruction.
Walter Buckley ( 1967) has provided a critique of the
inadequacies of conventional models used in social science in
similar terms. He argues that in the realm of human activity it is the
morphogenic nature of social arrangements which is all important,
and that systems models adequate for the task of analysing these
processes need to be adopted. Buckley's morphogenic view of
society takes him away from that of the majority of more conven-
tional social systems theorists, in that he sees social structure as
emerging from the process of social interaction. This view of social
process is in line with that of Radcliffe-Brown, though Buckley is
not constrained by any adherence to the organismic analogy. His
morphogenic systems theory is consistent with a more subjectivist
66 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
position within the context of the functionalist paradigm, and we
shall thus consider it in more detail ina later section of this chapter.
Buckley's analysis opens up new horizons as far as systems
theory in social science is concerned. It illustrates that systems
analysis need not be confined to the use of a particular kind of
well-worn analogy, such as that of the organism. Other choices
offer themselves for consideration. One of these, which has
already been explored to a certain extent, is that of the cybernetic
model. 17 Cybernetics has concerned itself with the study of
phenomena which behave as if they had goals. More specifically, it
is concerned with the theory of complex interlocking ·chains of
causation' from which goal-seeking and self-controlling forms of
behaviour emerge. Cybernetic models seek to cut through the
substantive differences which exist between, for example,
machines and organisms, in an attempt to focus upon common
organisational principles which define the nature of self-regulating
systems. Such models offer a useful alternative to the traditional
social system analogies in situations where the study of social
regulation or social engineering is a primary concern.
Other analogies also offer themselves as a basis for systems
analysis. As we shall argue in later chapters, if the concern is to
study situations in which conflictual relationships tend to pre-
dominate, then an analogy which emphasises that the system has a
tendency to break up or divide may be more appropriate. 'Fac-
tional' or ·catastrophic' systems models may provide a better
explanation of the subject under study. One of the central
problems facing the systems analyst is that of choosing an analogy
which reflects the basic nature of the phenomena to be investi-
gated.
Figure 4.1 presents an array of systems models arranged along a
continuum describing the extent to which they emphasise order
and stability as opposed to conflict and change as a normal
tendency in system operation. In certain respects a rough parallel
can be drawn between this continuum and the regulation--radical
change dimension of the analytical scheme which we are using to
differentiate between paradigms in social theory. Generally speak-
ing, the mechanical, organismic and morphogenic models are con-
sistent with a perspective characteristic of the functionalist para-
digm; the other two models are more characteristic of the radical
structuralist paradigm.
The emphasis in our discussion here has been placed upon the
fact that systems theory in principle is not linked to the use of any
one particular type of analogy. The fact that most applications
T
Y
P
I
QI
F
SY
ST
IM
A
IN
A
lO
G
Y
PF
U
N
C
IP
AL
TI
N
ID
EN
C
Y
O
R
D
ER
A
N
D
ST
A
IIU
TY
M
ec
ha
ni
cl
l
Q
,rg
an
ism
io
·E
qu
ilib
riu
m
IH
O
!I
ft
to
lt
la
il
M
~
r
p
h
o
g
e
n
i
c
S
·tf
lu
ct
U
!II
tla
bo
rt
tio
n
Fi
&
tn
4
.1
So•
• po
ss
i.b
lc
tw
es
o
f s
ys
~e
m
m
od
el$
Fe
ct
iO
nt
l
Tu
rb
ul
en
t
dl
iv
ili
on
C
et
as
tro
pl
ilic
Co
m
1P
tet
•
re
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
n
C
O
IN
FU
C
T
AN
ID
C
H
AN
G
I
68 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
have been based upon the mechanical and organismic models,
especially the latter, has often disguised this fact. The focus in
modern systems theory is upon the way in which a system is
organised internally and in relation to its environment. It seeks to
penetrate beyond the substantive nature of machine, organism or
whatever to reveal its principle of organisation. ·Systems theory is
about organisation - the organisation of 'complexes of elements
standing in interaction', to use von Bertalanffy's words ( 1956, p.
2). The automatic selection of one particular kind of analogy to
represent a system pre-empts systems analysis, since each kind of
analogy presumes a specific kind of structure and concommitant
pattern of information process, exchange, behaviour and the like.
The selection of a particular type of analogy to represent a system
in advance of a detailed analysis of its structure and mode of
operation is akin to prescription in advance of diagnosis. This has
been the principal problem with systems analysis in social science.
Social theorists have generally reached for some simple mechani-
cal or organismic analogy in advance of any study of the system to
which it is to be applied. In doing so, they have meted out rough
justice to the essential nature of the social phenomena which they
are investigating.
It will be clear from the above discussion that systems theory is
not intrinsically tied to any specific view of social reality. except
insofar as its general positivist orientation implies a social world
characterised by some form of order and regularity which can be
captured fn the notion of 'system'. Insofar as it has been applied
through use of mechanical and biological models. however, it has
been committed to a highly objectivist view ofthe social world. By
implication, the principles of physics and biology have been seen
as capable of explaining the nature of the social world. In this
respect there are direct parallels with structural functionalism and
the development of a functionalist perspective stretching back to
Durkheim, Spencer and other theorists before. We represent this
overall perspective under the notion of social system theory,
which occupies an area of that functionalist paradigm akin to that
illustrated in Figure 3.3. Its relatively objectivist location will
become all the more apparent as we move to consideration of other
schools of thought located within the paradigm.
lnteractionism and Social Action Theory
In terms of intellectual tradition, interactionism and social action
theory can both be understood as representing a fusion of certain
Functionalist Sociology 69
aspects of German idealism and Anglo-French sociological
positivism. We have already considered sociological positivism in
some detail and will be devoting attention to the idealist tradition in
Chapter 6. As a means of presenting the essential characteristics of
interactionism and action theory here, therefore, we will confine
our attention to their immediate intellectual history. We will show
how the foundations ofinteractionism were largely laid by Georg
Simmel and George Herbert Mead, two theorists whose thought is
characteristic of what has come to be known as the neo-idealist
tradition. We will show how action theory derives from the work of
Max Weber, another neo-idealist. Whilst sharing a similar position
in relation to the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme, their thought is differentiated because they focus upon
different elements of social process.
Interactionism
Georg Simmel (1858-1918) was, to use Merton's words, a man of
innumerable seminal ideas. 18 A philosopher and historian turned
sociologist, he contributed freely to a wide range of areas of
enquiry, and his thought defies simple and straightforward
classification. His eclectic approach led to the development of a
brand of sociology containing many strains and tensions which
have never been fully reconciled. Essentially he was an academic
renegade, shunning many aspects of both major contemporary
schools of thought. He drove a middle way between idealism and
positivism, retaining only those aspects of each which lent
themselves to his own particular needs.
The German idealist tradition held that there was a fundamental
difference between nature and culture and that natural laws were
inappropriate to the realm of human affairs, which were character-
ised by the autonomy of the human spirit. Society was regarded as
having no real existence above and beyond the individuals which
composed it; no social scie11ce was possible. As we have seen, the
Anglo-French tradition. on the other hand, held that society did
have an objective existence and in many respects could be likened
to a biological organism. Accordingly, it was characterised by the
operation of laws which were amenable to investigation through
the methods of natural science. Simmel rejected the extremes of
both positions and argued in favour of an analysis of human
association and interaction. Beneath the variety and complexity of
70 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
individual affairs. he argued, there was a pattern. Beneath the
content, an underlying form. He favoured a sociology focusing
upon an intermediate level of analysis. In Coser's words, he was
concerned with the study of society as
an intricate web of multiple relations established among individuals in
constant interaction with one another ... The larger superindividual
structures - the state, the clan. the family. the city. or the trade union
- turn out to be but crystallizations of this interaction, even though
they may attain autonomy and permanency and confront the individual
as if they were alien powers. The major field of study for the student of
society is, hence, association rather than society. (Coser, 1965, p. S)
Simmel thus focused his attention upon human beings in their
social context. a theme which reverberates throughout his many
works. He was interested, above all else. in what he describes as
'interactions among the atoms of society'. As he put it,
They account for all the toughness and elasticity. all the colour and
consistency of social life, that is so striking and yet so mysterious.
Sociology asks what happens to men and by what rules they behave,
not insofar as they unfold their understandable individual existences in
their totalities. but insofar as they form groups and are determined by
their group existence because of interaction. (Simmel, 1950, pp.
10-11)
Beneath the mystery and individual character of interactions lay
the 'form'. or what Coser describes as the 'geometry' or
'grammar', of social life. For Simmel. the basic patterns lay hidden
beneath the ·content' of social life and had to be extracted through
formal analysis. Much of his work was devoted to an analysis of
these forms and their influence upon human action and behaviour.
His analysis of social forms such as dyadic and triadic relation-
ships, group processes and the influence of group size on
activities, provide good illustrations of the general orientation of
his relativist, though firmly nomothetic, approach to the study of
social life.
Despite his concern for form and pattern in social affairs,
Simmel was by no means a strict determinist. In his view of human
nature he again occupies a middle ground between the German and
Anglo-French traditions. He saw social life as being characterised
by a continuous conflict between the individual and his social
world. His work is characterised by what Coser describes as an
emphasis on a 'dialectical tension between the individual and
Functionalist Sociology ·11
society', in which the individual, though a product of his social
world also stands apart. 'The individual is determined, yet deter-
mining, acted upon, yet self-actuating' (Coser, 1965, pp. 10, 11).
In terms of the subjective-objective dimension of our ana-
lytical scheme. therefore, Simmel occupies an interesting and
complex position. On the ontological strand, he stands mid-way
between the Anglo-French 'realism' and German ·nominalism'.
On the epistemological strand, his belief in underlying form and
pattern in human affairs places him towards the positivist position.
In terms of the methodological strand his position is clearly.
nomothetic. On the human nature strand, he occupies an
intermediate position. For these reasons we identify his brand of
theorising as characteristic of the least objectivist fringe of the
functionalist paradigm.
Simmel's interest in sociology at a micro-level of analysis led to
many insights with regard to the dynamics of social life. The theme
of conflict between the individual and the institutional context, for
example, is one which runs throughout many aspects of Simmel's
work and provides a valuable guideline as to where he stands in
relation to the regulatio~radical change dimension of our ana-
lytical scheme.
F~r Simmel, conflict was inherent in social life. As Coser notes,
Simmel would have rejected any attempt to understand societies by
way of models emphasising exclusively those processes making for
harmony, consensus, and balance among component individuals and
groups. To Simmel, sociation always involves harmony and conflict,
attraction and repulsion, love and hatred. He saw human relations as
characterised by ambivalence, precisely because those who are con-
nected in intimate relations are likely to harbour for one another not
only positive but also negative sentiments.
An entirely harmonious group, Simmel argued, could not exist
empirically .It would not partake of any kind of life process; it would be
incapable of change and development. Any social relationship needs
attractive and repulsive forces, harmony and disharmony, in order to
attain a specific form. (Coser, 1965, p. 12)
The inherent conflict between the individual and his situation
provides the basis of a penetrating analysis of the alienated state of
modern man, particularly in works such as The Stranger and The
Metropolis and Mental Life. Simmel presents the trend to mod-
ernity as reflecting a preponderance of what Nisbet has called 'the
tyrrany of objectivism' - the preponderance of 'the object spirit'
over the 'subjective spirit' (Nisbet, 1967, pp. 305-12).
72 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
The individual, for Simmel, had 'become a mere cog in an
enormous organisation of things and powers which tear from his
hands all progress, spirituality, and value in order to transform
them from their subjective form into the form of a purely objective
life' (Simmel, 1950, p. 422). His analysis of 'alienation' could well
have led him to a sociological perspective diametrically opposed to
the interests of the status quo. However, he did not follow this
path. As Nisbet notes, the notion of 'alienation' became for
Simmel a kind of methodological tool with which ·ever more
minute aspects of the social order are brought into view' (Nisbet,
1966, p. 311).
Within the context of his overall sociological perspective 'con-
flict' and 'alienation' were interpreted as playing an essential and
positive role in society. This view was an essential aspect of his
notion of the 'fallacy of separateness'. For Simmel, each aspect of
interaction had to be understood in terms of its reciprocal context.
Thus conflict and order were two aspects of the same reality; a
measure of alienation was an essential ingredient of man's aware-
ness of himself as a person. From this point of view, all social
phenomena could be interpreted as playing an essential part in the
maintenance of the wider society. This aspect of his thought brings
Simmel very close to a functionalist interpretation of society, a
view clearly reflected in his view of the latent positive functions of
conflict. 19 As Coser notes, Simmel argued that
Social conflict necessarily involves reciprocal action and is. hence,
based on reciprocity rather than unilateral imposition. Conflict might
often bind parties which might otherwise withdraw. It might serve as a
safety valve for negative attitudes and feelings. making further rela-
tionships possible. For example, conflict might lead to a strengthening
of the position of one or more parties to the relationship, increasing
their dignity and self-esteem through self-assertion. Thus. conflict
might produce new ties among the participants, strengthening their
existing bonds or establishing new ones. In this sense, conflict might be
considered a creative force rather than a destructive one ... The good
society -far from conflict-free- is, on the contrary, ·sewn together'
by a variety of criss-crossing conflicts among its component parts.
(Coser, 1965, p. 12)
Simmel's brand of social theorising, therefore, is firmly rooted
within the context of the sociology of regulation. Whilst recognis-
ing alienation and conflict as essential ingredients of social affairs,
he incorporates them within an explanation of the status quo rather
than as forces for radical change. Simmel's view of conflict has
Functionalist Sociology 73
been particularly influential in establishing the 'problem of order'
as the central problem of sociological analysis. 20 His writings have
influenced developments in a number of areas, particularly those
of urban sociology, experimental small-group research, reference
group behaviour, role theory and conflict functionalism. In these
diverse ways, Simmel's influence upon the functionalist paradigm
has been of a major importance. 21
The second theorist whom we identify as having made a major
contribution to the interactionist movement is George Herbert
Mead (1863-1931). Mead was an American social philosopher
who, like Simmel, was influenced by the major cross-currents of
thought flowing in the latter decades of the nineteenth century and
the early decades of the twentieth century. In his wide-ranging
contribution to social philosophy and social psychology, we again
witness a fusion of the biological models derived from the Anglo-
French tradition of social theorising with elements of German
idealism. The product is a distinctive and complex system of
thought containing many strains and tensions and is one which
defies simple and straightforward treatment. The position is com-
plicated by the fact that Mead published relatively little of his
work. The books which appear under his name were assembled
and edited posthumously from various notes and manuscripts held
by former students and associates. Mead's position has thus
necessarily been greatly influenced and modified by the interpreta-
tions placed upon it by students and editors alike and, as we shall
argue below, his impact upon developments in social theory have
been rather one-sided. Certain aspects of his thought have been
developed at the expense of others.
Mind, Self and Society (1934), Mead's most influential work, is
subtitled 'From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviourist'. Although
Mead only used this term on one occasion ( 1934, p. 6), it is the term
by which he and his work are most often identified and described.
In point of fact, his work is much more wide-ranging than this, and
a strong claim can be made that in his other books he moves away
from this position towards a much more phenomenological
stance. 22
In Mind, Self and Society Charles Morris, its editor, suggests
that 'philosophically, Mead was a pragmatist; scientifically, he
was a social psychologist' (Mead, 1934, p. ix). The pragmatist
movement sought to interpret the concepts of mind and intelli-
gence in biological, psychological and sociological terms, in line
with post-Darwinian views of the evolutionary nature of change
and development.u It was a movement which can be clearly
74 Soci()/ogical Paradigm.<; and Organisational Analysis
identified with the Anglo-French tradition of social theory. Mead,
through his social psychology, sought to combine the biological
models being used in psychology with the notion of ·society' or
·social interaction' .24 His theories, as reflected in Mind, Self and
Society, combined a modified form of behaviourism with elements
of German idealism, such as the Hegelian notion of the social
nature of self and morality. 25
In Mind, Self and Socie'? Mead seeks to establish how 'mind'
and 'self' arise within the context of social conduct and interac-
tion. His explanation places emphasis upon the role of gestures in
the interaction process. Mead views the notion of ·gesture' in
social terms -as part of an 'act'. In interaction between animals
the social act or 'conversation of gestures' can be understood in
terms of a series of symbols to which the various parties respond
according to the interpretation placed upon the various gestures.
Such action can be regarded as a form of communication, in which
the various gestures or symbols involved influence later stages of
the act. However, in the case of animals the meanings are not in
the mind. Animals are not consciously communicating selves.
Each animal determines its behaviour according to what the other
is beginning to do.
With human beings the situation is somewhat different, since
through ·vocal gestures' or language the individual has the capac-
ity to become conscious of what he is doing. For Mead, it is the
mechanism oflanguage which underlies the development of'mind'.
Through the operation of 'mind', the individual can become the
object of his own thoughts. It is this process which underlies the
development of'self' .In Morris's words, 'Mead's endeavour is to
show that mind and the self are without residue social emergents;
and that language, in the form of the vocal gesture, provides the
mechanism for their emergence' (Mead, 1934, p. xiv).
Thus, tor Mead, the conscious human being evolves through a
social process, a process of interaction which involves the
development of language and hence 'mind' and 'self'. The human
being, unlike other animal organisms, has the capacity to become
aware of what he is about. For this to happen, he must be able to
interpret the meaning of his personal gestures. This involves an
internal ·conversation' or process of thinking from the standpoint
of what Mead called 'the generalised other' (Mead, 1934, p. 155).
As Morris puts it,
Behaviouristically, this is to say that the biological individual must be
able to call out in himselfthe response his gesture calls out in the other,
Functionalist Sociology 15
and then utilise this response of the other for the control of his own
further conduct. Such gestures are significant symbols. Through their
use the individual is 'taking the role of the other' in the regulation of his
own conduct. Man is essentially the role-taking animal. The calling out
of the same response in both the self and the other gives the common
content necessary for community of meaning (Mead, 1934, p. xxi).
In providing a bio-social explanation of the emergence of'mind'
and 'self', Mead drives mid-way between the idealist view of
society as a subjectively constructed entity and a biological view
which ignores the influence of the social aspects of human
development. Ontologically, Mead's views, as expressed in Mind,
Self and Society, are predicated upon the existence of an external
world which influences human thought and action. Society is
ontologically prior to ·mind' and ·self'. 26 However, his position is
far from being deterministic. Rejecting the notion of simple
stimulus-response models of human behaviour ,27 Mead recognises
the role played by human beings in influencing their environment,
particularly through symbolic interpretation of the consequences
of various types of environmental conditions and modes of interac-
tion. Individual actors are thus accorded at least a mediating and
interpretive, if not entirely controlling or creative, role in relation
to their environment. Epistemologically, on the basis of Morris's
interpretation, Mead again occupies a middle ground. The world of
science is conceived as essentially social in nature:
composed of that which is common to and true for various observers -
the world of common or social experience as symbolically formu-
lated ... The experienced world is conceived by Mead as a realm of
natural events, emergent through the sensitivity of organisms, events
no more a property of the organism than of the things observed.
Philosophically the position here is an objective relativism: qualities of
the object may yet be relative to a conditioning organism. A certain
portion of the world, as experienced, is private, but a portion is social
or common, and science formulates it. Private experience and common
experience are polar concepts; the private can only be defined over
against that which is common. (Mead, 1934, p. xix)
Mead's position is presented by Morris as being essentially that
of 'objective relativism in regard to universals ... By making univ-
ersality relative to the act it is brought within the scope of an
empirical science and philosophy' (Mead, 1934, p. xxviii). Mead
was essentially a theorist who drew upon empirical examples to
illustrate his concepts and point of view.
76 SociohJRical Paradigms and OrRanisational Analysis
In terms of the four strands of the subjectiv~objective dimen-
sion of our analytical scheme, therefore, Mead's position as
reflected in Mind, Self and Society can be interpreted as being
close to that of Simmel. Although their theories and ideas differ in
many important respects, 28 they are both committed to an interac-
tionist form of analysis focusing upon individuals in a social con-
text. For both, the realm of social affairs is essentially processual
in nature, characterised by an underlying form expressed through
social interaction. The study of this interaction is central to their
social theories, which in the case of both writers are firmly geared
to providing an explanation of the status quo.
For these reasons we could identify Mead as essentially a theor-
ist of •regulation', whose thought, along with that of Simmel, can
be regarded as characteristic of the least objectivist fringe of the
functionalist paradigm. On the basis of the way in which Mead's
thought has been interpreted and used by subsequent theorists and
researchers, there is a large measure of justification for doing this,
since, as we shall argue later, Mead's work as interpreted above
has had a considerable influence upon various aspects of interac-
tionist thought. However, this whole mode of interpretation has
been criticised as unrepresentative of Mead's true position and,
following this line of argument, a case can be made for locating
Mead within the interpretive paradigm -even though the work of
most of his so-called followers and adherents would, without ques-
tion, remain firmly located within the context of the functionalist
paradigm. 29
Maurice Natanson ( 1973c), in a very clear and coherent analysis
of Mead's work, argues that the categorisation of Mead as a ·social
behaviourist' misrepresents his position, and that his theory of
social reality is of a more open-ended and developmental charac-
ter. He argues that Mind, Self and Society, The Philosophy of the
Present ( 1932b) and The Philosophy of the Act (1938) signify three
implicit directions in Mead's overall position, and that the funda-
mental themes explored ·bear amazing resemblance to the prob-
lems of phenomenological philosophising in the tradition of
Edmund Husser)' (Natanson, 1973c, p. 4). Natanson's view is that
as Mead moved in his development away from •pragmatic'
philosophers such as James, Cooley and Dewey, to philosophers
such as Bergson, Alexander and Whitehead, the nature of his
thought moved •from a problematic empiricism toward an idealis-
tic and subjectivistic account of the nature of social reality'
(Natanson. 1973c, p. 4). The three m;yor directions in Mead's
development are seen as:
Functionalist Sociology 77
(a) 'the attempt to explore and describe experience within
society, treating consciousness, language, communica-
tion, and meaning as emergents from the social process';
(b) 'the re-approach to the same phenomena in terms of sub-
jectivity, treating the given in experience as arising epis-
temologically and experientially within what Mead terms
the "Act'";
(c) 'the attempt to describe what is given in experience by
means of a radical theory of temporality which takes the
present as the locus of reality' (Natanson, 1973c, p. 5). 30
In terms of our analytical scheme the three directions represent
a progressive movement away from the context of the functionalist
paradigm towards the interpretive paradigm. In the course of his
intellectual development Mead's meta-theoretical assumptions
with regard to our subjective-objective dimension changed sub-
stantially, and it is this change which accounts for many of the
strains and contradictions which Natanson and others have iden-
tified in his work. In other words, Mead's adherents have inter-
preted his work from the context of their meta-theoretical assump-
tions. As Douglas ( 1970b, p. 17) has noted, and our above analysis
suggests, it is possible to distinguish between 'two parallel, but
conflicting strains of interactionist thought: "behavioural interac-
tionism" and "phenomenological interactionism" '. The
'behavioural interactionists' have interpreted Mead within the
context of the functionalist paradigm; the ·phenomenological
interactionists' within the context of the interpretive paradigm.
Whilst recognising their indebtedness to a common heritage, they
have used Mead's work in fundamentally divergent ways.
So much, for the moment, for the theories and ideas of Mead and
Simmel. To many readers the attention which we have devoted to
them may appear disproportionate within the context of our work
as a whole. We justify our position on the basis that their theories
and ideas have provided important foundations for developments
in sociology and social psychplogy which are not always fully
recognised. Simmel is given little prominence in modern sociologi-
cal texts; in the literature on social psychology he is rare!y men-
tioned. Yet his pioneering work underpins much contemporary
theory in both these fields. The influence of Mead, though often
recognised, is rarely treated comprehensively and his ideas are
interpreted in a partial and often misleading way.
It is through the melting pot of what has come to be known as
'Chicago sociology' that the influence of Simmel and Mead have
had the greatest impact upon contemporary sociological theory.3 •
78 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Under the influence of leading intellectual figures such as Albion
Small, W. I. Thomas, James Dewey, G. H. Mead, R. E. Park, E.
W. Burgess and E. Faris, the Department of Sociology at Chicago
had a major impact upon developments in American sociology
from the 1890s until at least the beginning of World War II.
Although each of these men made an original and distinctive con-
tribution to philosophical and sociological thought, it is the work of
Mead and Simmel which has had the most lasting influence. 31
Many of the interactionist ideas which characterise Chicago
sociology can be directly traced to one or other of these two key
figures or seen as representing a fusion of their respective con-
tributions.33 A full account of interactionist theory and research
would call for a volume in itself. Our discussion here, therefore,
will be restricted to an analysis of its dominant form - symbolic
interactionism.
Symbolic interactionism
The term •symbolic interactionism' has come to be associated
with a very wide range of interactionist thought. Essentially, the
notion derives directly from the work of Mead and the distinction
which he drew between ·non-symbolic' and ·symbolic' inter-
action. As Herbert Blumer, one of Mead's ex-students and most
prominent interpreters, has put it:
In non-symbolic interaction human beings respond directly to one
another's gestures or actions; in symbolic interaction they interpret
each other's gestures and act on the basis of the meaning yielded by the
interpretation. An unwitting response to the tone of another's voice
illustrates non-symbolic interaction. Interpreting the shaking of a fist
as signifying that a person is preparing to attack illustrates symbolic
interaction. Mead's concern was predominandy with symbolic interac-
tion. Symbolic interaction involves interpretation, or ascertaining the
meaning of the actions or remarks of the other person, and definition,
or conveying indications to another person as to how he is to act.
Human association consists of a process of such interpretation and
definition. Through this process the participants tit their own acts to
the ongoing acts of one another and guide others in doing so. (Blumer,
1966, pp. 537-8)l4
Whilst owing general allegiance to this notion, the symbolic
interactionist movement in sociology and social psychology has
not developed in anything like a consistent manner and has no
Functionalist SocioiORY 79
single integrated body of theory which defines its position. 15
Rather, it constitutes a general orientation which is concerned to
understand social phenomena through the micro-analysis of
human affairs. Mead's basic ideas and concepts appear under the
guise of 'role theory' ,36 'reference group theory' ,n 'self theory' ,31
'dramaturgical theory' ,19 and the like. All represent varieties of
symbolic interactionist thought which tend to emphasise one
aspect of Mead's work at the expense of another.
Although one can identify a range of symbolic interactionist
thought in terms of categories such as those listed above, this
misses a very important point, since the fundamental issue which
divides symbolic interactionists relates to the position which they
occupy on the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme. As has been suggested earlier, it is possible to distinguish
between so-called 'behavioural interactionism' and
'phenomenological interactionism'. The differences between
these two modes of theorising and research are so fundamental
that it is definitely misleading to regard symbolic interactionism as
a coherent school of thought.
The distinctions between these two strains of symbolic interac-
tionism can be clearly illustrated by comparing the views of Rose
and Blumer presented in the former's collection of specially com-
missioned readings on interactionism (Rose, 1962). In the intro-
ductory chapter Rose, recognising that there is no complete
agreement on concepts, premises and propositions among those
who regard themselves as symbolic interactionists, seeks to
restate Mead's theory as expressed in Mind, Self and Society in
'simple, systematic and researchable form'. More specifically, he
is concerned to state it 'in terms that will fit the frame of reference
of the behaviourist or Gestaltist so as to make it more generally
understandable' .In order to do this Rose identifies (and elaborates
upon) the following assumptions and propositions:
ASSUMPTION I Man lives in a symbolic environment as well as a
physical environment and can be 'stimulated' to act by symbols as well
as by physical stimuli ...
ASSUMPTION 2 Through symbols, man has the capacity to stimu-
late others in ways other than those in which he is himself stimu-
lated ...
ASSUMPTION 3 Through communication of symbols, man can/earn
hu.~e numbers of meanings and values - and henu ways of acting -
from other men ...
GENERAL PROPOSITION (DEDUCTION) I Through the/earning
of a culture (and subcultures, which are the specialised cultures found
in particular segments of society), men are able to predict each other's
80 Sociolof(ica/ Paradif(ms and Organisational Analysis
behaviour most of the time and {i!auge their own behaviour to the
predicted beha~·iour of others ...
ASSUMPTION 4 The symbols - and the meanings and values to
which they refer - do not occur only in isolated bits, but often in
clusters, sometimes large and £·omplex ...
GENERAL PROPOSITION (DEDUCTION) 2 The indi1•idual defines
(has a meaning for) himself as well as other objects, actions, and
characteristics ...
ASSUMPTION 5 Thinking is the process by which possible symbolic
solutions and other future courses of action are examined, assessed/or
their relative advantages and disadvantages in terms of the values of
the indh·idual. and one of them choun ... (Rose. 1962, pp. 5-12).411
This interpretation of Mead's work is clearly in the mould of the
'social behaviourist'. The essential concepts relating to symbolic
interactionism are interpreted within the context of a framework
which views man as living within an essentially 'realist' world of
symbolic and physical objects. It is a world to which man reacts
and which he influences, though the emphasis in Rose's work
appears to be on the former. The concern to deduce propositions
reflects a predilection for a positivist epistemology; specific
hypotheses are put forward in other contributions to Rose's book
and the methodologies employed are usually of a firmly nomothe-
tic character. Rose's overall standpoint provides a clear illustra-
tion of Strauss's observation that sociologists who tend to be social
determinists read Mead as if he too were a social determinist
(Strauss, 1964, pp. xii-xiii).
By way of contrast, Blumer, in an article in the same book of
readings, adopts a more subjectivist position. He argues that rec-
ognition of the process of interpretation in human affairs has
fundamental implications for an understanding of the human
being, human action and human association, and, in consequence,
he adopts an ontology which is much more nominalist than that of
Rose. As Blumer puts it, 'Instead of the individual being sur-
rounded by an environment of pre-existing objects which play
upon him and call forth his behaviour, the proper picture is that he
constructs his objects on the basis of his ongoing activity' (Blumer,
1962, p. 182). His view on human nature is also much more volun-
tarist: 'The second important implication of the fact that the human
being makes indications to himself is that his action is constructed
or built up instead of being a mere release' (Blumer, 1962, p. 182).
In line with this analysis, Blumer develops a view of society which
constitutes a process of symbolic interaction, in which individual
'selves' interpret their situation as a basis for action. Group or
collective action is seen as consisting of an alignment of individual
Functionalist SocioloRY 81
actions •brought about by the individuals' interpreting or taking
into account each other's actions' (Blumer, 1962, p. 184). In this
article, Blumer is concerned to establish the credentials of sym-
bolic interaction in preference to other elements of sociological
thought, particularly those based on organic rather than interac-
tionist models (structural functionalism and social systems theory,
for instance). Accordingly, he does not elaborate his particular
view of symbolic interaction in any real depth. 41 This is left to later
works, in which he adopts an increasingly subjectivist orientation.
In his 1966article discussing the work of G. H. Mead, for example,
he presents Mead as advocating a distinctly nominalist ontology
and goes on to draw out its implications for individual and group
action:
for Mead objects are human constructs and not self-existing entities
with intrinsic natures. Their nature is dependent on the orientation and
action of people toward them ... This analysis of objects puts human
group life into a new and interesting perspective. Human beings are
seen as Jiving in a world of meaningful objects - not in an environment
of stimuli or self-constituted entities. This world is socially produced in
that the meanings are fabricated through the process of social interac-
tion. Thus different groups come to develop different worlds - and
these worlds change as the objects that compose them change in
meaning. Since people are set to act in terms of the meanings of their
objects, the world of objects of a group represents in a genuine sense its
action organisation. To identify and understand the life of a group it is
necessary to identify its world of objects; this identification has to be in
terms of the meanings objects have for the members of the group.
Finally, people are not locked to their objects; they may check action
toward objects and indeed work out new lines of conduct toward
them. This condition introduces into human group life an indigenous
source of transformation. (Blumer, 1966, p. 539)
Blumer goes on to present symbolic interactionism as being
essentially concerned with the meanings which underlie the
process of interaction and as an attempt to understand society in
these terms. 42 It is presented as a form of analysis geared to under-
standing the way in which people align themselves with different
situations. This essentially phenomenological standpoint is
developed further in his 1969 study and reinforced by a call for
interactionist methodology to ·respect the nature of the empirical
world' (Blumer, 1969, p. 60).
This split in orientation between behavioural and
phenomenological symbolic interactionism which we have
82 Sociolof1ical Paradi11ms and Organisational Analysis
illustrated in relation to the work of Rose and Blumer is mirrored
on a wider scale in the work of the so-called Iowa and Chicago
approaches to symbolic interaction.41 The former have been
particularly concerned to operationalise their approach and, in so
doing, have become increasingly committed to a structural as
opposed to a processual view of the phenomena which they are
concerned to investigate. As Manis and Meltzer have observed,
this is very evident in the work on self theory, where there has been
a tendency to abandon the non-empirical concepts in Mead's
thought and focus upon the measurement of essentially abstract
concepts (Manis and Meltzer, 1967, p. vi). It also characterises a
great deal of the work on role theory, where the concern has been
to identify and measure the nature of the external situation in
which the particular actors under investigation find themselves.
Essentially, the Iowa interactionists, as a result of their commit-
ment to a positivist epistemology and nomothetic methodology ,44
have tended to violate their ontological assumptions.
It is this distinction which lies at the heart of the difference
between behavioural and phenomenological symbolic interaction-
ism. The difference between the two approaches is largely one of
epistemology and methodology. Whilst both recognise, at a con-
ceptual level, the processual nature of symbolic interaction, and
the significance of meaning and interpretation from the point of
view of the actors involved, their empirical work often fails to do
full justice to the nature of their theory .45 Indeed, on occasions it
bears little relation to the theory from which it is derived and ends
up as little more than an 'abstracted empiricism'. There is a parallel
to be drawn here with developments in the fields of structural
functionalism and systems theory. We noted in our discussion of
these approaches how the notion of 'functional process' became
lost in an empirical ·search for structure' .lnteractionism has often
suffered the same fate, many studies resulting in little more than a
series of empirical snapshots of reified concepts which defy the
processual nature of the interactionist perspective per se.
Social action theory
The theory of social action, sometimes described as 'the action
frame of reference'. derives largely from the work of Max Weber
(1864-1920) and the notion of verstehen. As we argue in some
detail in Chapter 6 on the sociology of the interpretive paradigm,
the method of verstehen or interpretive ·understanding' plays a
Functionalist Sociology 83
crucial role in neo-idealist social thought. Introduced by Wilhelm
Dilthey, and elaborated by Weber, it was seen as a method of
analysis particularly suited to the investigation of social affairs, for
which the subjective meanings of events was all important. In
contrast to the natural sciences, the cultural or social sciences
were viewed by the nco-idealists as being concerned with subject
matter of a fundamentally different kind. Whereas the natural
sciences were seen as dealing with the study of external processes
in a material world, the cultural sciences were seen as being
concerned with the internal and intangible processes of human
minds. Special approaches and methods were regarded as
necessary for an understanding of this world of human affairs. The
method ofverstehen -of placing oneself in the role of the actor-
was seen as a means of relating inner experience to outward
actions.
As we argue in our discussion of the interpretive paradigm,
Weber was something of a positivist in his general epistemology, in
that he wished to construct an objective social science capable of
providing causal explanations of social phenomena, yet one which
avoided what he regarded as glaringly obvious deficiencies in
positivist explanations of society. He saw the sociological positiv-
ists of his day as drawing too close an analogy between the natural
and social worlds.
For Weber, explanations of the social world had to be ·adequate
on the level of meaning'. Explanations of social affairs, he argued,
had to take account of the way in which individuals attached
subjective meaning to situations and orientated their actions in
accordance with their perceptions ofthose situations. Sociology,
from his point of view, had to be essentially 'interpretive' in
nature. Social action theory is based upon this Weberian view of
the nature of social science, but Weber's methods are not always
taken up in a systematic fashion.
Weber, in line with his method of analysis based on ideal types,
constructed a typology of social action which distinguished be-
tween: (a) action orientated to tradition; in essence this was con-
ceived as action dominated by a habitual response; (b) action
dominated by emotional factors - that is, spontaneous expres-
sions of feelings; (c) action which was rationally orientated
towards some absolute value- wertrational action; and (d) action
which was rationally orientated towards the achievement of
specific ends, and in which the relative advantages and dis-
advantages of alternative means are taken into account - zweck-
rational actions. It was Weber's view that these 'types of action',
84 Sociological Paradigms and Or!]anisational Analysis
albeit oversimplifications, could provide a useful sociological tool
for analysing the modes of orientation of social action in practice
(Weber, 1947. pp. 115-24). This scheme has normally been
neglected in favour of a more generalised interpretation of the
action perspective, which focuses upon the way in which individu-
als interpret the situation in which they find themselves. For
example, Cohen has suggested that the theory of action can be
regarded as consisting of a number of assumptions which provide a
mode of analysis for explaining the action and conduct of typical
individuals (actors or social actors) in typical situations. These
assumptions are stated as follows:
(i) The actor has goals (or aims, or ends); his actions are carried out
in pursuit of these.
(ii) Action often involves the selection of means to the attainment of
goals; but even where it appears that it does not, it is still
possible for an observer to distinguish analytically between
means and goals.
(iii) An actor always has many goals; his actions in pursuit of any
one affect and are affected by his actions in pursuit of others.
(iv) The pursuit of goals and the selection of means always occurs
within situations which influence the course of action.
(v) The actor always makes certain assumptions concerning the
nature of his goals and the possibility of their attainment.
(vi) Action is influenced not only by the situation but by the actor's
knowledge of it.
(vii) The actor has certain sentiments or affective dispositions which
affect both his perception of situations and his choice of goals.
(viii) The actor has certain norms and values which govern his selec-
tion of goals and his ordering of them in some scheme of
priorities. (Cohen, 1968, p. 69)
Interpreted from this viewpoint, the effect of Weberian action
theory has been to inject a measure of voluntarism into theories of
social behaviour by allowing for the fact that individuals interpret
and define their situation and act accordingly.46 Within the context
of the functionalist paradigm, Weberian action theory defines a
position which stands in contrast to the determinism which
characterises theories in the most objectivist regions, such as
Skinner's behaviourism, which we shall discuss in a later section
of this chapter.
Most prominent among the social action theorists is the name of
Talcott Parsons, who in his classic work, The Structure of Social
Action (1949), argued that there was a tendency for the work of
Durkheim, Marshall, Pareto and Weber to converge in terms of a
Functionalist Sociology 85
·voluntaristic theory of action'. Parsons advocated this
'voluntaristic theory' as a general sociological perspective, but in
point of fact it was relatively short-lived. In Parsons' hands the
theory of social action became steadily more deterministic and was
eventually incorporated into his theory of the social system which,
as we have argued earlier in this chapter, is located in a more
objectivist region of the paradigm. There has been much debate
over the nature of the changes reflected in Parsons' thought. 47 In
terms of our analytical scheme, he has journeyed across the
functionalist paradigm from a position on its subjectivist boundary
consonant with Weber's theory of social action to a position firmly
located within the bounds of social system theory. This positivist
inclination has always been evident in Parsons' work. The
Structure of Social Action is undoubtedly an impressive piece of
scholarship, thoroughly deserving of the description 'classic'. but,
given the range of social theorists whom Parsons considered, it is
hardly surprising that their thought converges within the bound-
aries of the functionalist paradigm. Durkheim, Marshall, Pareto
and Weber are all located in terms of their meta-theoretical
assumptions within this perspective. Giddens ( 1976, p. 16) has
observed that 'there is no action in Parsons' "action frame of
reference", only behaviour which is propelled by need-
dispositions or role expectations. The stage is set, but the actors
only perform according to scripts which have already been written
out for them.' Such is the nature of the functionalist perspective;
its underlying meta-theoretical assumptions only allow for a
limited m~~sure of voluntarism in human behaviour. As will
become apparent from our discussion of the social thought
characteristic of the interpretive paradigm, the social action
perspective reflected in the Weberian and Parsonian theories
represents a very limited excursion into the realm of the subjec-
tive. Weber, in attempting to synthesise idealism and positivism
within the bounds of an epistemology orientated towards the lat-
ter, necessarily committed himself to an intermediate position in
terms of the subjective>-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme.
Social action theory has never really obtained a firm foot-
ing in the USA. In addition to Parsons’s intellectual journey away
from the Weberian position towards social system theory. other
factors account for the lack of interest and popularity. First, and
perhaps most important, Weber’s work was not available in
English until the mid 1940s. Second, the dominant influence was
that of the symbolic interactionist movement. As we have argued
86 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
earlier in this section, as a result of the efforts of the Chicago
School, interactionism in the Meadian and Simmelian traditions
became firmly established from the early 1920s onwards. Their
position with regard to the subjectiv~objective dimension of our
analytical scheme was broadly equivalent to that of Weber and
provided a happy compromise position between raw idealism and
sociological positivism. The focus was placed firmly upon ‘interac-
tion’, within which the study of ‘action’ and subjective meaning
played an important part. Given the interest in micro-social pro-
cesses, the thought of G. H. Mead in particular was immeasurably
richer than that of Weber, infused as it was with much stronger
elements of the phenomenological tradition.•• Weber had moved
towards positivism; Mead was moving towards phenomenology.
Weber·s typology of social action appears pale when compared
with Mead’s notions about the genesis of self. In addition, W. I.
Thomas’s ideas on ‘the definition of the situation’ had close links
with Weber·s notion of meaningful action. In the USA the
Weberian theory of social action thus confronted a strong, popu-
lar, tailor-made alternative and made relatively little impression as
far as its potential adherents were concerned. It was Weber·s fate
to be embraced by his critics. As we shall discuss in the next
chapter, the notion of the ‘ideal-type’ bureaucracy and the concept
of purposive rationality were utilised by objectivists, social system
theorists and bureaucracy theorists in a way Weber never
intended. His conceptual tools were used by theorists located
within the objectivist region of the functionalist paradigm which he
had devoted much of his intellectual energy to avoiding at all costs.
Moving in the opposite direction, his work was used as a starting
point for Schutz’s development of ·existential phenomenology’.
As we shall see in our chapter on the interpretive paradigm.
Schutz’s analysis, whilst full of praise for Weber, revealed
Weber’s position for what it was- a compromise between subjec-
tivist and objectivist views of social life. With the resurgence of
interest in the subjective approach to sociology which took place
on the West Coast of the USA during the 1960s. therefore. it was
the work of Schutz rather than that of Weber which provided the
stimulus for further developments. Ethnomethodology and
phenomenoiQgical symbolic interclctionism had little use for
Weber’s analysis. In addition. as will become clear from our dis-
cussion of radical humanism in Chapter 8, Weber’s work was also
subjected to a through-going critique from yet another perspective
in the work of Herbert Marcuse. As far as the USA is concerned.
therefore. the Weberian influence has been perverse; the critics of
Functionalist Sociology 81
Weber have arguably been more influential than Weber himself.
In Europe the Weberian tradition has achieved quite a lot more
prominence, though here again the interpretations placed upon
Weber’s work are in many cases contrary to those Weber would
have wished. In particular, his work has been used by what we
shall call radical Weberians operating within the context of the
radical structuralist paradigm in their debate with Marxist theory,
who have produced a radical conflict theory of society. The work
of Dahrendorf ( 1959), which we have already discussed to an
extent in Chapter 2. provides a prominent example of this perspec-
tive, though we shall have yet more to say about it in our discussion
of radical structuralism in Chapters 10 and II. As far as Weber·s
theory of social action is concerned, since the early 1960s it has
received attention, in general terms, in the work of Rex ( 1961) and
Eldridge ( 1971) and is reflected in the empirical studies conducted
by Gold thorpe and his colleagues ( 1968) on orientations to work. It
has also achieved prominence through Silverman’s (1970) advo-
cacy of tbe action frame of reference as an alternative to the
·systems orthodoxy’ in organisation theory. We shall devote
further attention to some of these works in our discussion of
organisation theory in Chapter 5.
By way of conclusion. we note here that social action theory,
like the interactionist thought of Mead and Simmel, can be under-
stood in terms of an attempt to weld together idealist and positivist
approaches to the study of society. In essence, they define an
intermediate position in relation to the subjectiv~objective
dimension of our analytical scheme, characteristic of the subjectiv-
ist boundary of the functionalist paradigm. However, as we have
seen, they are often employed in practice in a manner consistent
with a whole range of ontological, epistemological and
methodological assumptions.
Integrative Theory
We use the term •integrative theory’ to characterise the brand of
sociological theorising which occupies the middle ground within
the functionalist paradigm.ln essence, it seeks to integrate various
elements of interactionism and social systems theory and, in cer-
tain cases, to counter the challenge to the functionalist perspective
posed by theories characteristic of the radical structuralist para-
digm, particularly those of Marx. It is by no means a coherent body
of theory, and we shall discuss it under the following four bead-
88 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
ings, which identify its most important variations: (a) Blau’s
exchange and power model; (b) Mertonian theory of social and
cultural structure: (c) conflict functionalism: (d) morphogenic sys-
tems theory.
Each of these four strains of thought rests upon the assumption
that the achievement of social order within society is in some way
problematic and calls for explanations which are not normally
provided within the bounds of social systems theory.
Blau’s theory emphasises the role of exchange and power as a
central source of integration in social life. Merton’s theory of
social and cultural structure tends to emphasise the functions
performed by elements of social structure in the integrative pro-
cess. Conflict functionalism tends to focus upon the ‘positive·
functions served by conflict. Morphogenic systems theory
emphasises the importance of information transmission as a cen-
tral variable of analysis. In the following sections we will briefly
discuss each in tum, demonstrating how they have drawn upon
various aspects of the cross-currents of sociological thought
reviewed earlier in the chapter and have been shaped into a distinc-
tive theoretical perspective.
Blau ‘s exchange and power model
Blau’s theory of exchange and power in social life ( 1964) sets out to
analyse the processes which govern human association, with a
view to establishing the basis for a theory of social structure. His
theory attempts to link the micro- and macro-levels of social
analysis – to build a bridge between interactionism and social
system theory. In this Blau draws heavily upon the perspectives
generally developed by Simmel and by Homans (1958 and 1961).
Blau, following Simmel, regards the study of social association
as the central task of sociology. and in this respect he is clearly
‘interactionist’ in his approach. However, he is firmly set against
reductionist explanations of society, since they ignore what he
calls the ·emergent properties’ of human interaction. For Blau,
society is more than the sum of its parts. Social structure cannot be
reduced to a series of constituent elements; it has to be understood
as an emergent social process.
In Blau’s hands the notion of ‘exchange’ is given a limited but
powerful role and is used as an analytical tool for tracing the
emergent properties of social interaction.49 For Homans, all
Functionali.tt Sociology 89
human behaviour and interaction can be understood in terms of
exchange based upon a form of economic calculus. Blau rejects
this. He recognises that what he identifies as ‘social exchange’ 50
only accounts for a part of the whole range of human action and
behaviour and thr.t Homans ‘s economic calculus only applies to an
element of this. His analysis of the process of social exchange
leads him to identify the ways in which status and power become
differentiated, and the way in which power makes it possible to
organise collective effort. He traces the manner in which the
legitmation of power has its source in the social approval its fair
exercise evokes among subordinates. His analysis recognises that
normative consensus is by no means automatic, and that the exer-
cise of power will not always be legitimised. Power, legitimised or
not, is thus a central variable in his analysis, providing a major
factor in accounting for social integration and control. 51
Blau is concerned to shift the balance in sociological theory
away from an emphasis upon normative consensus-orientated
explanations of social integration towards analysis of social
associations, the processes that sustain them, the forms they attain
and the complex social forces and structures to which they give
rise. He summarises the situation as follows:
A concern with social action, broadly conceived as any conduct that
derives its impetus and meaning from social values, has characterised
contemporary theory in sociology for some years. The resulting preoc-
cupation with value orientations has diverted theoretical attention
from the study of the actual associations between people and the
structures of their associations. While structures of social relations are,
of course, profoundly influenced by common values, these structures
have a significance of their own, which is ignored if concern is exclu-
sively with the underlying values and norms. Exchange transactions
and power relations, in particular, constitute social forces that must be
investigated in their own right, not merely in terms of the norms that
limit and the values that reinforce them. to arrive at an understanding
of the dynamics of social structures. (Biau. 1964. p. 13)
His analysis emphasises the role of exchange and power in the
emergence of social structure and thus their role as integrative
forces in any explanation of society as an ongoing process. The
Simmelian view of society as ‘sewn together’ by a variety of
cross-cutting conflicts between its component parts is prominent
in Blau’s work. He analyses the relationships between sub-
elements of society and the way in which conflicts produce a
pattern of dialectical change. As he puts it,
90 Sociological Paradigms and Organisalional Analysis
The cross-cutting conflicts and oppositions in complex. modem
societies, with many intersecting organised collectivities and interlock-
ing memberships in them, are a continual source of social reorganisa-
tion and change. The pattern eX change is dialectical, since each basic
reorganisation has wide repercussions that create new problems and
stimulate fresh oppositions. The cross pressures resulting from multi-
group affiliations and the recurrent alignments eX overlapping collec-
tivities in different controversies prevent conflicts over issues from
becoming cumulative and producing a deep cleavage between two
hostile camps. (Biau, 1964, p. 311)
Blau ‘s analysis thus builds from an interactionist view of associ-
ation towards a theory of social change which, inhis interpretation
of the spirit of a dialectic, involves neither evolutionary progress in
a straight line nor recurring cycles but alternating patterns of
intermittent social reorganisation along different lines. It is a per-
spective which sees society oscillating under the influence of
recurrent dis-equilibrating and re-equilibrating· forces. Although
recognising conflict as inherent in all social affairs, Blau’s view is
thus firmly rooted in the sociology of regulation. His work on
exchange and power in social life represents an attempt to develop
the interactionist perspective into an ‘integrative theory’ of social
structure.
Mertonian theory of social and cultural
structure
This second brand of integrative theory builds upon the work of
Robert Merton, who in many respects can be regarded as the
integrative sociologist par excellence. His work reflects the direct
influence of writers as widely diverse as Durkheim, Marx, Mead,
Parsons, Simmel and Weber, and has been subject to a wide range
ofinterpretations.52 As we shall argue, Merton’s work is integra-
tive in the sense that it seeks to link a number of conceptually
distinct theories within the context of the functionalist paradigm.lt
is also integrative in the sense that it seeks to link micro- and
macro-levels of analysis, empiricism and grand theory, through
what Merton has described as theories of the ‘middle range’
(Merton, 1968). Although integrative theory as defined here would
for the most part correspond with Merton’s specification of the
·middle range’, it is not identical with it, since it is possible to
develop ‘middle-range’ theories in a number of areas within the
functionalist paradigm.
We take our point of departure here, from Merton’s early work
Functionalist Sociology 91
on ‘reference groups’ and ‘anomie theory’, which seeks to under-
stand how sub-groupings arise within the context of the social
structure (Merton, 1968). In his paper ‘Social Structure and
Anomie’. first published in 1938, Merton seeks to discover how
social structures exert a definite pressure upon certain persons in a
society to engage in non-conforming behaviour. His perspective is
described as that of a ‘functional analyst who considers socially
deviant behaviour just as much a product of social structure as
conformist behaviour’ (Merton, 1968, p. 175). In essence, his
paper represents a direct attempt to counter the tendency preval-
ent within functional analysis of explaining social behaviour in
terms of its orientation towards a system of central normative
values. Merton’s work thus stands out against the sort of explana-
tions offered in Parsonian systems theory and attempts to modify
the functionalist perspective so as to introduce elements capable of
explaining the process of social change. By tracing the possible
relationships between two elements of social structure – ‘cultural
goals’ and the ‘institutionalised means’ of achiev-ng them –
Merton is able to develop a typology of individual adaptation
which, in addition to ·conformity’, allows for aberrant behaviour
associated with ‘innovation’. ‘ritualism’, ‘retreatism • and
‘rebellion’ (Merton. 1968, p. 194).
Merton’s analysis must be understood as an attempt to streng-
then functionalism. His treatment of aberrant or deviant behaviour
stands in stark contrast to a symbolic interactionist view. which
would stress the emergent character of norms and values. From an
interactionist perspective, norms and values are socially generated
and sustained by human beings in their everyday interaction with
others. For Merton. they are part of a predefined social context
within which social action takes place. Thus, whilst Merton’s
functional analysis of deviance moves some way from social sys-
tem theory towards an interactionist perspective, it remains fun-
damentally distinct in terms of the position occupied on the
subjectivo-objective continuum of our analytical scheme.
This intermediate position is also evident in Merton’s analysis of
reference group behaviour. As he suggests, his work in this area
represents an effort to utilize functional analysis in the study of
reference groups as an important component of social structure
(Merton, 1968, p. 181). According to Merton, ‘reference group
theory aims to systematise the determinants and consequences of
those processes of evaluation and self-appraisal in which the indi-
vidual takes the values or standards of other individuals or groups
as a comparative frame of reference’ (Merton, 1968, p. 288).
92 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
This view of reference groups is a direct development of Mead’s
‘generalised other’ – a notion used by Mead to explain the
emergence of self through interaction (Mead, 1934, pp. 152-64).
Merton thus uses an interactionist concept for the analysis of
social structure. In doing so, he again integrates certain aspects of
interactionism with social system theory. This is clearly evident in
his concern for the problem of identifying ‘functional types’ of
reference groups and subsequent research directed towards this
endeavour. Kelley ( 1968), for example, has distinguished between
two kinds of reference groups according to the two functions they
perform in the determination of attitudes. The first of these – the
normative function – is seen as being concerned with the setting
and enforcing of standards, a possibility which arises whenever a
group is in a position to deliver rewards or punishments for con-
formity or non-conformity.n The second- thecomparisonfunc-
tion – refers to the role of a reference group in providing a standard
or point of comparison against which a person can evaluate himself
or others.
Merton’s contribution to both reference group theory and
anomie theory has provided a fruitful basis for further detailed
theorising and empirical research. As an examination of Hyman
and Singer’s ( 1968) collection of readings on reference groups and
Clinard’s ( 1964) readings on anomie and deviant behaviour will
reveal, the manner and context in which the notions have been
applied is quite diverse. Some of it is true to the integrative style
characteristic of Merton’s work and occupies a similar position
within the context of the functionalist paradigm. The remainder is
often much more objectivist in orientation and in certain cases is
more appropriately classified as abstracted empiricism. As in
other areas of the functionalist paradigm, positivist methodology
has often done rough justice to the more subjectivist elements of
the underlying theory on which the research is ostensibly based.
Merton’s sociology is complex and wide-ranging. In the areas of
theorising discussed above. emphasis tends to be placed upon the
problematic nature of social order. Merton seeks to demonstrate
that whilst the process of social integration is not as straightfor-
ward as many social systems theorists have presumed, an analysis
of the relationship between human behaviour and social structure
can demonstrate the ways in which order or deviance arise. In the
work which we have discussed thus far problems of change and
conflict are recognised but not pursued in any depth. In later work
Merton becomes increasingly involved with these problems and
lays the basis for another brand of integrative theory – conflict
Functionalist Sociology 93
functionalism. His article ‘Bureaucratic Structure and Personal-
ity’ (Merton, 1968, pp. 249-60) marks the point of transition to this
perspective. Using functional theory in the analysis of bureaucra-
tic activities, he demonstrates how conformity to regulations can
be dysfunctional for realising the objectives of the structure and
the groups in society the bureaucracy is intended to serve.'” In
other words, Merton demonstrates that conformity to normative
standards can actually provide a force for the disintegration of the
social order, a perspective which is further developed in his
analysis of manifest and latent functions discussed below.
Conflict functionalism
This third category of integrative theory developed as a response
to the charges that functionalist theories of society are unable to
provide explanations of social change and are essentially conser-
vative in orientation. It represents a fusion of the functionalist
tradition with the theories of Simmel and an incorporation of the
work of Marx. Whilst most of its leading proponents, such as
Merton and Coser, pose as critics of functionalism, they have
perhaps done more than its enthusiastic adherents to establish the
overall dominance of the functionalist approach over the last
twenty-five years. Their ‘radical’ critique has done much to
remedy the deficiencies of more conventional approaches to the
extent that certain theorists have argued that there is now a con-
vergence between the analytical characteristics of Marxism and
functionalism. ss
The basis of conflict functionalism was in many respects laid in
Merton’s classic article of 1948, ‘Manifest and Latent Functions’
(reproduced in Merton, 1968). This piece set out to codify and
bring together the diverse strands of functionalism and to provide a
comprehensive critique. Merton’s argument was directed against
three central postulates of traditional functional analysis which he
argued were debatable and unnecessary to the functional orienta-
tion as such. These were(a) the ‘postulate of the functional unity of
society’ – that is. ‘that standardised social activities or cultural
items are functional fortheentire social or cultural system’; (b) the
‘postulate of universal functionalism· – that is, ‘that all social and
cultural items fulfil sociological functions’; (c) the ‘postulate of
indispensability’ – that is, ‘that these items are consequently
indispensable’ (Merton, 1968, pp. 79-91).
94 Sociologic·al Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Merton discussed each of these postulates in relation to cases
drawn from functionalist anthropology and demonstrated that they
were by no means always true. In essence he argued that (a)
societies are not unitary in nature – certain elements may be
functionally autonomous and hence the degree of integration is an
empirical variable; (b) societies may have non-functional ele-
ments, such as ‘survivals’ from the past, which need not necessar-
ily make a positive contribution; (c) societies are quite capable of
dispensing with certain activities without prejudice to their survi-
val and, in any case, are capable of developing alternatives.
This critique of traditional functionalism led to a focus upon a
number offactors which are usually excluded from consideration.
Most importantly, it introduced the notion of ‘dysfunctions’ and
the problematical nature of social integration, and it recognised
that a particular social unit or activity may have negative con-
sequences for society as a whole or for some particular part of it. It
also attacked the concept of ‘functional prerequisites’ or ·precon-
ditions functionally necessary for a society’, thus questioning the
•indispensability’ of certain cultural forms. It opened the way for a
consideration of ‘functional alternatives’, ‘functional equivalents’
or ‘functional substitutes’. Merton recognised that functional
needs are permissive rather than determinant and that there is a
range of variation in the structures which fulfil any given function
(Merton, 1968, p. 88).
Merton’s critique paved the way for an approach to functional
analysis which, in contrast to traditional functionalism, sees the
nature of social order as essentially problematic, allows analysis to
take place from a variety of perspectives and gives full recognition
to the process of social change. As Gouldner has noted, one of the
strengths of Merton’s approach is that it ‘prevents either prema-
ture commitment to, or premature exclusion of, any given struc-
ture as an element in the social system’ (Gouldner, 1959, p. 194).
Merton is concerned to establish functionalism as an essentially
neutral analytical tool. He recognises that its previous use has
been tainted with ideology and demonstrates how in different
hands it has attracted the charges of being both ‘conservative’ and
‘radical’. On the basis of this he argues that functional analysis
does not entail any necessary or intrinsic ideological commitment
– ideology is an extraneous factor resulting from the manner in
which functionalism is used. In order to demonstrate this he pre-
sents a detailed point-by-point comparison of dialectical material-
ism and functional analysis. Taking Marx and Engels’ statements
on dialectical materialism as a starting point, Merton specifies an
Functionalist Sociology 9S
equivalent statement in terms of functional analysis. His overall
purpose in doing so is unclear. Whilst it directly illustrates his point
about ideology, it also leaves the reader wondering whether Mer-
ton is suggesting that functional analysis can be substituted for the
Marxist dialectic or whether he is merely seeking to introduce
certain Marxist notions to his functionalist audience. Whatever the
motive, its impact on sociological thought is clear. Merton’s article
has above all served the purpose of suggesting that the problems
addressed by Marxism can be handled through appropriate forms
of functional analysis. As will become evident from our discussion
below, conflict functionalism, in essence, can be seen as the func-
tionalists’ response to Marx.
Perhaps significantly, Merton did not choose to follow the
“radical’ implications of his critique of traditional functionalism.
As we shall argue later, the notions of •dysfunction’ and •func-
tional autonomy’, if followed to their logical conclusion, lead
towards the notion of contradiction. The task of following this path
was left for one of his students, Alvin Gouldner (1959). In the
remainder of his article Merton contents himself with an analysis
of the problem of the items to be subjected to functional analysis
and the issue of manifest and latent functions. s• As Merton notes,
the notions of manifest and latent functions have a particularly
important contribution to make to functional analysis. In particu-
lar, they can clarify the analysis of ‘seemingly irrational social
patterns’ and also direct attention to theoretically fruitful fields of
investigation. Indeed, the notions have provided sociologists with
a means of directing their enquiry beyond the familiar and super-
ficially related patterns of social activities towards analysis of un-
recognised functions. The discovery of latent functions provided
yet another means of explaining the ordered pattern of social
affairs – through the identification of ways in which the ‘un-
intended consequences • of social action perform positive
functions within its context of the wider social system.
The influence of these ideas is particularly evident in the work of
Coser (1956 and 1967). His analysis of social conflict represents in
large measure an attempt to extend Simmel’s insights into the
subject through the perspective developed by Merton. In essence,
it represents an analysis of the latent functions of social conflict.
Coser builds upon a central thesis running through Simmel’s
work -that ·conflict is a form of socialisation’ and that no group
can be entirely harmonious. Paraphrasing Simmel, he suggests
that:
96 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
no group can be entirely harmonious, for it would then be devoid of
process and structure. Groups require disharmony as well as harmony.
dissociation as well as association; and conflicts within them are by no
means altogether disruptive factors. Group formation is the result of
both types of processes … both ·positive’ and ·negative’ factors build
group relations. Conflict as well as co-operation has social functions.
Far from being necessarily dysfunctional, a certain degree of conflict is
an essential element in group formation and the persistence of group
life. (Coser, 1956, p. 31)
In his essay Coser takes a series of propositions from Simmel’s
work and systematically analyses the manner and ·conditions
under which social conflict may contribute to the maintenance,
adjustment or adaption of social relationships and social struc-
tures’ (Coser, 1956, p. 151). As the title of his work suggests, Coser
is specifically concerned with the functions of social conflict, and
he builds up to a conclusion which emphasises the fundamental
importance of the relationship between conflict and its institu-
tional context in determining the stability of the overall social
system. Coser’s essay ends with a classic formulation of the plural-
ist perspective on social organisation, in which conflict is viewed
as an essential ingredient of social life, creating strains and ten-
sions with which the institutional structure must cope if the social
system is to stabilise itself and evolve in an ordered manner. As we
shall show in Chapter 5, this pluralist view is of considerable
significance as far as the study of organisations is concerned.
In an essay written at the same time as ‘The Functions of Social
Conflict’, Coser extends his analysis to cover situations in which
social systems actually break their boundaries and lead to the
establishment of new ones (Coser, 1967, pp. 17-35). The focus is
upon the problems of social change, and an attempt is made to
·specify the structural conditions under which social conflicts lead
to inner adjustments of social systems or the break-up of existing
social orders and the emergence of a new set of social relations
within a new social structure’ (Coser, 1967, p. 18). In addition to
generating new norms and new institutions, conflict is seen as
stimulating technological innovation and economic change.
Coser’s analysis draws simultaneously on the work of such diverse
theorists as Weber, Marx, Parsons and Veblen, although the ideas
of none are followed in depth to their logical conclusion. Coser
seems less interested in understanding the process of social change
than in identifying the situations in which change can be con-
strained by institutional mechanisms. Whilst Coser follows
Merton in his views on the ideological misuse of functionalism,
Functionalist Sociology CJ7
there is, in fact, a strong normative undertone in his writings. His
analysis of change is strongly orientated towards the development
of a theory which explains how conflicts can be controlled and
channelled through a system of normative regulation. This general
orientation is very evident in Coser’s other papers on, for example,
the termination of conflict, the social functions of violence and its
role in conflict resolution, and the fu.nctions of deviant behaviour
and normative flexibility (Coser, 1967). Coser’s whole theory of
conflict is essentially pluralist in its ideological stance.
Both Merton and Coser, though critical offunctionalism, are in
essence committed to its problematic. It is for this reason that we
identify their work as conflict functionalism. They recognise that
social integration is by no means the straightforward process
implicit in the work of normative functionalists such as Parsons,
and they do much to recognise the role of conflict in social life.
However, their view is firmly rooted in the sociology of regulation,
a paradox clearly illustrated by the way in which conflict, particu-
larly in Coser’s hands, can be used as a conceptual tool for explain-
ing social order. Despite their protestations to the contrary, their
problematic is that of social order- they are principally concerned
to explain why it is that society tends to hold together rather than
fall apart.
Their position in this regard is clearly illustrated when compared
with the critique of functionalism presented by Gouldner (1959).
Taking the concept of system as a starting point, Gouldner argues
that if one compares the work of Merton and Parsons, one finds
many differences in approach but an underlying similarity with
regard to the ·strategic place of the concept of a system. especially
as an explanatory tool’ (Gou!dner, 1959, p. 198). He demonstrates
that Merton,like Parsons, is concerned with explaining the persis-
tence of social factors and in so doing tends to provide a ·partial
and one-sided’ explanation, since he fails to give specific attention
to the concept of ‘functional reciprocity’. For this reason explana-
tions are likely to be incomplete. since, as he puts it, ‘the only
logically stable terminal point for a functional analysis is not the
demonstration of a social pattern’s function for others, but the
demonstration of the latter’s reciprocal functionality for the prob-
lematic social pattern’ (Gouldner, 1959, pp. 199-200).
In other words, it is necessary to demonstrate functionality
within a reciprocal context. This concept of ‘functional reciproc-
ity’ is crucial to the notion of interdependence of parts which is so
central to functional analysis. It is quite remarkable, therefore,
that it has not been given more systematic consideration by func-
98 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
tional analysts, since if functional reciprocity is asymmetrical,
then the whole notion of interdependence becomes open to ques-
tion. In recognising this, Gouldner arrives at a conclusion similar
to Merton’s but by a different route. For Merton, it is the recogni-
tion of •dysfunctions’ that leads him to view social integration as
problematic.
However, in contrast to Merton, Gouldner carries the logic of
his analysis much further. The notion of varying degrees of inter-
dependence among the parts of a system leads him to the concept
of •functional autonomy’ which, operationally speaking, relates to
the probability of a system part’s survival in separation from the
system. High system interdependence means low functional
autonomy of parts, and vice versa. This notion of functional auton-
omy is important, since it reflects a view which focuses upon the
parts of a system (albeit in their relation to each other). This is in
direct contrast to the more usual systems view, which tends to
focus upon the whole and sees the parts in their relation to the
whole. Gouldner’s analysis is important, in that it focuses atten-
tion upon interchanges where functional reciprocity may not be
symmetrical and thus directs analysis to tension-producing
relationships. In this way Gouldner, starting from a systems per-
spective, arrives at the notion of •contradiction’, with a focus upon
incompatible elements of a social system. Building upon the idea
that the parts of a system may seek to maintain their functional
autonomy, he shows how attempts at system control are likely to
generate conflict. Moreover, system parts may take positive steps
to resist incorporation and containment, and may generate
changes in the system itself which are consistent within their
overall autonomy. Different parts are likely to have ·greater or
lesser vested interest in system maintenance’ (Gouldner, 1959, p.
211).
This focus upon functional autonomy thus raises many issues
which contradict the tenets of traditional systems theory and func-
tional analysis. It places the parts rather than the whole at the
centre of analysis. The focus upon contradictions provides an
explanation of change and conflict which contributes to the inter-
ests and independence of the constituent elements of a system
rather than the abstract whole. Although Gouldner only makes
passing reference to Marx on two occasions in the whole of the
article and couches his discussion almost exclusively in terms of
the functionalist problematic, this piece of work represents a
cautious but, in essence, truly radical critique of the functionalist
approach to social analysis. It contains many signs and elements of
Functionalist Sociology 99
the thought of the ‘Marxist outlaw’ which finds much clearer and
more direct expression in some of Gouldner’s later work. 57
Gouldner’s critique clearly serves to illustrate the extent to
which Merton and Coser are committed to a view of society rooted
in the sociology of regulation. Although they recognise the prob-
lematic nature of social integration and the relevance of Marxist
theory, they do not pursue the full implications of these issues. As
in the case of other conflict functionalists who have followed in
their footsteps, they have incorporated and reinterpreted the con-
cerns of Marx within the problematic of functionalism. Although
they have recognised the existence of ‘dysfunctions’ within social
systems and some of the consequences which this entails, they
have stopped short of a theory of contradiction. As Gouldner has
suggested. they have remained ‘functionalists’ at heart, in that
they have not chosen to develop ‘dysfunctionalism’ as an alterna-
tive (Gouldner, 1970, p. 336). As we shall see, this would have led
to a perspective characteristic of the radical structuralist para-
digm.
Morphogenic systems theory
This brand of integrative theory is principally associated with the
work of Buckley (1967) and the ‘process model’ which he advo-
cates for the study ofsociety.ln essence, Buckley·s work attempts
to introduce to the social sciences the modern systems theory
reflected in cybernetics, information and communication theory
and general systems research. His work attempts to present a
systems model with the capacity to explain the way in which
societies change and elaborate their basic structures. His process
model embraces and attempts to synthesise the whole range of
thought contained within the functionalist paradigm – from
interactionism to social systems theory – and makes passing
reference to some of the ideas of Marx. It represents an extremely
sophisticated attempt to develop an integrative systems model
characteristic of the middle ground of the paradigm.
Buckley begins his analysis by recognising that the usual
mechanical and organic systems models employed in the social
sciences are inherently inadequate for their task, parti cu larl y when
it comes to analysing factors such as ‘structurally induced and
maintained conflict and dissensus; the structure elaborating and
changing feature of all societies; the theoretical status of less
100 Socioloeical Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
structured “collective” behaviour as a neglected but Important
aspect ofthe social system; the systemic status of “deviance” and
“social control’ .. (Buckley, 1967, p. 4). He is thus essentially
interested in the same kinds of functionalist issues as other integra-
tive theorists, especially Merton, though his analysis and proposed
solutions are quite different.
Buckley maintains that mechanical and organic systems models
are inadequate, since they are based upon an outdated view of
science and do not recognise the special qualities of socio-cultural
systems. 58 He argues that in the twentieth century there has been a
shifting scientific perspective, reflected in the growth of cyberne-
tics, information and communication theory and general systems
research, which ‘marks the transition from a concern for eternal
substance and the dynamics of energy transformation to a focus on
organisation and its dynamics based on the ”triggering” effects of
information transmission’ (Buckley, 1967, pp. 1-2). He argues
that the social sciences need to adopt this perspective in recog-
nition of the true character of socio-cultural systems whose mor-
phogenic properties distinguish them from other types of biolog-
ical and physical systems.
After providing a comprehensive critique of the mechanical and
organic systems models, with specific reference to those of
Parsons (1951) and Homans (1950), Buckley develops a process
model which, in essence, represents a fusion of various strains of
interactionism and modern systems theory. Buckley seeks to re-
interpret the work of theorists such as G. H. Mead, Simmel, Small,
Park, Burgess, Blumer and other members of the Chicago School
of sociology within the context of cybernetics and information
theory.
Buckley’s model attempts to link micro- and macro-levels of
analysis, building from the Meadian notion of the ·act’ and the
basic symbolic interaction process, through the notion of ‘role’
and role dynamics, to the emergence of organisations and institu-
tions. The socio-cultural system is viewed as a ·set of elements
linked almost entirely by way of the intercommunication of infor-
mation (in the broad sense) rather than being energy- or
substance-linked as are physical or organismic systems’ (Buckley,
1967, p. 82). It emerges from a network of interaction among
individuals in which information is selectively perceived and
interpreted in accordance with the meaning it holds for the actors
involved. The model is processual rather than structural in nature.
‘Information’, for example, is regarded as a ‘carrier of meaning’
rather than as ‘an entity that exists some place or flows from one
Functionalist Sociology 101
place to another’ (Buckley. 1967. p. 92).1t is a relation rather than a
thing. Society is viewed as an organisation of meanings which
emerge from the process of interaction between individuals deal-
ing with a more or less common environment. Meanings may be
sufficiently stable or clear to become generalised as codes. rules or
norms for behaviour. However, these norms are not to be con-
fused with ‘the actual organisational process they partly inform’
(Buckley, 1967. p. 94). Society remains an intangible process of
interaction which ultimately rests with the actors directly involved
and the way in which they choose to interpret and respond to their
environment. The essentially processual nature of socio-cultural
systems is not to be confused with the structure or organisation its
components may take on at any particular time.
Buckley has undoubtedly made an important contribution to the
application of systems theory in the social sciences. His argument
that socio-cultural systems are not amenable to adequate study
through the use of equilibrium or homeostatic models challenges
the validity and usefulness of virtually all the social systems
studies which have been made to date. Conceptually, his process
model represents a considerable advance over these earlier
approaches, restoring the processual element so essential to the
very notion of system.
At first sight Buckley’s interest in interactionist thought could
be seen as an argument for locating him on the subjectivist boun-
dary of the functionalist paradigm. This, however, would be an
error. Buckley gives a great deal of attention to the work of
interactionists such as Mead, because he interprets their work as
being consistent with his own, at least in contrast to that of social
theorists such as Parsons. Buckley is able to argue that the interac-
tionist perspective represents a step in the right direction as far as
social research is concerned, being ‘congenial to- even anticipa-
tive of- basic principles of cybernetics’ (Buckley, 1967, p. 17). If
one has to rank his priorities, one can fairly conclude that Buckley
is systems theorist first, interactionist second. His main concern is
to translate the work of the interactionists into the concepts and
language of cybernetics, which, as part of a general systems pers-
pective, he sees as providing a framework for organising the
insights derived from interactionist research. Buckley’s work can
best be understood as that of a systems theorist concerned to
synthesise various elements within the functionalist paradigm. He
attempts to bridge the gulf between interactionism and social sys-
tems theory from a systems perspective.
Our discussion of Buckley’s work concludes our brief review of
102 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
integrative theory. In their different ways, all four of the brands
which we have considered seek to bridge the gap between interac-
tionism and social system theory. Conflict functionalism also
attempts to bridge the gap between the functionalist and radical
structuralist paradigms. Placing emphasis upon different analyti-
cal variables, they have all made a substantial contribution to the
development and general sophistication offunctionalist theory by
seeking to synthesise its potentially divergent elements.
Objectivism
We use the term ‘objectivism’ to refer to the considerable amount
of sociological work located on the objectivist boundary of the
functionalist paradigm. It is characterised by an extremely high
degree of commitment to models and methods derived from the
natural sciences.
The relationship between social systems theory and objectivism
is thus obviously a close one. The difference between them hinges
upon what may be described as the difference between metaphor
and reality. Social systems theorists use the biological and physi-
cal world as a source of analogies for studying the social world, as a
source of hypotheses and insight. Objectivists, on the other hand,
treat the social world exactly as if it were the natural world; they
treat human beings as machines or biological organisms, and social
structure as if it were a physical structure. We identify two broad
types of objectivism – behaviourism and abstracted empiricism.
Behaviourism
The notion of behaviourism is most often associated with the work
of B. F. Skinner, who has attempted to develop causal theories of
behaviour based upon an analysis of stimulus and response. 59 For
this purpose man is treated, like any other natural organism, as
entirely the product of his environment. Man, in essence, is
regarded as little more than a machine, responding in a determinis-
tic way to the external conditions to which he is exposed. In
Skinner’s work all reference to subjective states of mind are consi-
dered irrelevant- indeed, counterproductive- as far as scientific
enquiry is concerned. As Skinner has put it,
the practice of looking inside an organism for an explanation cl
behaviour has tended to obscure the variables which are immediately
Functionalist Sociology 103
available for scientific analysis. These variables lie outside the organ-
ism. in its immediate environment and in its environmental history.
They have a physical status to which the usual techniques of science
are adapted, and they make it possible to explain behaviour as other
subjects are explained in science. (Skinner, 1953. p. 31)
Skinner’s approach to the study of human behaviour is very
much geared to the use of experimental methods typical of those
utilised in the natural sciences. He is committed to the view that
one learns about phenomena under investigation by careful man-
ipulation of particular stimuli in controlled situations in which all
other environmental influences are either excluded or accounted
for in some way. It is a method which approximates a closed
system form of analysis. The study of human behaviour from this
perspective is very much an activity aimed at the discovery of
universal laws and regularities which underlie the science of man.
These laws exist out there in the external world. The social scien-
tist’s task is to discover them.
Skinner’s perspective is a highly coherent and consistent one in
terms ofthe four strands of the subjectiv~objective dimension of
our analytical scheme. Ontologically, his view is firmly realist;
epistemologically, his work is the archetype of positivism; his view
of human nature reflects a determinism of an extreme form; the
highly nomothetic methodology reflected in his experimental
approach is congruent with these other assumptions.
On the regulatio~radical change dimension Skinner occupies
an equally extreme position. His view of the social world is one
which emphasises the possibility and desirability of both predic-
tion and control. He has been greatly concerned to develop a
technology of behaviour modification and to spell out its relation-
ships in a wider social context (Skinner, 1972). His theory is truly
regulative in orientation. in that. given the correct conditioning
environment, Skinner believes that human behaviour can be
moulded and transformed into a perfectly ordered and regular
pattern. We argue that Skinner’s behaviourism occupies a position
at the extremities of both dimensions of the functionalist paradigm.
Skinner’s theorising reflects a behaviourisf!t of an extreme form
which. outside the realm of experimental psychology, has not
served directly as a model for theory and research in the social
sciences. However, there are a number of behavioural theories
which are directly related to Skinner’s model, such as the
exchange theory developed by Homans ( 1958 and 1961). There are
also many theories which share Skinner’s assumptions in relation
104 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
to the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme.
Those which attempt to explain behaviour in terms of universal
psychological Jaws fall into this category. For example, many
studies examining work group behaviour and motivation at work
are based upon this type of thinking. 60 Wider social or environ-
mental influences are ignored, and indeed in many experimental
and research designs a deliberate attempt is made to exclude them;
the rationale of ‘controlled’ experiments and research constitutes
the epitome of such closed system thinking. Another related
category of theory is found in the work of those theorists some-
times labelled determinists. Their focus of interest rests not upon
the psychological make-up of the individuals to be studied but
upon the environment in which they operate. Their energies are
addressed to establishing situational laws which determine human
behaviour. Studies of the relationship between .work behaviour
and technology, leadership styles, payment systems, etc., often
provide illustrations of this perspective. The ‘situational deter-
minant’ is viewed as all-important; individuals are assigned essen-
tially passive and responding roles in relation to the conditions
which they encounter in their immediate environment.
These types of theorising and research have had considerable
influence in the field of organisational studies and will receive
further attention in Chapter S. We close our discussion here by
re-emphasising their behaviouristic nature and the close parallels
which exist with Skinner’s work. Like Skinner. the theorists who
~vocate such views occupy a clear and consistent position in
terms of the four strands of the subjective-objective dimension of
our analytical scheme. Their determinist stance is paralleled by
equally objectivist assumptions in relation to ontology, epistemol-
ogy and methodology. However, in relation to the regulation-
radical change dimension they are usually committed to a position
which allows for more flexibility and variation than Skinner·s
model.
Abstracted empiricism
At certain points in our discussion of the schools of thought associ-
ated with interactionism, integrative theory. and social system
theory, we have referred to the fact that the work of various
theorists and researchers has ended up as abstracted empiricism.
Systems theorists who spend their energies measuring •struc-
Functionali.’it SocioloKY 105
tures’; interactionists who utilise static measurements of
‘attitudes’ and •role situations’; integrative theorists who attempt
to produce quantitative indices of ‘power’, ·conflict’, ‘deviancy’
and the like – all provide illustrations of abstracted empiricism, in
that they engage in empirical research which violates the assump-
tions of their theoretical perspective.
The term ‘abstracted empiricism’ has entered popular usage
largely through the work of C. Wright Mills ( 1959) who, in his
critique of theory_ and method in the social sciences, has used it to
describe the output of researchers who have allowed
methodologies derived from the natural sciences to dominate their
work. 61 We use it here in a related but more specific and limited
sense. Stating the position in terms of the subjective-objective
dimension of our analytical scheme, abstracted empiricism re-
presents a situation in which a highly nomothetic methodology is
used to test a theory which is based upon an ontology, an
epistemology and a theory of human nature of a more subjectivist
kind. It represents a situation in which a nomothetic methodology
is incongruent with the assumptions of the other three strands of
the subjective-objective dimension. It is with regard to this in-
congruence that abstracted empiricism differs from behaviourism.
As we have illustrated, Skinner and other behaviourists adopt a
perfectly coherent and congruent perspective in relation to the
four elements of the subjective-objective dimension. Their
engagement in the wholesale use of experimental and other
research methods derived from the natural sciences is consistent
with the nature of their theorising. Abstracted empiricism arises
in situations where the methods used are inconsistent with the
underlying theory.
It is a regrettable fact that a major proportion of research work in
the social sciences at the present time results in abstracted empiric-
ism. The drive to obtain research funding to sustain teams of
research workers tends to favour the collection of large quantities
of empirical data. Indeed, the collection and processing of such
data is often equated with the total research effort and is regarded
as an essential ingredient of any proposal likely to meet the ·quality
control’ requirements of research funding institutions. The
demands for pragmatic results from social science research pro-
grammes also tends to favour some form of substantive informa-
tion output. Under the pressure of such forces, research pro-
grammes often become tailored to the requirements and methods
of their data base, to the extent that theoretical assumptions with
regard to basic ontology, epistemology and human nature are
106 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
relegated to a background role and are eventually violated by the
demands of empiricism. It is no exaggeration to suggest that there
is scarcely a theoretical perspective within the context of the
functionalist paradigm which has not been translated into abstract
empiricism of one form or another.
We identify abstracted empiricism as being characteristic of the
objectivist boundary of the functionalist paradigm. We locate it
here in recognition of the fact that the bulk of such work arises as a
result of extreme commitment to nomothetic methodologies in
which quantitative measures of reified social constructs dominate
the reseach endeavour. It represents research in which the social
world is treated methodologically as if it were a world of hard,
concrete, tangible reality, whereas theoretically it is conceived as
being of a more subjectivist nature. The problem of adopting
methodologies appropriate to the nature of the phenomena under
investigation is a crucial one in contemporary social science. As
we shall see, it is also encountered by sociologists working within
the context of the interpretive paradigm. Problems of incongru-
ence between theory and method raise issues of concern to
sociologists of all kinds.
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
The functionalist paradigm contains a wide range of theorising. At
a superficial level. it is its diversity which is most apparent. The
contrasts between social system theory and interactionism, for
example, cannot fail to catch one’s attention. The differences
between the many schools of thought which we have identified are
clear. Beneath the diversity, however. there is an underlying unity
and form. The paradigm is characterised by a fundamental com-
monality of perspective in terms of basic, ‘taken for granted’
assumptions, which provide a hidden link between its constituent
theories and which distinguishes them from those in other para-
digms. Indeed, it is this underlying unity which the very notion of
paradigm reflects.
Theorists located in the functionalist paradigm are linked by a
shared view of the fundamental nature of the socio-scientific real-
ity to which their work is addressed. They are committed to a view
cl the social world which regards society as ontologically prior to
man and seek to place man and his activities within that wider
social context. Merton has noted that ‘the concept of function
Functionalist Sociology 107
involves the standpoint of the observer, not necessarily that of the
participant’ (Merton, 1968, p. 78). Theorists located within the
context of the functionalist paradigm tend to assume the stand-
point of the observer and attempt to relate what they observe to
what they regard as important elements in a wider social context.
This perspective is common to the interactionist, the integrative
theorist, the social system theorist and the objectivist.
The functionalist view of this wider social context also tends to
have many common reference points. It is a view which assumes a
continuing order and pattern. It is geared to providing an explana-
tion of what is. Allowing for various but limited degrees of order
and disorder, consensus and dissensus, social integration and dis-
integration, solidarity and conflict, need satisfaction and frustra-
tion, the overall endeavour is to provide an explanation of why the
social fabric of society tends to hold together. It is geared to
providing an explanation of the regulated nature of human affairs.
The paradigm is based upon an underlying norm of purposive
rationality. This concept provides a direct link between the two
dimensions which define the paradigm’s regulative and objectivist
view of the social world. The conception of science which under-
lies the paradigm emphasises the possibility of objective enquiry
capable of providing true explanatory and predictive knowledge of
an external reality .It is a conception which assumes that scientific
theories can be assessed objectively by reference to empirical
evidence. It is a conception which attributes independence to the
observer- an ability to observe what is, without affecting it. It is a
conception which assumes there are general external and universal
standards of science which can serve as a basis for determining
what constitutes an adequate explanation of what is observed. It is
a conception which, above all else, assumes that there are external
rules and regulations governing the external world.
The essential rationality reflected in this view of science is put to
use by the functionalist to explain the essential rationality of soci-
ety. Science provides a frame of reference for structuring and
ordering the social world, a frame of reference which emphasises
an order and coherence similar to that found in the natural world.
The methods of science are used to generate explanations of the
social world consistent with the nature and philosophy of science
itself. Science, in the functionalist’s hands, becomes a tool for
imposing order and regulation upon the social world – order and
regulation from the standpoint of the observer.
The diversity of thought which exists within the context of the
functionalist paradigm is a diversity within the confines of this
108 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
overall view of science and society. The various broad categories
and schools of thought differ in the degree and manner in which
they subscribe to and address themselves to common basic
assumptions. It is important to emphasise this. The difference
between theories within the paradigm is one of degree rather than
offundamental perspective, a feature which becomes clearly evi-
dent when theories are compared with those located in other
paradigms.
As we have attempted to show, differences within the paradigm
reflect the intellectual response to the interaction between the
main currents of sociological thought which have come into prom-
inence in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Building upon
basic models derived from the natural sciences (as modified by
Comte, Spencer, Pareto and Durkheim), sociologists have
responded to the external challenge and threat posed by alterna-
tive intellectual traditions through both fusion and incorporation.
As we have seen, elements of German idealism have been fused
with the Anglo-French tradition to produce interactionism.
Aspects of the work of Marx has been incorporated into integrative
theory. In each case the rival intellectual tradition has been sucked
into the paradigm and used in a manner which defies certain of its
basic assumptions. In other words, these different intellectual
traditions have been reinterpreted from a functionalist perspec-
tive.
This process of fusion and incorporation is reflected in the
position which the resulting theory occupies on the two analytical
dimensions of the paradigm. The German idealist tradition has
influenced the emergence of functionalist theories of a more sub-
jectivist orientation. The Marxist tradition is reflected in func-
tionalist theories which focus upon conflict and change. The dif-
ferences thus generated account in large measure for the ongoing
debate within the paradigm between rival schools of thought, and
also for the nature of the issues discussed. Thus integrative theor-
ists criticise structural functionalists and systems theorists on the
grounds that the latter cannot handle the problems of conflict,
change and deviancy. The interactionists criticise them for being
too orientated towards structural considerations and for ignoring
the emergent nature of social organisation. Process versus struc-
ture, voluntarism versus determinism, become the issues for
debate here. We end this chapter by emphasising the limited nature
of this debate. Conducted within the paradigm, it reflects little
more than a disagreement about the variations which characterise
a commonly accepted theme.
Functionalist Sociology 109
Notes and References
I. Our review of the intellectual foundations of the functionalist
perspective has been necessarily terse. Readers interested in
more extensive analyses of Comte, Spencer and Durkheim
and the relationships between them might usefully consult
Parsons (1949), Aron (1965), Gouldner (1970), Lukes (1973)
and Keat and Urry(l97.5). For a general discussion of Pareto,
see Parsons (1949), Homans and Curtis (1934) and Russett
(1966), pp. 8.5-101.
2. For a discussion of the emergence of functionalism in social
anthropology, see Jarvie (1964). The concept of functional-
ism in psychology predates its appearance in anthropology-
see, for example, James (1890) and Angell (1902). Psychol-
ogy at this time was, of course, primarily physiological in
orientation.
3. For a clear exposition of his views, see Radcliffe-Brown
(19.52). especially his article ‘On the Concept of Function in
Social Science’, pp. 178-87.
4. For a further discussion of these issues, see, for example,
Jarvie (1964) pp. 182-98 and Cohen (1968) pp. 37-4.5 .
.5. The literature on sociology is replete with studies which
focus upon the empirical measurement of ‘social structure’ in
one aspect or another. See, for example, our discussion of
research on organisations in Chapter .5.
6. For two excellent analyses of Parsons’s writings, see Rocher
(1974) and Black (1961).
7. Rocher (1974) presents a very clear analysis of the AGIL
scheme. Our categorisation here draws upon this source.
8. It is never entirely clear in Parsons’s work whether these
functional imperatives exist empirically or whether they are
purely analytic constructs for making society intelligible
from a functionalist standpoint. Although he maintains a
posture of ·analytical realism’, he does not appear to dis-
courage others from engaging in empirical research in rela-
tion to his theoretical scheme. It is from this dualism that
ambiguity regarding his position arises.
9. See, for example, Gouldner ( 1970) and C. Wright Mills
( 19.59). Other writers however, have argued to the contrary.
See, for example, Rocher (1974) and Martins (1974).
10. Parsons’s own version of structural functionalism builds
largely upon the work of Durkheim and Pareto, and on
Weber’s notion of the action frame of reference. It fuses the
110 Sodolof(ica/ Paradif(ms and Orf(anisational Ana/y.tis
biological approach of Durkheim with the mechanical
equilibrium approach of Pareto. In this his scheme is some-
what inconsistent. The Social System contains no reference
to Radcliffe-Brown, and it is clear that Parsons differs quite
considerably in the way in which he uses the concept of
structure and function .In his later work Parsons prefers to be
identified with systems theory rather than structural func-
tionalism as such.
11. A common approach is to take the concept of ‘system’ as
self-evident and confine discussion to the difference between
‘closed’ and ·open’ systems.
12. Buckley ( 1967) adds to this definition: ‘That a system is open
means not simply that it engages in interchanges with the
environment, but that this interchange is an essential factor
underlying the system’s viability, its reproductive ability or
continuity, and its ability to change’ (p. 50).
13. For an excellent and detailed analysis of this field, see Buck-
ley (1967).
14. For a discussion of Henderson and his influence, see, for
example, Russett (1966), pp. 111-24.
15. For a discussion of these concepts, see Katz and Kahn
(1966), pp. 19-26.
16. In point of fact. Parsons’ model fuses the mechanical and
organismic analogies.
17. For a clear discussion of the principles of cybernetics, see
Wisdom (1956) and Dechert (1965).
18. For a clear and comprehensive discussion of some of the
major aspects ofSimmel’s work, see Coser (1965) and Wolff
(1950).
19. A detailed presentation of his views on conflict can be found
in Simmel (1955).
20. As will be apparent from our discussion in Chapter 2, Sim-
mel, particularly through the work of Coser ( 1956), has pro-
vided the main platform for sociologists to argue that the
order-conflict debate is dead.
21. A short time before his death Simmel wrote: ‘I know that I
shall die without intellectual heirs – and that is as it should
be. My legacy will be. as it were, in cash. distributed to many
heirs, each transforming his part into use conformed to his
nature: a use which will reveal no longer its indebtness to this
heritage’ (Georg Simmel, 1919, p. 121). As Coser notes (1%5,
p. 24), this is indeed what happened. No clear-cut school of
thought has emerged around Simmel’s work, and his influ-
Functionali.ft Socio/OflY Ill
ence is not always specifically recognised. Yet his impact has
been important and diverse, particularly through the work of
Coser (1956), Merton (1949), Blau (1964), the work of the
Chicago School of sociologists and the ‘formal sociology’ of
von Wiese at Cologne.
22. See, for example, Natanson (J973a, band c). If Mind, Self
and Society is interpreted within the context of Mead’s other
work, the term ·social behaviourist’ becomes increasingly
inappropriate as a means of describing his overall position.
Mead takes the behaviourism of Watson as a starting point
for his analysis, but from the outset recognises the necessity
for a much wider approach.
23. For a discussion of pragmatism, see ‘The Philosophies of
Royce, James and Dewey in their American Setting’ ,Inter-
national Journal of Ethic.f, XL ( 1930); its historical genesis is
discussed in Mead’s Movements of Thought in the
Nineteenth Century ( 1932).
24. In Mind, Self and Society Mead traces the process by which
biological considerations forced psychology through the
stages of associationism, parallelism, functionalism and
behaviourism, and, against this background, introduces
essentially ·social’ concepts (for example, the notion of the
gesture derived from Wundt) to formulate his own distinctive
position. As noted above, his ‘social behaviourism’ can only
be regarded as a behaviourism in the very widest of senses.
25. Early in his intellectual development, Mead became
interested in Hegelian idealism, largely through the influence
of Royce. Indeed, there are indications that at one time (circa
1887 -8) Mead was more attracted to idealism than to prag-
matism (see, for example, Miller, 1973, p. xiv). It is also
likely that he was influenced by other aspects of German
idealism, in the same manner as Simmel, during a period of
study at Leipzig and Berlin (1888-91).
26. In Morris·s words, ‘instead of beginning with individual
minds and working out to society, Mead starts with an objec-
tive social process and works inward through the importation
ofthe social process of communication into the individual by
the medium of the vocal gesture’ (Mead, 1934, p. xxii).
27. In this Mead, along with Dewey and the ideas expressed in
the latter’s paper of 1896, ‘The Reflex Arc Concept in
Psychology’, stressed the correlation between stimulation
and response.
112 Sociolopical Paradipms and Organisational Analysis
Aspects of the world become parts of the psychological envi-
ronment. become stimuli, only in so far as they effect the further
release of an ongoing impulse. Thus. the sensitivity and activity
of the organism determine its effective environment as genuinely
as the physical environment affects the sensitivity of the form.
The resulting view does more justice to the dynamic and agres-
sive aspects of behaviour than does Watsonism, which gives the
impression of regarding the organism as a puppet, whose wires
are pulled by the physical environment. (Mead, 1934, pp.
xvii- xviii)
28. Their interactionist perspective served different purposes.
For Mead, the study of human interaction provided a key to
understanding the genesis of ‘self. For Simmel, it was more
of an end in itself – reflecting the underlying ‘form’ and
characteristics of human association.
29. See, for example, our discussion of symbolic interactionism
later in this chapter.
30. The account which we have presented of Mead’s work in the
preceeding pages draws heavily upon Mind, Self and Society
and largely relates to point (a) above. Points (b) and (c) are
reflected more clearly in The Philosophy of the Act, and The
Philosophy of the Present. An analysis of the thought con-
tained in the latter two works is beyond the scope of the
present enquiry (the reader is referred to Natanson ‘s ( 1973c)
extremely comprehensive discussion). Since the
phenomenological aspects and interpretations of Mead’s
work have largely been neglected, it is significant that Natan-
son’s excellent analysis from this point of view has only
recently been republished in the wake of the 1960s’
enthusiasm for phenomenological ideas. In the present work
we shall confine discussion of Mead’s ‘phenomenology’ to
the impact it has had upon symbolic interactionism, particu-
larly through the work of Herbert Blumer.
31. For a discussion of the background and dynamics of ‘Chicago
sociology’ during the period 1920-32, see Faris (1967).
32. Simmers ideas had an important impact upon ‘Chicago
sociology’ through Robert Park. who was arguably the lead-
ing figure at Chicago during the 1920s. Park, like other
Chicago scholars such as Mead, studied in Germany and was
directly influenced by Simmers ideas. In their famous intro-
duction to the Science of Sociology ( 1921) Park and Burgess
present a view of sociology which Faris has described as
geared to ‘the pursuit of objective scientific knowledge con-
Functionalist Sociology 113
ceming the nature of society and social organisation, groups,
and institutions. the nature and effects of processes of social
interaction, and the effects of these forms and processes on
the behaviour of persons • (Faris, 1967. p. 41). This approach
to sociology has a distinctly Simmelian flavour.lnterestingly
though, Park’s teachings in the 1920s paid little attention to
the work of Mead (Strauss, 1964. p. xi).
Although interactionist thought is sometimes presented as
having developed independently at Chicago and in Germany,
a strong claim can be made that the two schools of thought
derive from a common Germanic source.
33. Simmel and Mead have also had an influence upon the
development of the integrative theories relating to social
exchange, social control and conflict functionalism which
will be discussed in a later section of this chapter. These
theories build upon interactionist concepts.
34. Although Blumer is generally recognised as interpreting
Mead’s thought from a more phenomenological perspective
than many other theorists, there would probably be little
dispute over the essentials of symbolic interactionism as
described in this quotation.
35. The variety of thought can be clearly seen by consulting one
of the popular readers on symbolic interaction; see. for exam-
ple. Rose ( 1962), and Manis and Meltzer( 1967). For a review
of the trends in symbolic interactionism theory in the
twenty-five years from 1937-62. see the article by Manford
H. Kuhn in Manis and Meltzer (1967), pp. 46-7.
36. The development of role theory owes much to the Chicago
School of sociologists, including Mead, and also, though this
is rarely recognised, to Simmel. For a discussion of role
theory and concepts such as role taking, role sets, role con-
flicts, see, for example, Grosset a/. (1958) and Newcomb
( 1950 and 1953).
37. The notion ofreferencegroups owes much to Mead’s notion
of ‘the generalised other’. and has been most systematically
developed by Merton in the classic articles ‘Contributions to
the Theory of Reference Group Behaviour’ and ‘Continuities
in the Theory of Reference Groups and Social Structure’ in
Merton ( 1968). This work also draws very heavily upon S. A.
Stouffer’s The American Soldier ( 1949), particularly the con-
cept of ·relative deprivation’. and Simmel’s concept of the
‘completeness’ of a group (Merton, 1968, pp. 242-6).
For a further selection of writings on reference group
114 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
analysis, see the articles in Rose ( 1962), Manis and Meltzer
(1967) and Hyman and Singer (1968).
38. Self theory in symbolic interaction (not to be confused with
the psychological theory of Carl Rogers) embraces a wide
range of research directed at analysis and application of this
aspect of Mead’s work. As Manis and Meltzer (1967) point
out, it includes those who see ·self’ as a dynamic process of
viewing and responding to one’s own behaviour; those who
see ‘self’ as a structure of internalised roles; and those who
conceive ·self’ as a set of attitudes or evaluations (p. 215).
For a selection of articles reflecting these points of view,
see Manis and Meltzer (1967). pp. 215-366.
39. Dramaturgical theory, closely related to self theory, is most
often associated with the work of Erving GotTman and his
studies of the active self in social situations. His perspective
presents the individual as an actor shaping his social situation
through the images which he presents. See, for example.
GotTman (1959, 1961, 1963 and 1967).
40. In addition to these general assumptions and propositions,
Rose goes on to specify four further assumptions in relation
to the process of socialisation of the individual child (Rose,
1962, pp. 13-18).
41. Indeed, it could be argued that in his attempt to meet the
structural functionalists on their own ground. Blumer is
drawn into a position which to an extent goes against his view
of ontology quoted earlier (Rose, 1962, p. 182). For example.
towards the end of his article he places much more emphasis
upon action ‘with regard to a situation • (p. 187) and the fact
that ‘human society is the framework inside of which social
action takes place’ (p. 189).
42. In his 1966 article Blumer presents symbolic interactionism
as an approach which is capable of covering ‘the full range of
the generic forms of human association. It embraces equally
well such relationships as co-operation. conflict, domina-
tion. exploitation, consensus. disagreement, closely knit
identification, and indifferent concern for one another. The
participants in each of such relations have the same common
task of constructing their acts by interpreting and defining the
acts of each other’ (Blumer, 1966, p. 538). He goes on to
criticise those theorists who tend to impose a particular
frame of reference on the nature of interaction: ‘Their great
danger lies in imposing on the breadth of human interaction
an image derived from the study of only one form of interac-
Functionalist Socio/ofu 115
tion. Thus, in different hands. human society is said to be
fundamentally a sharing of common values; or. conversely. a
struggle for power; or. still differently. the exercise of con-
sensus and so on’ (Blumer, 1966, p. 538).
Blumer is thus. in essence. advocating symbolic interac-
tionism as an approach capable of occupying a wide range of
positions in relation to the vertical dimension of our analyti-
cal scheme. Theoretically, it can be conceptualised as rang-
ing along the whole of the vertical dimension within the
context of the sociology of regulation.
43. For an analysis of the distinctions between these two ver-
sions, see, for example. Meltzer and Petras (1973), and
Meltzer eta/. (1975).
44. As Reynolds and Meltzer ( 1973) have put it. the Chicago
interactionists ‘tend to prefer phenomenological approaches,
participant observation and “sensitising concepts”. all
linked with a logic of discovery’. This is in contrast with the
Iowa researchers who ‘have preferred operational
approaches. The Twenty Statements Test and “definitive
concepts”. all linked with a “logic of verification”‘.
45. For a clear and articulate discussion of some of the issues
involved here, see Williams (1976).
46. Cohen ( 1968). p. 69. This statement of the assumptions of the
theory of action draws upon the work of von Mises and
Parsons. as well as that of Weber. It provides a good illustra-
tion of the way in which Weber’s ideas are adapted to suit the
purposes of individual authors. Cohen provides a good
description and critique of action theory in general. and
rightly emphasises that it should be regarded as a method
rather than a theory as such (Cohen, 1968. pp. 70-94).
47. See, for example, the analysis of Parsons’s epistemological
and other movements presented in Scott ( 1963).
48. On the other hand, the strength of Weber’s work (as opposed
to that of the interactionist tradition) lay in its conscious
attempt to link the concept of social action to wider aspects of
social structure. particularly through the notion of ‘legitimate
order’. Given the priorities of the functionalist paradigm, this
is indeed a strength of Weber’s work; social action, with its
emphasis on the individual’s interpretation of the situation, is
always related to the wider context of that action.
49. Blau’s version of exchange theory is often linked to that of
Homans (1958 and 1961). Whilst the work of these two
writers has developed through a process of mutual influence,
116 Sociological Pamdi,::ms and Organisational Analy.fis
they are, in fact, quite different and occupy conceptually
distinct locations within the functionalist paradigm.
SO. Blau’s notion of ‘social exchange’ is restricted to behaviour
orientated towards ends that can only be achieved through
interaction with other persons and which seeks to adapt
means to achieve those ends. It thus represents action which
is purposive and calculative. It is wider than the notion of
economic exchange because of the unspecified obligations
incurred within it and the trust both required for and pro-
moted by it. It excludes behaviour based on the ‘irrational
push’ of emotional forces, that based on coercion and that
orientated towards ultimate values and issues of conscience
rather than towards immediate rewards (Biau, 1964, pp.
4-8).
51. The conceptualisation of power found in Blau is very similar
to that of Emerson (1962). Emerson stresses the need to see
power as a relationship, as the propeny of interaction rather
than as the attribute of individuals or of groups.
52. See, for example, the interpretations of Gouldner ( 1970),
Horton (1964) and Strasser (1976).
53. The concept of ‘normative function’ in relation t.o reference
groups builds upon another Meadian idea- that of the social-
ised ‘self – and converts it into an instrument for explaining
social control. Mead was interested in ‘self as a process. As
Strauss notes, in the theory of reference groups (and also in
Parsonian functionalism) the notion is used in a very
restricted way, largely for the purposes of explaining how
norms get internalised and how self-control is, in essence, a
reflection of social control (Strauss, 1964, p. xii).
54. Applying Veblen’s concept of ‘trained incapacity’, Merton
argues that bureaucrats may develop blind spots – abilities
function as inadequacies. He suggests that bureaucratic per-
sonnel may overconform to the normative structure of the
enterprise which emphasises strict devotion to regulations.
This process stifles initiative and, under changed conditions,
produces inappropriate responses and impairs the efficient
performance of organisational tasks.
55. See, for example, the argument put forward by van den
Berghe suggesting that the basic postulates of functionalism
and the Hegelian- Marxian dialectic are capable of synthesis
(van den Berghe, 1963).
56. Merton defines ‘manifest functions’ as ‘those objective con-
sequences contributing to the adjustment or adaption of the
FunctionaliJt Sociolo~y 117
system which are intended and recognised by participants in
the system. •Latent functions’ are •those which are neither
intended nor recognised’ (Merton. 1968, p. 105). The distinc-
tion is introduced to differentiate and avoid confusion ‘be-
tween conscious motivation.<; for social behaviour and its
objecth·e con.tequence.<;' (Merton, 1968, p. 114).
51. See, for example, Gouldner (1973 and 1976).
58. The term ·socio-cultural' is used by Buckley •to make
explicit the difference between the human level of organisa-
tion and the lower, merely .. social" ,level of certain animal
or insect species' (Buckley. 1967, p. 1). As Buckley argues in
dealing with socio-cultural systems, one is not only con-
cerned with the issue of structure maintenance, as in biologi-
cal systems, but also with the structure-elaborating and
structure-changing feature of the inherently unstable system,
i.e. morphogenesis (Buckley. 1967, pp. 14-15, 58-62).
59. See, for example, Skinner (1953, 1957 and 1952).
60. See, for example, some of the work presented in Cartwright
and Zander ( 1968) and Landy and Trumbo ( 1976), pp.
293-335.
61. Mills uses the term to castigate those researchers who, along
with ·grand' theorists, have abandoned what he sees as being
the central task of sociology, that of grasping •history and
biography and the relations between the two within soci-
ety, .. To recognise this task and this promise is the mark of
the classic social analyst ... No social study that does not
come back to the problems of biography, of history and of
their intersections within a society. has completed its intel-
lectual journey' (Mills, 1959, p. 12). On the basis of this
criterion, the work of most theorists who engage in empirical
work would be categorised as abstracted empiricism. Our
definition is more limited, in that it relates to empirical work
which is abstracted from its theoretical context.
5. Functionalist Organisation
Theory
In recent years the study of organisations has established itself as
an increasingly significant area of social-scientific investigation.ln
terms of the number of research studies conducted, the volume of
literature produced and its establishment as a recognised field of
study within academic institutions,the study of organisations has a
good claim to being regarded as a distinct branch of social science
of some importance.
Yet in many respects it is a confusing field. It is usually pre-
sented as comprising of at least three lines of development, each
drawing upon a number of different intellectual traditions. First,
there is what may be described as organisation theory, which
addresses itself to the study of 'formal organisations' and builds
upon the work of the so-called 'classical school' of management
and administrative theory. As Salaman and Thompson have noted,
this is often seen as the ·orthodox approach' to the study of
organisations and 'tends to adopt theories and models of organisa-
tional functioning, and to focus on areas of empirical investigation,
that are highly oriented towards managerial conceptions of organ-
isations, managerial priorities and problems. and managerial con-
cerns for practical outcomes· (Salaman and Thompson, 1973, p. I).
The foundations of classical theory were largely laid by practising
managers with little or no social science background. Second,
there is the approach which is sometimes described as the sociol-
ogy of organisations. For the most part this builds upon the founda-
tions laid by Max Weber, and it approaches the study of organisa-
tions from a sociological as opposed to a managerial perspective.
Third, there is the approach which is essentially concerned with
the study of the behaviour of individuals within organisations. This
builds upon the work of the human relations movement and for the
most part approaches the subject from a psychological standpoint,
though a significant number of industrial sociologists have also
contributed to work conducted from this point of view.
These three lines of development thus draw upon a variety of
perspectives and academic disciplines. In the course of their
development they have often had a significant influence upon each
Functionalist Organisation Theory J 19
other, and it is not uncommon for them to be fused and described
under the guise of a multi-disciplinary approach to the study of
•organisational behaviour'. Many theorists shy away from this
fusion, recognising that the different theories are not always com-
patible and that the term ·organisational behaviour' reflects a
reification of the subject of study. However, the term is often used
to denote interest in a whole range of organisation studies, embrac-
ing theories of organisation, theories of the individual in the work
situation and the way in which both relate to the wider social
environment.
In this chapter we intend to examine a wide range of these
theories, particularly with regard to the assumptions on which they
are based. As we have noted earlier, all theories of organisation are
founded upon a philosophy of science and a theory of society,
whether the theorists are aware of it or not. To many this may
appear an unduly banal and simplistic statement. However, within
the context of an analysis of the field of organisation studies it
seems more than justified. Many theorists appear to be unaware
of, or at least ignore, the assumptions which various theories
reflect.
This is particularly evident, for example, in the way in which
reviewers of the field are normally content to rely upon simple
linear explanations of the historical development of the subject as a
means of presenting the current state of the art. It is also reflected
in the host of rival typologies which attempt to classify the subject
area. Both are symptomatic of a reluctance to penetrate to the
foundations of the discipline. The typical analysis of the historical
development of the subject, for example, usually traces how clas-
sical management theory, Weber's theory of bureaucracy and
human relations theory existed side by side until synthesised in
terms of open systems theory during the 1950s, and how subse-
quent research has sought to explore the ramifications of the
systems approach at an empirical level. Theorists who choose
typologies as a means of organising the subject area vary quite
considerably in approach. Pugh ( 1966), for example, identifies six
approaches: management theory, structural theory, group theory,
individual theory, technology theory and economic theory. Whyte
(1969) identifies seven schools of thought and activity: event-
process analysts, structuralists, organisational surveyors, group
dynamicists, decision making theorists, psychiatric analysts and
technological structuralists. Eldridge and Crombie (1974), in a
review of the typologies which have been used by various organ-
isation theorists, differentiate between typologies based on
120 Sodologictll Paradigms and Organisational Anc1ly.o;is
functions (for example, Katz and Kahn, Tavistock, Blau and
Scott), technology (for example, Woodward. Blauner, Thomp-
son), regulation (Etzioni) and structure (for example, Ackoff,
Vickers). As many of the authors who engage in the construction
of such typologies readily recognise, the classifications thus pro-
duced are rough and ready and have many imperfections. They
tend to emphasise certain aspects of the work under review whilst
ignoring others. Again. it is not uncommon to find that a particular
theory can be legitimately classified under more than one of the
typologies produced.
It is our view that although they are helpful in identifying some of
the detailed differences between various approaches to the study
of organisations, both the simple linear historical description and
the construction of descriptive typologies are inherently limiting in
perspective unless they seek to e:cplore the basic theoretical
assumptions of the work which they purport to. describe. Unless
they do this, such analyses can be positively misleading, in that in
emphasising differences between theories, they imply a diversity
in approach. Insofar as these differences are identified in terms of
superticial characteristics rather than fundamental assumptions,
the diversity is more apparent than real. As w.ill become clear from
the discussion conducted in the rest of this work, we believe this to
be the case in the field of organisation studies. Whilst superficially
there appears to be a dazzling array of different kinds of theory and
research, in point of fact the subject tends to be very narrowly
founded indeed. This becomes evident when the theories which
comprise the field are related to the wider background of social
theory as a whole. As will become apparent, most are located
within the context of what we have called the functionalist para-
digm. The other social science paradigms remain almost com-
pletely unexplored as far as theories of organisation are con-
cerned. Moreover, within the context of the functionalist para-
digm, the majority of existing theories tend to be located within a
relatively narrow range of academic territory. Despite the appar-
ent diversity reflected in current debate, the issues which separate
the parties in academic controversy often tend to be of minor
rather than of major significance. The really big issues are rarely
discussed, lying hidden beneath the commonality of perspective
which induces organisation theorists to get together and talk with
each other in the first place.
Functionalist Organisation Theory 121
Theories of Organisation within the
Functionalist Paradigm
Figure 5.1 presents a very rough overview of the location of
contemporary theories of organisation within the context of the
functionalist paradigm. It identifies four principal theoretical
perspectives.
Act ion
f rame
of
reference
Plural ism
Theories
o f
bureaucratic
dysfunct ions
Social
system
theory
Object ivism
Figure .5.1 Functionalist approaches to the study of organisations
1. Social system theory and objectivism
This perspective, which characterises the most objectivist region
of the paradigm, is of overwhelming significance as far as con-
temporary theories of organisation are concerned. The vast major-
ity of writers on organisational issues adopt a perspective located
here. It corresponds with the categories of social theory identified
in Chapter4 as social system theory and objectivism. In the field of
organisation studies there has been a continuous interaction be-
tween these two categories of theory. since the conceptual distinc-
122 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
lions between them have not often been recognised. We will
attempt to follow some of these interactions and show how various
theories have evolved. The overall perspective broadly corres-
ponds to what Silverman (1970) has described as the •systems
orthodoxy', though, as we shall argue, it is positively misleading to
view many of the theories located within it as systems theories in
anything but name. It embraces a small amount of genuine social
system theory and a larger element of behaviourism, but it is
dominated by abstracted empiricism.
2. The action frame of reference
This perspective, which occupies the subjective boundary of the
paradigm, is considerably less developed. Deriving principally
from the work of Weber. it has received its clearest expression and
formulation in the work of Silverman (1970). Contrary to Silver-
man's view, we do not see it as constituting an alternative para-
digm for the study of organisations. We see it as an alternative
perspective which remain~ essentially within the context of the
functionalist paradigm. It is a perspective which, in terms of the
analysis contained in Chapter4, is akin to symbolic interactionism
and social action theory.
3. Theories of bureaucratic dysfunctions
This perspective builds upon the category of integrative theory
described in Chapter 4 as Mertonian theory of social and cultural
structure. It embraces a relatively small number oftheorists, who
have specifically developed Merton's work and have carried the
perspective to a position approaching that of conflict functional-
ism.
4. Pluralist theory
This is another category of integrative theory akin to the ·conflict
functionalism' discussed in Chapter 4. Theorists have arrived at
this perspective by different routes. In terms of numbers they are
Functionalist Organisation Theory 123
relatively few, but the perspective is of growing importance within
the subject area as a whole.
The rest of this chapter is devoted to a systematic analysis of
theories of organisation agaiust the theoretical background defined
by the functionalist paradigm as discussed in Chapter 4. We
attempt to penetrate beyond simple historical and typological
analysis to the essential theoretical foundations which underlie
contemporary work in the subject.
Social System Theory and Objectivism
The dominant perspective within the field of organisation studies is
characterised by a close and interactive relationship between
social system theory and objectivism. In the rest of this section we
intend to sketch the relationships between some of its prominent
landmarks. In order to provide an overview, albeit in rough and
ready terms, Figure 5.2 illustrates the general course of develop-
ment.
Our plan for negotiating this complex field of theory and
research is as follows. We take our starting point from the work of
the classical management theorists and the industrial psycholog-
ists who were the fore-runners of the human relations movement.
We argue that, despite the detailed differences in the theories
which they expounded, both occupied a similar position hard
against the most objectivist boundary of the functionalist para-
digm. The perspective of both sets of theorists reflected a raw
determinism, in which objective factors in the work environment
were treated as of paramount importance to the analysis and
explanation of behaviour in organisations. As we have attempted
to illustrate in Figure 5.2, both approaches are alive and well
today. They have flourished throughout the period and are most
evident in the work of ergonomists, work study theorists and the
management theorists who continue to prescribe rules of organisa-
tion.
We move from these early examples of objectivism to a consid-
eration of the social system theory reflected in The Hawthorne
Studies. We argue that the theoretical model which emerged from
this work was, for its time, quite sophisticated, though the insights
it offered were largely lost in the ensuing debate which tended to
focus upon the empirical results of the study. As a result, post-
Hawthorne research on work behaviour usually reverted to the
objectivism of earlier years. We devote our next section to a
I i 0 > c 0 “‘ ~ :1 ~ en > en ~ c u i :1 !a ~ iJ 0 1
10
0
11
10
1
9
2
0
–
1
9
3
0
19
40
19
50
19
60
1
9
7
0
–
–
–
–
1
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I E
ar
ly
i
nd
us
tr
ia
l p
sy
ch
ol
og
y
1
-‘
Y
-·
·-
··
··
—
r
–
1
~
o
s
t
·
H
a
w
t
h
o
r
n
e
o
bj
ec
tiv
is
m
:
hu
m
an
r
el
at
io
ns
r
es
ea
rc
h
on
j
ob
s
at
is
fa
ct
io
n,
g
ro
up
d
yn
am
ic
s,
l
ea
de
rs
hi
p,
e
tc
.
S
oc
io
·
Jo
b
de
si
gn
t
he
or
y
~
d
~
:
·
r
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
te
ch
ni
ca
l
sy
st
em
s
th
eo
ry
Q
ua
lit
y
of
w
or
ki
ng
l
ife
E
qu
ili
br
iu
m
th
eo
rie
s
o
f
D
ec
is
io
n
m
ak
in
gJ
m
od
el
s
m
ov
em
en
t
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
n
O
rg
an
is
at
io
ns
as
o
pe
n
S
tr
uc
tu
ra
l
sy
st
em
s
fu
nc
tio
na
lis
t
C
on
tin
ge
nc
y
ap
pr
oa
ch
es
t
o
th
eo
ry
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
n
E
m
pi
ric
al
s
tu
di
es
o
f
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
na
l
ch
ar
ac
te
ris
tic
s
I
S
ci
en
tif
ic
m
an
ag
em
en
t
an
d
l
W
o
rk
s
tu
dy
,
0
an
d
M
.
an
d
m
an
ag
em
en
t
th
eo
ry
cl
as
si
ca
l m
an
ag
em
en
t
th
eo
ry
_
_
I
Fi
gu
re
.5
.2
T
he
d
ev
el
op
m
en
t
of
s
oc
ia
l
sy
st
em
t
he
or
y
an
d
ob
je
cl
iv
is
m
Functionali.’it Organi.wtion Theory 12S
consideration of this post-Hawthorne objectivism which has
dominated the human relations movement and research on job
satisfaction, group dynamics, leadership and managerial styles,
etc., right up to the present day. This is followed by a short section
on socio-technical systems theory, which in essence represents a
direct development of the theoretical insights generated in the
Hawthorne research, and which has had such a major influence
upon the theory of job design.
A consideration of socio-technical systems theory leads natur-
ally to an examination of the open systems approach to the study of
organisations. In order to provide an adequate account of this,
however, it is necessary to return to the Hawthorne studies and
trace another line of development, which begins with Barnard’s
theory of organisation. Barnard’s work represented one of the first
attempts at developing a comprehensive model of an organisation.
All the other research which we have just mentioned focuses
attention upon behaviour within organisations and is concerned
with the individual, social group and work environment. Barnard’s
work represented a clear move towards an organisational level of
analysis. Later in this chapter we consider Barnard’s theory, along
with the work of Herbert Simon, as equilibrium theories of organ-
isation.
Barnard’s theory, heavily influenced by the Hawthorne
resear~h. tended to emphasise social aspects of organisation. He
was concerned, first and foremost, to see the organisation as a
social enterprise. This tendency was modified by subsequent
theorists such as Philip Selznick and Herbert Simon who, influ-
enced by Weber and some of the classical theorists, gave the
rational/legal or bureaucratic aspects of organisation greater
prominence. Simon did so within the context of an equilibrium
model embracing rational and social factors. Selznick did so within
the context of a structural functionalist approach to organisation.
Developing certain principles derived from the use of an
organismic analogy, structural functionalism has had an important
influence upon organisation theory. Our next section. therefore, is
devoted to a consideration of Selznick’s early work as an example
of the structural functionalist approach to organisation.
Having considered these foundations for a theory of organisa-
tions, we will then be in a position to link up with our previous
discussion of socio-technical systems theory, and we devote a
section to a consideration of some of the theories which emerged in
the 1960s treating organisations as open systems. These models
incorporate the insights of earlier approaches and tend to place
126 ScJcicJ/ogical Paradigm.<; and Organisational Analysis
primary emphasis upon the relationship between organisation and
environment.
In the following section we consider some empirical studies of
organisational characteristics which reflect a movement away
from social system theory and towards objectivism. These studies,
along with the open systems models of the 1960s. paved the way
for a major synthesis in terms of contingency theory. This
approach, which has dominated organisation theory during the
1970s, is the subject of our penultimate section.
We conclude our analysis with a discussion of the quality of
working life movement. This too has come into prominence in the
1970s and in essence fuses the perspectives of job design theorists
with those deriving from open systems theory. Drawing upon the
notion of post-industrialism, it links the traditional concerns of the
human relations movement and socio-technical systems theory
with changes taking place within the context of contemporary
society as a whole.
Classical management theory and industrial
psychology
F. W. Taylor ( 1856-191 S), the founder of 'scientific management'
was very much a man of practical affairs. A chief engineer of a
large steel works who had worked his way up from the position of
ordinary labourer on the shop floor. he was interested in manager-
ial action and its immediate measurable results. We learn that he
developed the work study techniques for which he has become so
famous as a result of problems experienced as a gang boss seeking
to increase output by putting pressure on the men. A serious
struggle ensued which Taylor finally won but at the expense of
considerable soul-searching. He gave the matter thought and
decided that the primary cause of such conflict was that manage-
ment, without knowing what constituted a proper day's work,
tried to secure output by pressure. He felt that if management
knew what work was possible, they could then ascertain output by
demonstration. He decided to experiment to discover what was a
proper day's work for every operation in the steel shop (Taylor,
1947).
Taylor continued his experiments throughout his career in the
steel industry and later as a consultant, communicating his findings
to other managers through meetings of the American Society m
Mechanical Engineers, for example, and through the publication
Functionalist Organisation Theory 127
of papers such as 'Shop Management· ( 1903) and 'The Principles of
Scientific Management' (1911) (see Taylor, 1947). These works
bristle with a meticulous concern for the detailed analysis of
everyday work activities, such as the process of earth shovelling,
pig-iron handling, etc. Taylor realised that by matching men, tools
and the tasks they were required to perform, it was possible to
increase productivity without placing increased physical burdens
upon the men. He sought to convert the process of management
from an art form based upon experience and rule of thumb to •a
true science, resting upon clearly defined laws, rules, and princi-
ples, as a foundation' (Taylor, 1947, p. 7).
Most of Taylor's work was conducted in relation to shop floor
management. Whilst recognising that the scientific approach could
be applied to all kinds of human activities, even 'the work of our
great corporations, which call for the most elaborate co-
operation', Taylor did not pursue the latter to any real extent. This
was left to other members of the so-called classical school of
administrative and management theory, many of whom found
great inspiration in Taylor's work.
Henri Fayol (1841-1925) was a French mining engineer who
rose to the top of the managerial hierarchy. After thirty years as
managing director of a group of coal mines he turned his attention
to popularising his 'theory of administration' which articulated
various principles relating to the task of general management
(Fayol, 1949). Whereas Taylor had concentrated on work con-
ducted on the shop floor, Fayol concentrated upon the problems of
work at a managerial level. Planning, organisation, command,
co-ordination and control were the focus of his interest; he defined
various principles which could be taught to managers. He saw the
need for a theory of management.
Subsequent members of the "classical school' for the most part
built upon the foundations laid by Taylor and Fayol. Gulick, Mary
Parker Follett, Mooney, Urwick and others concerned themselves
with formulating and popularising principles of management.
Their work related broadly to what would now be regarded as
problems of organisation structure, leadership style and effi-
ciency, and constituted a guide to managerial action rather than a
theory of organisation in any formal sense.
The theories of Taylor, Fayol and the classical management
school as a whole are founded upon assumptions which charac-
terise the most objectivist region of the functionalist paradigm.
The world of organisations is treated as if it were the world of
natural phenomena, characterised by a hard concrete reality which
128 Socioloxical Paradixm.f and Orxanisational Analysis
can be systematically investigated in a way which reveals its
underlying regularities. Above all else it is a world of cause and
effect: the task of the management theorist is seen as the identifica-
tion of the fundamental laws which characterise its day-to-day
operation. Given this overall view, the individual is assigned an
essentially passive and responding role; the individual and his
behaviour at work is seen as being determined by the situation to
which he is exposed. From this, the golden rule of scientific man-
agement emerges: 'Get the situation right, and the appropriate
human behaviour and organisational performance will follow' .•
By the beginning of World War I another movement which was
to have a considerable impact upon theories of behaviour in organ-
isations was well under way in the USA, Britain and certain other
European countries. Unlike scientific management, however,
which was the subject of controversy from its earliest days, 2 the
industrial psychology movement adopted a lower profile. For the
most part it was a consultancy-orientated concern, supplying
advice to industrial managers on problems associated with indus-
trial fatigue, employee selection, individual differences and the
like. 1 As such, most of the work conducted was practice- rather
than research-orientated and its results often confidential. As an
academic discipline, therefore, its development was severely con-
strained until after 1915, when as part of the war effort in Britain,
the Health of Munitions Workers Committee was established. The
Committee and its successor, the Industrial Fatigue Research
Board (established in 1918), did much to sponsor research into
problems offatigue and health at work, with a view to contributing
to the general efficiency of industry. The results of the research
studies conducted were published on a systematic basis and did
much to launch industrial psychology as a field of enquiry. The
research papers stimulated discussion of the psychological prob-
lems of industry and further research, particularly in the USA.
From its earliest days the industrial psychology movement was
at pains to emphasise its humanitarian as well as its managerial
interests. In particular it was anxious to disassociate itself from
any connection with Taylor and scientific management, with
which it was often identified by working men. As Lupton has
noted, when the National Institute of Industrial Psychology (a
private foundation supported mainly by industry) was set up in
Britain in 1921, 'there was some suspicion that it was practising
Taylorism under another name, whereupon it was explained that
the work of the NIIP was based upon sound psychology rather
than on a mechanical analogue of the human being.lt sought not to
Functionalist Organiscllion Theory 129
push the worker from behind but to ease his difficulties, and by this
to increase his output and his personal satisfaction' (Lupton, 1971,
p. 30). The industrial psychology movement has adhered to this
standpoint as a guiding principle more or less throughout the sixty
or so years of its history. It has always presented itself as vigor-
ously humanitarian and opposed to Taylorism. Indeed. the attacks
upon Taylor and his system have at times been particularly sca-
thing, as Taylor's notion of 'The One Best Way' and his over-
simplified model of ·economic man' have been subjected to
systematic criticism and sometimes ridicule. 4 In most com-
parisons of scientific management and industrial psychology it is
the differences bet ween the two approaches which tend to be given
prominence, 5 and any casual observer of the debate may well be
forgiven for believing that it is the differences rather than the
similarities between the two approaches which are all-important.
Ho"wever. probing well beneath the surface, one finds many
points of similarity between Taylor's approach and that of the
industrial psychologists. The work of the early psychologists, for
example. was largely directed at establishing the causes offatigue
and monotony at work and their effects upon performance and
efficiency. Among the factors studied one finds the degree of
mechanisation and routineness of work, methods of payment, job
rotation. hours of work, the introduction of rest pauses and the
influence of social groups receiving attention. All these factors
(which, incidentally, are still, fifty years on, receiving much atten-
tion from industrial psychologists) had been the subject of research
by the late 1920s. There can be little doubt that Taylor would have
been interested in the results of these studies and would have
applauded the attempt to bring science to bear upon these prob-
lems, even though it has not been the science of the stop-watch
which was reflected in his predilection for time and motion study.
Taylor himself had, in fact, addressed some of the problems
examined by the psychologists (for example, payment systems,
rest pauses, job design, etc.). The research reported by Elton
Mayo ( 1933) on the problems of telegraphists· cramp, the perfor-
mance of 'spinning mule' workers (who were all provided with
sacking so that they could lie down in comfort by their machines
during rest pauses) and the illumination experiments which pre-
ceded the Hawthorne studies are all reminiscent of Taylor's inter-
est in earth shovelling and pig-iron handling.
The work of the industrial psychologists, like Taylor's, was
based upon the assumption that objective factors in the work
situation have a rJUUOr influence upon behaviour in organisations.
130 Sociologkcll Paradigms and Organisational Anttlysis
This view, as we have indicated earlier. is informed by a highly
objectivist ontology and epistemology. The world of work is
treated as a world of hard concrete reality characterised by
uniformities and regularities which can be understood in terms of
cause and effect. Given these assumptions, the individual is
accorded an essentially passive role; his behaviour is regarded as
being determined by the work environment. The main difference
between Taylorism and the work of the early industrial psychol-
ogists is thus one not so much of principle as of detail. They differ
in the sophistication of their determinism. Within the context of
Taylor's scheme it is crude; man is no more than a machine. Within
the industrial psychologists' scheme man is a more complex
psychological entity; the relationship between his environment
and his behaviour can only be unravelled and understood through
the use of a more complex psychological model.lt is this which lies
at the heart of the difference between Taylorism and traditional
industrial psychology and gives rise to the different conclusions
which they draw from their research. Among the psychologists a
behavioural as opposed to a mechanical analogy is preferred; man
is treated as a sophisticated machine which can only be understood
through detailed analysis of the complex relations of stimulus and
response. As will become clear from subsequent discussion, the
history of industrial psychology largely reflects a sequence of
attempts to plug different models of man into an essentially deter-
ministic theory of work behaviour characteristic of the objectivist
boundary of the functionalist paradigm.
The Hawthorne studies
Over the last twenty-five years or so the Hawthorne studies have
been subjected to an increasing barrage of criticism, to the extent
that in many quarters they are now largely discredited as a piece of
social research. They have been criticised for ignoring the role of
conflict in the work place; for being ideologically biased in favour
of management; for being paternalistic; for adopting an inapprop-
riate view of man and society; for ignoring unions and the role of
collective bargaining; for giving insufficient attention to the role of
factors in the outside environment; for being very unscientific in
their approach to their research; and for misinterpreting the evi-
dence which they collected (Landsberger, 1958; Carey, 1967).
Given these criticisms, almost all of which are valid in varying
degrees, it is often difficult to know precisely what to make of the
Functionalist OrRanisation Theory 131
Hawthorne studies. Most theorists would agree that their signifi-
cance from a historical viewpoint is beyond dispute. Whether right
or wrong, they have drawn the attention of researchers to the role
of social factors within the work place and what has been called the
informal organisation. The Hawthorne studies have had a massive
impact upon subsequent developments in industrial psychology
and sociology, particularly in relation to the so-called human rela-
tions movement. 6
In many respects the Hawthorne research has entered the realm
of mythology. Few students of organisations now read either
Mayo's The Human Problems of an Industrial Civilisation (1933)
or the more comprehensive report Management and the Worker
by Roethlisberger and Dickson ( 1939). They tend to learn about the
Hawthorne studies at second or third hand. The literature is
replete with oversimplified accounts and reports of the Hawthorne
investigations which tend to focus for the most part upon their
practical implications for management. Schein presents a good
illustration of this, concluding that:
what this study brought home to the industrial psychologist was the
importance of the .
–
–
–
–
–
<
l
l
~
C
r
e
a
~
l
o
n
o
f
le
ar
n1
ng
s
ys
te
m
R
ou
tin
e,
I
lo
w
d
i$
cr
et
io
n
C
om
pl
ex
,
/
ro
le
s
hi
gh
d
is
cr
et
io
n
E
.
~
~
. c
on
om
1c
m
an
;
m~
tr
um
~n
ta
l
-'
(A
JI
--
--
~~
..
.;
::
::
.
S
el
f-
ac
tu
al
is
in
g
m
an
·
'
or
.e
nt
at
1o
n
to
w
or
k
a
ce
nt
ra
l
'
w
or
k
lif
e
in
te
re
st
B
ur
ea
uc
ra
tic
8
0
·
~
rg
an
1c
/
A
ut
ho
rit
ar
ia
n
(t
he
or
y
xl
D
em
oc
ra
tic
(t
he
or
y
rl
is
c
on
tin
ge
nt
u
po
n
a
di
ff
er
en
til
lti
on
o
f
th
e
or
ga
ni
sa
tio
n
in
a
cc
or
da
nc
e
w
ith
t
he
d
em
an
ds
o
f
th
e
en
vi
ro
nm
en
t.
ch
ar
ac
te
ris
ed
b
y
co
ng
ru
en
cy
b
et
w
ee
n
su
b-
sy
st
em
e
le
m
en
ts
. a
nd
s
up
pl
em
en
te
d
by
a
n
ap
pr
op
ria
te
p
ro
ce
ss
o
f
in
te
gr
at
io
n.
Th
es
e
co
nd
iti
on
s
ar
e
ex
pr
es
se
d
w
ith
in
t
he
c
on
te
xt
o
f t
he
o
ve
ra
ll
m
od
el
in
t
er
m
s
of
th
e
co
ng
ru
en
cy
h
yp
ot
he
si
s,
a
nd
t
he
in
te
gr
at
io
n
hy
po
th
es
is
.
Fi
gu
re
S
.S
A
co
nt
in
ge
nc
y
m
od
el
f
or
o
rg
an
is
at
io
na
l a
na
ly
si
s
178 Socioloxical Paradixms and Orf(ani.wtional Analysis
ships are incongruent. It is hypothesised. for example. that
an organisation or part of an organisation dealing with a
highly stable and certain environment can operate effectively
when:
(a) the strategic subsystem is geared to operational goal
setting;
(b) the operational subsystem employs a technology which
leads to high specialisation and division of labour in
accordance, for example, with the principles of
scientific management;
(c) employees are content with economic rewards and
have low expectations with regard to work;
(d) the organisation is structured in a bureaucratic fashion;
(e) the organisation is managed in a highly authoritarian
and directive way.
Conversely, it is hypothesised that when an organisation
or an element of an organisation is dealing with a turbulent
and unpredictable environment, the appropriate element of
the organisation needs:
(a) strategic management which fosters the ability of the
organisational unit to learn and respond to the
environment by
(b) adopting an operational system characterised by com-
plex, high-discretion roles, which are
(c) filled by 'organisation men' who see work as their
central life interest and attempt to satisfy higher-level
psychological needs through their work experience,
and
(d) who are managed within the context of an organic form
of organisation structure by
(e) managers who adopt an open and democratic style of
management, and gear their efforts to creating a situa-
tion in which it is possible for the individuals being
managed to satisfy their own personal goals through the
achievement of organisational objectives.
These two hypothesised relationships characterise
extreme positions with regard to modes of organisation and
management, and are illustrated in Figure 5.5 by the broken
lines marked A and B respectively. The contingency model
allows for intermediate positions with regard to the nature of
organisational environments and subsystems. Each
Functionalist Organisation Theory 119
dimension should be regarded as a contiuum rather than a
dichotomy, varying in accordance with the characteristics
discussed under point II above.
The congruency hypothesis applies to all these intermed-
iate positions. maintaining that congruency with the demands
of the environment is an essential characteristic of subsystem
elements if an organisation is to succeed in its primary tasks.
An intermediate stage of congruency is illustrated by the
broken line marked C. Jhe continuous line marked D illus-
trates a position characterised by incongruency; it is
hypothesised that such an organisation would be less
effective than that illustrated by line C. given that they
operate under similar environmental conditions.
13. The adaption of subsystem elements to environmental
demands leads to a differentiation within the organisation
which calls for appropriate boundary management to achieve
an adequate state of integration for the system as a whole.
This integration is one of the ongoing functions of the
managerial and strategic subsystems. As Lawrence and
Lorsch (1967) have argued, integration is as important as
differentiation in influencing an organisation's success in
coping with the demands posed by its environment. Con-
gruency between subsystem elements is thus a necessary
condition for success but not a sufficient one. It needs to be
supplemented by what may be called the integration
hypothesis. This postulates that an organisation, once
differentiated, must achieve an appropriate state of
reintegration if it is to be fully effective.
We have attempted to illustrate this requirement in Figure
5.5 by adding a third dimension to our model of the relation-
ships between organisational environment and subsystems.
This illustrates that various elements of an organisation may
be differentiated in relation to the environment and all ofthe
subsystems. We have chosen to demonstrate this by placing
three departments in locations consistent with supposed
environmental characteristics. 36 The congruency hypothesis
requires that the nature of all subsystems be congruent with
this environmental characteristic, as argued under point 12
above. The integration hypothesis calls for adequate
boundary management to ensure appropriate links between
these different elements of the organisation.
14. Bringing the congruency and integration hypotheses
180 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
together, therefore, the contingency model outlined above
postulates that the success of an organisation in dealing with
the demands made on it by its environment is contingent
upon appropriate differentiation characterised by a con-
gruency between subsystem elements and the achievement
of an appropriate state of integration.
The contingency model outlined above provides a theoretical
framework for analysing organisations from a managerial point of
view, and represents a synthesis of the concepts and ideas implicit
in a great deal of contemporary organisation theory. Much of the
empirical research on organisations conducted during the 1960s
and 1970s has been informed by various elements of the model,
though it is very questionable whether it has been true to the basic
ontological and epistemological foundations upon which the model
is based. We have in mind here the distinction between 'process'
and 'structure' (Cooper, 1976) which we have already referred to
on a number of occasions in this and the previous chapter. The
contingency model, based as it is upon an open systems approach,
is essentially processual in nature. The subsystems are viewed in
terms of functional imperatives which interact with the environ-
ment in a manner geared to achieve the survival of the system as a
whole through appropriate adaption to environmental circum-
stances. This system process expresses itself in a partial and
transient manner through various 'structural' characteristics such
as 'technology' and the degree of 'bureaucratisation'. It is these
temporary structural manifestations of a more fundamental and
ongoing process which organisational researchers tend to seize
upon for the purpose of empirical research. The organisation is
often equated with these structural characteristics, while the pro-
cessual aspects of system are ignored. Much of the research which
has been conducted under the guiding ftotion of the contingency
approach has been of this nature and as such stands as an
abstracted form of empiricism. 17 The incongruence between
theory and method which this reflects is a fundamental problem
facing social systems theorists in general. The processual nature of
'system' does not lend itself to meaningful study through the use of
quantitative snapshots of objectified social structures. Social
systems theorists who wish to operationalise contingency theory
thus face very real problems, in that a new methodology is needed
which is consistent with the ontology and epistemology of a true
open systems approach.
Our final remarks on contingency theory here will focus upon
Functionalist Organisation Theory 181
some of the conceptual implications of the model which we have
presented. The first of these emerges from the role of the strategic
control subsystem within the context of the model as a whole. As
we have argued. one of the functions of this subsystem is to
interpret what is happening in the environment and to guide and
adapt the organisation in an appropriate manner. It follows that the
relationship between elements of subsystems and their environ-
ment is contingent upon the decisions emerging from the strategic
control subsystem and also, at a lower level within the organisa-
tion, those emerging from the managerial subsystem. Thus, a
search for determinate relationships between contextual factors
and organisational characteristics, and between the elements of
different subsystems, is ill-founded. The pattern of relationships is
the product of human decision, and is influenced by choice. 38
The congruency hypothesis spells out many implications for
theories of organisational change and development. It suggests,
for example, that attempts to change the operational subsystem
through some programme of job redesign has implic~tions for all
the other subsystems within the organisation. Any analytical
framework for studying and prescribing organisational change
must therefore pay due adherence to the elements of the model as a
whole. We shall give further consideration to this point in the next
section on the quality of working life movement.
A third point of some importance arises from the fact that the
role of 'choice' draws attention to the issue of power as an
organisational variable. Within the context of social systems
theory the issue of power within organisations is virtually ignored.
An organismic systems model stresses the functional unity of
system parts, and views the organisation as being geared to the
achievement of end states shared by the system as a whole. Func-
tional imperatives and unity of purpose tend to dominate the
analysis. Although the contingency model implicitly identifies
power as a variable, it does not address it in any specific fashion.
To do so in a meaningful sense involves a shift in perspective away
from the bounds of social systems theory. We will discuss such
perspectives later in this chapter, and in our discussion of the
radical structuralist paradigm.
The quality of working life movement
We conclude our analysis of social system theory with a short
discussion of the quality of working life movement which has come
182 SocioloRical ParadiRms and OrRanisational Analysis
into prominence during the 1970s. In essence this movement seeks
to apply the insights of open systems theory, particularly through
the notions of open soci~technical systems theory and the theory
of job design, to the problems which its followers see as
characterising post-industrial societies. It is based upon a philos-
ophy of piecemeal social engineering which seeks to solve the
problems posed by the transition from the industrial to the post-
industrial society.
The key perspectives are well illustrated in the recent volumes
of readings edited by Davis and Cherns (1975). The authors argue
that there is a growing crisis which calls into question the viability
of present relationships between work, economic production, man
and society, and the ability of organisations to adapt to the rapid
pace of environmental change. The solution to many of these
problems is seen as the creation of an improvement in the quality of
working life. As they put it, ·confronting us is the need to accept, as
a national goal, both public and private responsibility for the
quality of working life in all of productive society, particularly in
facing the transition into the post-industrial era, if we are to
develop useful social policy and devise workable responses to
problems' (Davis and Cherns, 1975, p. 5). They argue thai the key
to the problem revolves around the •humanization of work·, which
•far from impo~ing economic costs. yields societal, personal and
economic gains' ( 1975, p. 6). They argue that there is a need to build
upon the body of knowledge, research and techniques which is
currently available and to formulate
a coherent body of theory and prtlctice on how to create the conditions
for a humane workinR life in its relevant .wcial environments.
Researchers and practitioners must learn how to define the situation,
how to study ongoing social systems. how to intervene in such situa-
tions with enhanced probability of success, how to identify and
measure a successful outcome, how to develop conceptual bases
within institutions which will support the diffusion of outcomes, and
how to assure that continued adaptation will take place.· ( 1976, p. 8)
Viewed within the context of the contingency model presented
in the previous section, therefore. the quality of working life
movement urges a programme of organisational change based
upon the assumption that a more humane working situation is a
functional imperative within the context of the system as a whole.
The argument is that social change within the wider environment is
such that people are beginning to demand more satisfying work,
and that organisations need to make operational and managerial
Functionalist Organisation Theory 183
subsystems congruent with these demands. This is a familiar
theme, which has long been the concern of neo-human relations
theorists and, more generally, those concerned with the theory of
organisational development (for example, Bennis, 1966): the
quality of working life movement represents a logical development
of these traditions. Its propositions run counter to those of con-
tingency theory, which stresses that in stable environments rigid,
dehumanising work structures may be appropriate for achieving
organisational effectiveness. The quality of working life theorists
tend to stand against such a proposition, arguing that the nature of
the post-industrial environment ('context' as opposed to 'task
environment') is such that in the long run open, flexible organisa-
tional design and management will prove the more effective. The
argument is pitched not merely at the organisational level: the
organisation is seen as a subsystem of the wider society, and the
view propounded is essentially that it is a functional imperative
that the quality of working life be improved to sustain society as a
whole. The notions of 'social responsibility' and. 'individual
responsibility' are often summoned to bridge the gap between
organisational or personal interests on the one hand and societal
interests on the other. Social responsibility thus becomes a func-.
tiona I imperative as far as the maintenance of the social system as a
whole is concerned.
The quality of working life movement is often seen and pre-
sented as a radical action-orientated response to the current
problems facing modern Western industrial societies. However,
their stance is essentially a regulative one, concerned to make
piecemeal adjustments designed to improve the viability of the
technological society characteristic of the present era. Their
fundamental commitment to existing social forms is evident when
one compares their approach, for example, with the theories
characteristic of the radical humanist paradigm discussed in Chap-
ters 8 and 9. Although committed to humanitarian concern for the
development of human growth and potential through the satisfac-
tion of 'higher-level' psychological needs, their 'selling pitch' is
invariably geared to the contribution which this will make to the
stability and survival of the system as a whole. This is clear, for
example, from the way in which Davis and Cherns emphasise the
economic benefits to be derived from improving the quality of
working life.
The 'hardware' or conceptual apparatus of the quality of work-
ing life movement is firmly based upon open socio-technical
systems theory. The socio-technical approach to job redesign is
184 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
given prominence, though the movement turns away from an
exclusively psychological perspective to embrace wider socio-
logical concerns. In particular, there are strong links with the
industrial democracy movement, which at times approaches a
pluralist view of organisations.
This review of the quality of working life movement completes
our analysis of social system theory and objectivism. We shall
return to an evaluation of the perspective as a whole at the end of
this chapter. For the moment we will close with the somewhat
oversimplified but at heart realistic observation that whereas con-
tingency theory stands as the contemporary equivalent of classical
management theory, the quality of working life movement stands
as the contemporary equivalent of the industrial psychology and
human relations movements. Whilst there has been a shift in per-
spective away from objectivism and towards a social systems
approach, the dominant concern is still to provide an understand-
ing of organisations, and the behaviour of individuals within them,
from an essentially managerial point of view.
Theories of Bureaucratic Dysfunctions
In this section we wish to devote some attention to the work on
organisations conducted by Robert Merton and three of his most
prominent students, Selznick, Gouldner and Blau. A case could be
made for treating this work as just one link within the overall chain
of development of social system theory, as presented in Figure 5.2;
indeed, we have already discussed the structural functionalist
orientation which characterises some of Selznick's work in that
context. However, separate treatment seems warranted on at least
two grounds. First, much of the work of Merton and his colleagues
is addressed to the theory of bureaucracy as developed by Max
Weber. It does not specifically seek to develop a functionalist
theory or organisations; it seeks to provide a critique of an
important element of Weber's work. A second and related point is
that the work of these theorists is primarily addressed to the study
and explanation of •dysfunctions'. Subject to a qualification with
regard to some of Selznick's work, it reflects an explicit break with
the use of an organismic analogy stressing the functional unity and
functional interdependence of system parts. Merton and his col-
leagues have been less concerned with explaining the unity and
interdependence of social systems than with explaining dis-
Functionalist Orxanisation Theory J85
equilibrium and change, in line with Merton's general sociological
concern to explain how socially deviant behaviour can be seen as
a product of social structure. As we have argued in Chapter 4,
Merton's work characterises the middle ground of the functionalist
paradigm and his work on the study of organisations is no excep-
tion. His influential study of the 'bureaucratic personality' pro-
vides an illustration of his approach to the analysis of 'deviant' or
'non-conforming' behaviour in action, and it Jays the basis for
further studies of the 'unanticipated consequences' and 'dysfunc-
tions of bureaucracy' which stand at the centre of the analyses
offered by Selznick, Gouldner and Blau. In the rest of this section
we will review the essential features of these studies. 39
Merton's article on 'Bureaucratic Structure and Personality'
(1968) focuses upon the internal stresses and strains which he sees
as characterising bureaucratic activities. Observing that the formal
Weberian theory of bureaucracy places emphasis upon the
positive attainments and functions of bureaucratic organisation.
Merton seeks to approach the subject from the opposite point of
view. As he puts it, 'Weber is almost exclusively concerned with
what the bureaucratic structure attains: precision, reliability.
efficiency. This same structure may be examined from another
perspective ... What are the limitations of the organisations
designed to attain these goals?' (Merton, 1968, p. 252). Merton
argues that bureaucratic operations. with their emphasis upon
method, prudence, discipline and conformity, may have such an
impact upon the bureaucrat that the adherence to rules and regula-
tions. originally conceived as means to wider purposes, become
ends in themselves. There thus occurs a 'displacement of goals'-
'an instrumental value becomes a terminal value' (1968, p. 253).
This pattern of behaviour of the bureaucrat provides an example of
what Merton classifies in his typology of adaption as ·ritualism •. It
is an example of a ritualistic situation where culturally defined
aspirations (in this case organisational goals) are abandoned, and
behaviour is governed by an almost compulsive adherence to
institutional norms (in this case bureaucratic rules and regula-
tions). Merton goes on to argue that the problems which the
rigidities create (for example, in dealing with the bureaucracy's
clients) generate further responses within the organisation which
reinforce the importance of conformity to rules and regulations.
The situation thus becomes cumulatively worse, as bureaucrats
proceed to defend their actions against outside pressures.
Bureaucratic behaviour and operation becomes increasingly
ritualistic in nature, characterised by the ·red tape' image so
186 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
familiar to the public eye. Merton stresses, in line with his general
sociological concern to explain the structural sources of deviancy,
that the •trained incapacity' of the bureaucrat is a product of the
bureaucratic structure within which he works. His model of
bureaucratic functioning is one which stresses the dysfunctions
which emerge from the overall attempt to achieve structural con-
trol over the operations of the organisation.
Philip Selznick's famous empirical study of organisation, 7V A
and the Grass Roots ( 1949), is informed by the Mertonian concern
for the study of unanticipated consequences and dysfunctions and
by Robert Michels's ideas on the 'iron law of oligarchy' .It is also
informed by Selznick's concern to construct a structural
functionalist theory of organisations.
The Tennessee Valley Authority (TV A) was, at the time of
Selznick's study, riding upon the crest of a wave. It was regarded
as a model of democratic organisation and a symbol of the aspira-
tions characteristic ofthe New Deal policy in the USA. Selznick's
study in essence shows that behind the democratic fa~ade lay a
bureaucratic oligarchy. The main thrust of the study is the notion
that ·an formal organisations are moulded by forces which are
tangential to their rationally ordered structures and stated goals'
(Selznick, 1966, p. 251). As we have discussed earlier in this
chapter, Selznick believed that the formal aspects of organisation
never succeed in conquering the non-rational human aspects of
behaviour. His study of TVA demonstrates this, through a detailed
analysis of administrative processes both within the organisation
and in its relations with its environment. More specifically, he
shows how the delegation of authority within the organisation
leads to specialisation within limited spheres of activity and the
orientation of groups of individuals to various sub-goals associated
with these specialised interests. The division of labour within the
bureaucratic structure in terms of expertise is thus seen as leading
to a focus upon operational goals which may be in conflict with each
other and detrimental to the overall purposes of the organisation as a
whole. 'Commitment' is seen as a basic mechanism in the genera-
tion of unanticipated consequences. The struggle for control which
results from these various commitments and conflicts of interest is
seen as reinforcing the division of the organisation and commitment
to sub-unit ideologies and goals. As in the case of the Merton model,
therefore, the dysfunctional consequences are cumulative and
self-reinforcing. They thus become increasingly embedded within
the nature of the organisation as a whole, potentially diverting it
further and further away from its formal objectives.
Functionalist Organisation Theory 187
Thus far the analyses of Merton and Selznick show a high degree
of similarity. Whilst Merton's study focused upon the dysfunc-
tional influence of rules as a form of bureaucratic control, Selznick
focused upon the dysfunctional consequences of delegation and
specialisation. However, from this point on their studies diverge
since, as we have noted, Selznick was also concerned to interpret
organisation from a more conventional structural functionalist
perspective. He thus resorts to the use of an organismic model
which stresses the relevance of•needs' and the process ofadaption
to the external environment in the interests of survival. The prob-
lem becomes that of establishing how the organisation limits the
cumulative and potentially destructive influence of the dysfunc-
tions. Selznick identifies two principal mechanisms. The first
relies upon the use of •ideology' to achieve conformity and loyalty
in the organisation. The second relates to the process of •co-
optation', through which various sectional interests within the
organisation and its environment are brought into a power-sharing
situation.ln these ways formal organisations such as TV A are seen
as being able to stem their dysfunctions, adapt and survive.
Selznick thus arrives at a structural functionalist view of organ-
isations which also has many similarities with the pluralist theories
discussed later in this chapter.
Alvin Gouldner's study of a gypsum factory reported in Patterns
of Industrial Bureaucracy (1954a) and Wildcat Strike (J954b) pro-
vides a third example of the Mertonian approach to the study of
bureaucratic dysfunctions. Gouldner addresses his work to certain
•obscurities' and •tensions in Weber's theory' (Gouldner, 1954a,
pp. 19-20), particularly with regard to the notion that the
effectiveness of bureaucratic functioning depends upon organisa-
tional members accepting the legitimacy of the rules or •legal
norms', whether these are established by agreement or imposition.
Gouldner points out that the manner in which rules are initiated
(for example, by agreement as opposed to imposition) may have a
fundamental influence upon the dynamics and effectiveness of
bureaucratic operations. His empirical analysis of managerial
succession within the gypsum factory, and the impact which this
has upon bureaucratic rules and employee activities, leads him to
conclude that the manner in which rules are initiated is of consid-
erable importance. On the basis of his analysis he identifies three
types of bureaucracy, ·mock', ·representative' and ·punitive',
each of which is characterised by different patterns of rule setting
and enforcement, different modes of social organisation and
different levels of tension and conflict.
188 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Gouldner's study thus leads to important modifications of the
notion of bureaucracy as conceived by Weber. His mode of
analysis focuses upon the way in which the human element of
organisation modifies the formal or technical aspect. His study of
the way in which bureaucracy develops through the creation and
use of impersonal rules emphasises the unanticipated conse-
quences which result because of their effect upon interpersonal
relations within the organisation. Rules are shown as being used by
managers and workers for fundamentally different ends and in
ways which are dysfunctional for the formal aims ofthe organisa-
tion. In the process of his analysis Gouldner illustrates quite
clearly that organisations as such only have goals or ends in an
abstract or ·metaphorical' sense, and that the reality of organisa-
tional life is one dominated by individuals and groups striving
towards different ends. As in the case of Selznick, therefore,
insofar as the focus on dysfunctions takes the analysis of organisa-
tion away from the social system postulate of functional unity, a
pluralist view of organisation emerges, though it is not developed
to its full extent. Whose goals is the organisation trying to achieve?
For whom are the rules useful as a rational device? Questions such
as these are central to pluralist views and emerge quite clearly from
Gouldner's analysis.
A fourth study relating to the dysfunctional aspects of
bureaucratic organisation is presented in Peter Blau's The Dynam-
ics of Bureaucracy ( 1955). In this work Blau sets out to apply the
principles contained in Merton's ·paradigm for functional analysis·
to the daily operations and interpersonal relations of government
officials in two bureaucratic agencies. His analysis focuses upon
the factors which generate disequilibrium and change within the
organisation, and confirms many of the bureaucratic dysfunctions
identified by Merton and his colleagues, such as overconformity
and goal displacement. It demonstrates how bureaucracies, far
from being the static structures supposedly envisaged in Weber's
ideal type, are the scenes of an ongoing process of interpersonal
relationships which generate new elements of organisation. The
study also demonstrates the part played by the latent as opposed to
the manifest functions of bureaucratic procedure. Blau 's analysis
of the way in which employee performance is evaluated through
the use of statistical records, for example, demonstrates that in
addition to serving as a performance control, the system also has
the latent function of maintaining cordial relations between super-
visors and subordinates. The study emphasises the importance
of tracing these unanticipated consequences as a basis for under-
Functiont1list Or~:cmi.tation Theory 189
standing the true significance of any particular organisational
characteristic. It clearly demonstrates the futility of confining
attention solely to the rational or manifest functions of organisa-
tion.ln Blau's analysis such factors are seen as lying at the heart of
explanations of organisational change. Bureaucratic structure,
like other aspects of social structure, is seen as generating forces
which lead to its own transformation.
This work of Merton, Selznick, Gouldner and Blau thus presents
a coherent and systematically developed critique of the notion of
bureaucracy they saw as reflected in Weber's ideal type. 4 ° Coming
as it did in the wake of the Hawthorne studies and the development
of the human relations movement, it is understandable that so
much attention should be devoted to the human or informal
aspects of organisation. However, in contrast to the perspective
reflected in the human relations movement and, indeed, social
system theory in general, the work of Merton and his colleagues
was specifically addressed to providing explanations of change in
social systems. They sought to inject a dynamic element into the
functionalist perspective. As we argued in Chapter4. the notion of
'dysfunction' and its corollary. 'functional autonomy', contained
the potential for a radically different theory of organisation. How-
ever, with the exception of Gouldner·s steps in this direction in his
article 'Reciprocity and Autonomy in Functional Theory' (1959),
this path was not followed. As we shall argue in a later chapter, it
was left to theorists approaching organisations from a fundamen-
tally different standpoint to develop the implications of this line of
enquiry. 41 Merton and his colleagues were largely content to dwell
upon the implications which their modified version of functional-
ism suggested.
The Action Frame of Reference
As will be clear from our discussion in Chapter 4, social action
theory or the action frame of reference is a perspective
characteristic of the most subjectivist boundary of the
functionalist paradigm. We have demonstrated how, along with
behavioural symbolic interactionism, it has developed largely as a
result of the fusion between positivist and idealist approaches to
social science. Whereas the action frame of reference was first
articulated by Max Weber, symbolic interactionism is largely the
product of the theoretical perspectives of Simmel and Mead.
190 Sc1cioloRkal ParadiRms and Organisaticmal Analysis
Strictly speaking, it would be appropriate to give consideration
to both these schools of thought in any detailed analysis of the
theory of organisations, since, as we have argued, whilst reflecting
a similar perspective in terms of the subjective-objective
dimension of our analytical scheme, their focus of attention is
often somewhat different. However, we shall not do so here
because, for one reason or another, symbolic interactionism has,
in a pure sense, had relatively little impact upon the theory of
organisations. Whilst there have been many studies of interaction
at work, they have rarely been true to the assumptions
characteristic of the subjectivist region of the paradigm. More
often than not such studies have been conducted within the con-
text of a systems approach to organisations (for example, Homans,
1950; Lupton, 1963) or have been cast as studies of ;deviant
behaviour' or 'informal organisation' (for example, Roy, 1960).
Yet others have ended up as an abstracted form of empiricism.
Similarly, the action frame of reference has rarely been con-
ceptualised or implemented in the pure form envisaged by Weber.
Its adherents have often taken as much of a lead from writers such
as Schutz, Blumer, Mead or even Merton as they have from
Weber:42 The lack of appreciation of the basic ontological,epi-
stemological and methodological assumptions which differentiate
the perspectives of these key writers has often led to hybrid
schemes of analysis which one can say are characteristic of the
subjectivist boundary of the functionalist paradigm but no more.
For this reason we are going to discuss them all under the heading
of the action frame of reference which, at least in Britain, has been
generally used as a label for describing a major proportion of the
work to be considered here. Whilst the work of GotTman and
Turner can be regarded as typical of symbolic interactionism, the
work of Gold thorpe and Silverman is more explicitly aligned with
the action frame of reference. However, this division, for the
reasons discussed above, is by no means a rigid one, there being
many points of overlap, particularly between the perspectives of
GotTman, Turner and Silverman.
Erving GotTman has established himself as the foremost expo-
nent of the "dramaturgical' approach to symbolic interactionism. A
product of the Chicago School of sociology, the principal
orientation of his work has been to demonstrate the way in which
individuals shape and influence their social reality. One of his
earliest and most famous works, The Presentation of Self in
Everyday Life ( 1959), otTers a view of individuals in ordinary work
situations as engaged in a 'theatrical performance', in a process of
Functionalist Organisation Theory 191
'impression management'. as putting on a show through which
they attempt to guide and control the impressions which people
form ofthem. The purpose of GotTman's analysis is to identify the
features which characterise the patterns of everyday life. In line
with the perspective of Si mmel, he is concerned to penetrate to the
underlying 'form' of human affairs. As he observes in the introduc-
tion to another of his books, he is interested in building up a picture
of human interaction from basic elements such as glances,
gestures, positioning and verbal statements, with a view to
uncovering the normative order of social affairs (GotTman, 1967).
His analyses focus upon the rituals and routines which
characterise human interaction.
However, GotTman does not restrict himself merely to the study
of the rules. He is also concerned to show how people relate to
them, either conforming or adapting them to their purposes. Roles
and institutional patterns are not seen as determining individual
behaviour in any sense; rather, they provide a framework within
which the process of social life is acted out. Ontologically, in the
tradition of behavioural symbolic interactionism, society is seen as
being prior to self, but the individual is accorded a creative role in
the production of self, or at least the impression of self created as a
result of performance management. In these respects GotTman's
analysis of interaction is much more subjectivist in orientation
than that of many other interactionists operating within the
functionalist paradigm. Compare his work, for example, with the
studies of behaviour in organisations offered by those theorists
who cast their analysis within a more managerially orientated
frame of reference and emphasise the systemic nature of life in an
organisational context (for example, Lupton, 1963; Roy, 1960).
GotTman's approach to the analysis of human interaction clearly
has implications for the study of behaviour in organisations in a
general sense. In addition, GotTman himself has made a number of
studies of institutional behaviour, particularly within the context
of mental institutions. On the basis of these studies he has offered
an analysis of the nature of 'total institutions', a term which is used
to characterise organisations such as prisons, mental hospitals,
concentration camps. ships, monastries, etc., in which people
spend whole periods of their lives, sleeping, playing and working
within institutional boundaries. GotTman depicts such institutions
as being characterised by the fact that all aspects of life are con-
ducted in the same place and under the same single authority; that
each member is in the company of a large group of others who are
treated alike and required to do the same things together; that the
192 Sociological Paradigms and Organi.wtional Analysis
phases of the days' activities are tightly scheduled, with the
patterns imposed from above; that the various enforced activities
are brought together to form a single rational plan supposedly
designed to fulfil the official aims of the institution (Goffman,
1961).
For Goff man one of the most important aspects of such institu-
tions is that, whilst the authorities attempt to define the situation
for the inmates - through rules, regulations, indoctrination, dis-
cipline, etc. - the individuals who live within them ·make out' by
adjusting in various ways. They 'develop a life of their own that
becomes meaningful, reasonable and normal once you get close to
it' (Goffman, 1961, p. 7). Such adjustments take the form of 'con-
formity' (behaving as a 'normal' member) or it may be achieved
through unauthorised means. Goffman's work focuses upon these
adjustment processes, revealing what he calls the ·underlife' of the
organisation -the ways in which inmates 'make out' in an attempt
to defend themselves against the onslaught of the system upon
their impressions of self.
As Eldridge and Crombie (1974), have noted, in addition to
illuminating the concept of self, Goffman's study of 'total institu-
tions' also informs us about the processes of sociai control within
them and teaches us generally about the life and mechanisms
which operate in all formal organisations. Those who are familiar
with Goffman's work can approach the interactionist-type studies
reflected in the work of more management-orientated theorists,
such as those referred to earlier, with a fresh and critical eye. The
difference in approach reflects their relative positions with regard
to the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme.
Another example of interactionist research, of relevance to the
study of organisations and characteristic of the subjectivist region
of the functionalist paradigm, is presented by Barry Turner in his
monograph Exploring the Industrial Subculture ( 1971). Turner
was a member of Joan Woodward's research team investigating
management control within organisations, a piece of work
characteristic of social system theory in the more objectivist
region of the paradigm (Woodward, 1972). Turner informs us that
his own particular book was written as a result of his dissatisfac-
tion with the prevailing forms of organisational analysis in general
and the management control project in particular. He was con-
cerned about the high levels of abstraction which characterised
much of this work and its remoteness from what seemed to him to
be ·real' industrial life. He was more interested in developing a
sociology of organisations which concerned itself 'with discover-
Functionalist Organisation Theory 193
ing the way in which people in industry define their life-positions,
with learning the sets of symbolisms which they adopt in the
definitions, and with examining the collective or organisational
consequences of these views which they hold of themselves •
(Turner, 1971, p. vii). In the course of his research for the
management control project, he also kept notes on his own
informal research observations of life in the organisation with
which he was concerned. It is this informal material which
provides the basis for his analysis of the industrial subculture.
Having collected his data, Turner searched the literature for
relevant concepts and theories which would make sense of his field
of observations, and he informs us in the course of his book that the
ideas of Schutz, Berger and Luckmann, and Weber had particular
relevance. From Schutz he seems to take the view that one of the
tasks of sociologists should be to analyse the 'taken for granted'
assumptions of everyday life. Turner sets out to do this with regard
to what he calls the 'industrial subculture' - a feature of organisa-
tional life worthy of understanding in its own right but which most
researchers take for granted or dismiss in summary terms.
Although Turner takes Schutz as his point of reference, his
analysis is by no means representative of the phenomenological
sociology to be discussed in our chapter on the interpretive para-
digm. Rather, it is much more orientated towards an analysis of
'meaning', fused with the concerns of what we have described as
'behavioural symbolic interactionism'. The general orientation of
Turner's study is clearly indicated in his opening paragraph, in
which he defines his view of the notion of 'subculture' and the way
in which it is maintained. As he puts it,
A subculture is a distinctive set of meanings shared by a group of
people whose forms of behaviour differ to some extent from those of
wider society. The distinctive nature of the set of meanings is
maintained by ensuring that newcomers to the group undergo a process
of learning or socialisation. The process links the individual to the
values of the group, and generates common motives, common reaction
patterns and common perceptual habits. Distinctiveness is also
maintained by the use of sanctions which are operated against those
who do not behave in appropriate ways. (Turner, 1971, p. I)
Turner is thus concerned to study the way in which subcultures
evolve and are sustained. His focus is upon 'meaning' and the way
in which it becomes shared through ·communicative exchanges'.
In his analysis of meaning Turner again makes reference to the
work of Schutz, particularly in relation to the notion of ·reflexiv-
194 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
ity', though, in point offact, his overall perspective on this is much
more closely related to the symbolic interaction model outlined by
Rose discussed in Chapter 4. There is undoubted confusion with
regard to ontology in this aspect of Turner's work. In contrast to
the Schutzian position, Turner's ontology is much more realist in
nature. However, this aside, his primary concern is to follow
Schutz in the study of the nature of meaning patterns and the
mechanisms by which they are conveyed. In this he pays consider-
able attention to the role of language and the ritualistic role of
objects.
Turner's thorough and clearly presented analysis of basic con-
cepts and their relationship to his empirical evidence results in a
valuable study of the informal aspects of organisational life. His
perspective is a very refreshing one. In contrast to most
interactionist studies of informal organisation, which are often
implicitly informed by a managerial perspective which regards
'informal' as 'deviant', Turner approaches the industrial sub-
culture on its own terms. He is concerned to reveal it for what it is,
without bringing in too many assumptions and preconceptions in
advance of detailed analysis. Although aspiring to a
phenomenological perspective, tor reasons which have been
argued above, it should be regarded as a piece of theory and
research on organisational life typical of the subjectivist region of
the functionalist paradigm.
A third example of theory and research typical of this region of
the paradigm is found in the work of those members of the Chicago
School who have concerned themselves with the sociology of
occupations. Among these Everett Hughes is particularly promi-
nent for the work which he himself has conducted (for example,
Hughes, 1958) and for his influence upon other scholars who have
chosen to follow his lead. Their work is characterised by an
attempt to penetrate to the level of subjective meaning in an
exploration of occupational roles. In contrast to other role
theorists, who often tend to be concerned with the structural
aspects of role and tangible role behaviour, the Chicago theorists
have interested themselves in the study of what work means for the
individual, and the way in which this is related to attitudes and
relationships within the work place. These theorists tend to start
with the individual and build out from there in the construction of
his organisational world. Thus we are given an inside view of what
it is like to be 'in the basement' as an apartment janitor or to be a
cab-driver relating to his 'fares' (Gold, 1964; Davis, 1967). Taken
together, such studies build up a picture of work experience in
Functionali.'>t Organi.wtion Tlreory 195
contemporary society. as viewed by the workers themselves
rather than by a ·detached’ observer.41 The approach draws
heavily upon ethnographic accounts and participant observation
techniques, and tends to focus upon process as opposed to static
structure as a means of characterising the principal features of
the world of work and everyday life.
The work of the occupational sociologists moves very close to
the use of an action frame of reference, in that they are primarily
concerned with the general orientation of individuals to their roles
and with the meaning of work at a subjective level. A similar
perspective characterises the work of Goldthorpe and his col-
leagues (1968), in their study of industrial workers’ orientations to
work, though little explicit interest is shown in the analysis of
subjective meaning as such, particularly in its processual and
emergent aspects. 44 Their study of ·affluent’ manual workers in
the context of their industrial employment attempts to describe
and explain ‘orientations to work·. This perspective has much in
common with Weber’s attempt to construct a typology of social
action based on four kinds of orientations – traditional, emotional,
value-rational and purposively rational. Goldthorpe and his col-
leagues do not employ Weber’s typology as such or, for that
matter, make much reference to his work, though there are clear
and obvious links. They argue that among the workers studied a
particular orientation to work is predominant- one of a markedly
instrumental kind. As Eldridge (1971) has noted, the analysis of
Goldthorpe et al is closely linked to the use of reference group
analysis, in that one of the primary concerns of the research is to
examine the relationship between orientations to work and the
worker’s place in the class structure. This research on orientation
to work is cast within the context of a wider study concerned to test
the widely acknowledged thesis of working-class embourgeoise-
mem: that is, as manual workers and their families become more
affluent. they become progressively assimilated into the middle
class. Thus in this study the action frame of reference is given a
background role: it is a tool to be used in relation to but a small part
of the research project as a whole. It does, however. present one of
the few well-known British attempts to operationalise the action
frame of reference, albeit in this limited sense.
Most prominent among the advocates of the action frame of
reference as a basis for organisational analysis has been the name
of David Silverman. Indeed, it was he who, for the most part,
introduced the term to organisation theorists, arguing in his book
The Theory of Organisations ( 1970) that it provides an alternative
196 Sociological Pamdi!(m.’l and Or!(anisational Analysis
to systems theory. Silverman suggests that the systems approach,
as applied to organisations, has ‘severe logical difficulties’,
particularly in its assumption that organisations as systems have
‘needs’ or are ·self-regulating’ .45 He points out that to attribute
such characteristics to organisations, except as a heuristic device,
involves the problem of ‘reification’, a process whereby social
constructs are accorded the power of thought and action. He
argues that explanations of social change at a systems level usually
involves these problems of reification, since attention is drawn to
the purposive actions of the system, which is seen as recognising
threats to its existence and as adapting accordingly. The systems
view of organisations is thus seen as being pitched at a level of
analysis which does not take into account, or provide explanations
in terms of, the actions of the individual human beings who are its
constituent members. In opposition to this systems view Silver-
man argues that social scientists should build their theories upon
foundations which view social reality as being socially con-
structed, socially sustained and socially changed. In other words,
Silverman wishes to place man as a social actor at the centre of
the stage, insofar as the analysis of social phenomena such as
organisations are concerned. In recognition of the fact that social
life is an ongoing process, sustained and ·accomplished’ by social
actors, Silverman advocates the action frame of reference as pro-
viding an appropriate basis for analysis.
Silverman’s view of the action frame of reference, which is
based upon the work of a number of writers, is summarised in
terms of the following seven propositions:
I. The social sciences and the natural sciences deal with entirely
different orders of subject-matter. While the canons of rigour
and scepticism apply to both, one should not expect their
perspective to be the same.
2. Sociology is concerned with understanding action rather than
with observing behaviour. Action arises out of meanings which
define social reality.
3. Meanings are given to men by their society. Shared orientations
become institutionalised and are experienced by later genera-
tions as social facts.
4. While society defines man, man in turn defines society.
Particular constellations of meaning are only sustained by con-
tinual reaffirmation in everyday actions.
S. Through their interaction men also modify, change and trans-
form social meanings.
Functionalist Organisation Theory 197
6. It follows that explanations of human actions must take account
of the meanings which those concerned assign to their acts; the
manner in which the everyday world is socially constructed yet
perceived as real and routine becomes a crucial concern of
sociological analysis.
7. Positivistic explanations, which assert that action is determined
by external and constraining social or non-social forces, are
inadmissible. (Silverman, 1970, pp. 126-7)
In developing these propositions Silverman draws very heavily
upon ideas characteristic of the work of Dilthey, Weber and
Schutz.46 His distinction between the subject matter which charac-
terises the natural and social sciences (Proposition 1), for example,
follows Dilthey’s distinction between Naturwissenschaften
(natural sciences) and Geisteswissenschaften (cultural sciences).
As we argue in Chapter 6 on the interpretive paradigm, this dis-
tinction is central to an understanding of the German idealist
tradition of social thought. The cultural sciences were seen as being
distinguished by their essentially ‘spiritual’ character, and it was
held that they could not be understood through the approaches and
methods of the natural sciences. The idealists rejected positivist
epistemology and the nomothetic methods employed by the natural
scientists as simply inappropriate to the realm ofsocial and cultural
affairs. They held that man was ‘free’ and did not behave and act in
accordance with positivist-type laws. As a means of bridging this
gap between idealist and positivist perspectives, theorists such as
Dilthey and Weber concerned themselves with problems of
‘understanding’ in the realm of human affairs. The notion of
verstehen or ‘interpretive understanding’ which they developed
was seen as providing a method appropriate to the social sciences.
As developed by Weber, the notion of verstehen was used as a
methodological tool which drew attention to the importance of
understanding the subjective meaning which lay behind social
action. For Weber explanations of social phenomena had to be
‘adequate on the level of meaning’.
It is precisely this point which Silverman seeks to emphasise in a
number of the propositions of his action schema. Proposition 2, for
example, emphasises that ·sociology is concerned with under-
standing action rather than with observing behaviour’, and that
·action arises out of meanings which define social reality·. This is
firmly in line with the Weberian position. Social action is seen as
deriving from the meaning which is attributed to the social world
198 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
by individual actors. It is imperative, therefore, that the sociologist
understand these subjective meanings if he is to understand the full
significance of individual acts. Thus to focus upon the behaviour of
individuals in the tradition of positivist social science is to miss the
point, since patterns of behaviour may mean different things to
different people. The action of men is meaningful to them. They
construct their social world by attributing meaning to it. Action
arises from meanings, so it is necessary to understand social
activities at the level of subjective meaning. This point is again
emphasised by Silverman in Proposition 6, which states that
‘explanations of human actions must take account of the meanings
which those concerned assign to their acts; the manner in which
the everyday world is socially constructed yet perceived as real
and routine becomes a crucial concern of sociological analysis’.
In Proposition 3 Silverman asserts that ·meanings are given to
men by their society. Shared orientations become institutionalised
and are experienced by later generations as social facts’. Here we
are concerned with the issue of ontology, and we find Silverman
adopting a ‘realist’ position in which society is seen as being
ontologically prior to man. In developing his position on this point
Silverman makes specific reference to Durkheim and the view that
men are constrained by social facts which determine their actions
and their consciousness. Following Durkheim, Silverman suggests
that meanings reside in social institutions and that individuals play
roles that are given to them as a result of their location upon the
social map. As he puts it, ‘by participating in society, they are
given expectations about the appropriate acts of themselves and of
others when in various status positions. They are able to
apprehend the meanings associated with the actions of other
people and to form a view of self based on the responses of others’
(1970, p. 131). In order to explain why people should meet the
expectations of others Silverman invokes explanations presented
by Talcott Parsons in The Social System, which emphasise the
tendency to order in social affairs – ‘common values must pre-
dominate if the system is to survive’ ( 1970, p. 131). Ontologically,
therefore, Silverman’s position appears to be as ‘realist’ as that of
anyothertheorist within the functionalist paradigm. He argues, for
example, that ‘the social world is given to us by the past history
and structure of our society’, and that ·social reality is .. pre-
defined” in the very language in which we are socialised.
Language provides us with categories which define as well as
distinguish our experiences’ (1970, p. 132). We are thus left in no
doubt that individual actors occupy a ‘realist’ social world which is
Functionalist Organisation Theory 199
external to the individual and has a reality which is independent of
any individual’s social construction of it.
However, in Proposition 4 Silverman immediately proceeds lO
qualify this ‘realism’ by asserting that ‘while society defines man,
man in turn defines society’. He emphasises that ‘particular con-
stellations of meaning are only sustained by continual reaffirma-
tion in everyday actions’. In developing this proposition Silverman
emphasises that whilst individual actors may operate in
accordance with the ‘common-sense’ belief that the social world
exists outside themselves, in point of fact this common-sense
notion only holds insofar as it is sustained and reinforced through
the everyday actions of the actors directly involved in any given
social situation. It thus has a precarious existence. ‘The existence
of society depends upon it being continuously confirmed in the
actions of its members’ (1970, p. 134). In support of this view he
argues, following Berger and Pull berg ( 1966), that social structure
‘has no reality except a human one. It is not characterisable as
being a thing able to stand on its own … [and) exists only insofar
and as long as human beings realise it as part of their world’. He
goes on to argue that to attribute to society an existence separate
from and above its members is to reify it. Again following Berger
and Pullberg, Silverman suggests that ‘social roles and institutions
exist only as an expression of the meanings which men attach to
their world- they have no “ontological status”‘ (1970, p. 134).1n
other words, Silverman is suggesting that reality is socially con-
structed. He is advocating an ontology which is essentially
‘nominalist’ in orientation.
Propositions 3 and 4 thus tend to qualify one another, in that
the former suggests a ‘realist’ ontology, and the latter a
·nominalist’ ontology. As we shall argue in Chapter 7, Silverman is
unclear on this point in most of his work and he oscillates pre-
cariously from one position to another according to his purpose.
His overall position seems to be that whilst recognising that there
is an external world which is ontologically prior to man, its crucial
significance as far as the study of social affairs is concerned lies in
the way in which its ·meaning’ resulted from the interpretations
placed upon it by individual actors.
In emphasising the way in which individuals have the ability to
interpret and attribute meaning to their social world, Silverman in
effect directs attention to the voluntaristic nature of human
activities. This receives specific attention in PropositionS, which
asserts that ‘through their interaction men … modify, change and
transform social meanings’. In elaborating this proposition he
200 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
places emphasis upon the ways in which individuals can choose to
interpret the roles which they play, and how they can disrupt
prevailing views of reality by engaging in disruptive activities of
one kind or another. In his analysis Silverman qualities his position
with regard to Parsons’ view of the nature of social order referred
to earlier, and recognises that because of the choices available to
the individual, social integration may, in fact, be problematic.
In the elaboration of his action schema Silverman thus presents
a view of the social world which emphasises the processual nature
of human affairs. It is a world where human actors interpret the
situation in which they find themselves and act in ways which are
meaningful to them. Social reality is thus seen as being in a process
of continual flux, as human beings interpret and redefine, through
their actions, the world in which they live. It follows that special
methods are required to study this social world. Thus Silverman,
in line with his -opening proposition on the distinction between the
natural and social sciences, concludes by asserting that
‘positivistic explanations, which assert that action is determined
by external and constraining social or non-social forces, are
inadmissible’ (Proposition 7). Explanations of social affairs must
be adequate, on the level of meaning, for the actors directly
involved. The action frame of reference is offered as a perspective
adequate for this end.
As will become apparent from our analysis in Chapter 6, Silver-
man’s action approach has much more in common with the work of
Weber than with that of Schutz. Although Silverman makes
frequent reference to Schutzian concepts, his perspective is far
r.emoved from the ‘existential phenomenology’ which
characterises Schutz’s work. Silverman, in The Theory of
Organi:wtions, seems primarily concerned, like Weber, to develop
a method of analysis appropriate to the nature of social
phenomena, and he advocates the action frame of reference as a
method of analysing social relations within organisations. It repre-
sents a perspective characteristic of the subjectivist boundary of
the functionalist paradigm. While quite voluntarist in terms of its
assumptions with regard to the way in which individuals define and
interpret the situations in which they find themselves, it is based
upon an ontology which is essentially realist in orientatio11. As
advocated by Silverman, in terms of epistemology the perspective
is set against the extreme form of positivism characteristic of the
most objectivist region of the functionalist paradigm, but does not
reject the positivist approach in its entirety. Silverman, for exam-
ple, is in favour of a measure of ‘generalisation’ in the social
Functionalist Organisation Theory 201
sciences, but emphasises that the ‘generalisations which the social
sciences develop’ are ‘fundamentally different from the laws of the
natural sciences’ (1970, p. 128).
There has been a tendency in recent years for writers on
organisations to equate the action frame of reference with schools
of thought such as ethnomethodology and phenomenology. This
represents a gross misstatement of the actual position. Whilst
action theorists often make reference to the work of
phenomenologists and ethnomethodologists, they do not follow
the full implications of the latter’s point of view. In the manner of
other theorists within the paradigm, they tend to incorporate the
insights of ‘outsiders’ insofar as they serve useful ends. Action
theorists have used notions derived from the phenomenological
perspective to shore up and support the functionalist pointofview.
As will be clear from our discussion in Chapter 6 this is clearly
evident in the work of Weber, who used idealist notions in a
positivist way. The same is true of Parsons and of Silverman.
Silverman, for example, in addition to concluding that the action
frame of reference is no more than a method of analysis, suggests
that it may ‘be a useful source of propositions in organisational
analysis’ (1970, p. 143). This view is firmly in line with the
positivist attitude to the whole concept of verstehen and clearly
emphasises its location within the context of the functionalist
paradigm. In Silverman’s work the action frame of reference
becomes no more than a different way of studying the same reality.
Emphasis is placed upon the importance of developing scientific
explanations at an individual as opposed to a systems level of
analysis, because of the problems of reification. The ontological
and epistemological assumptions remain firmly grounded in the
functionalist perspective. As will become clear in our discussion in
Chapters 6 and 7, phenomenology and ethnomethodology in their
true form are predicated upon fundamentally different views with
regard to the ontological nature of social reality itself.
Silverman did not adhere to the position articulated in The
Theory of Organi.wtions for long. As we will see in Chapter 7, his
subsequent work led him to a perspective firmly located within the
context of the interpretive paradigm. A comparison of this later
work with the approach presented in The Theory of Organisations
clearly illustrates the essentially intermediate position which the
latter reflects in terms of the subjectivo-objective dimension of
our analytical scheme. Silverman’s early and later works are para-
digms apart.
202 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Pluralist Theory
The issues of power and conflict within organisations have long
attracted the attention of organisation theorists but have rarely
received sustained and systematic consideration. We intend to
argue here that many of the ideas and research findings which this
interest has generated anticipate, and point the way towards, the
development of a pluralist theory of organisations characteristic of
the conflict functionalism discussed in Chapter 4. Taken together.
they lay the basis for the analysis of organisations as pluralist
political systems – according to which organisations and their
environment are viewed principally as arenas of conflict between
individuals and groups whose activities are orientated towards the
achievement of their own personal goals, values and interests.
Many current theories of organisation contain elements of this
view but stop some way short of a fully developed pluralist theory
of organisations. Power and conflict are often studied as isolated
phenomena or used as concepts in schemes geared to wider ends.
They are rarely regarded as defining the nature of organisation
itself.
As Eldridge and Crombie ( 1974) have noted, the use of the term
“pluralism’ is fraught with danger because of the wide range of
interpretations which have come to be placed upon it. It will be as
well, therefore, if we set out in a little more detail the way in which
we intend to use it here. Broadly speaking, we see a “pluralist’ as
opposed to a ·unitary’ view of organisations as reflecting three sets
of assumptions relating to what we shall describe as interests.
conflict and power .47
The different assumptions with regard to interests are clearly
reflected in the distinction which Fox (1966) has drawn between
the industrial organisation as a ‘team’ striving towards the
achievement of a common objective and as a coalition with
divergent interests. Whereas the unitary view of organisations
tends to stress that an organisation is a co-operative enterprise
united in the pursuit of a common goal, the pluralist view stresses
the diversity of individual interests and goals. Whereas from a
unitary perspective organisations are viewed as instruments of
rational and purposive activity. from a pluralist view they rep-
resent a network of sectional groups interested in the wider pur-
pose of the organisation as a whole only insofar as it serves their
own individual ends. From a pluralist perspective the formal goals
of an organisation have the status of little more than a legitimising
Functionalist Organisation Theory 203
fa~ade, an umbrella under which a host of individual and group
interests are pursued as ends in themselves.
The unitary view of organisations regards conflict within
organisations as a rare and transient phenomenon which, when
present, can easily be eradicated or controlled through appropriate
managerial action. Because interests are regarded as being
characterised by a harmonious order, conflict within organisations
is regarded as an alien, obstrusive and unwelcome force and one
which is largely the creation of deviants and troublemakers. From
a pluralist perspective, on the other hand, conflict within organisa-
tions is viewed as an inevitable and ineradicable feature of every-
day life. The organisation is seen as a web of cross-cutting con-
flicts between the individuals and interest groups which give it life.
Rather than advocating its removal, the pluralist view emphasises
the possibilities of its playing a constructive role within the context
of the organisation as a whole. For the pluralist, conflict must be
institutionalised in some way, so that it can find expression and
‘work itself through’ without prejudice to the survival of the
system as a whole.
Within the context of a unitary view of organisation the ques-
tion of power is largely ignored. Since the organisation is viewed as
a harmonious and conflict-free enterprise, striving uniformly·
towards the achievement of what is common and in the interests of
all, questions about the source and use of power do not often arise.
Concepts such as authority, leadership and control are preferred
ways of describing the ‘prerogative’ of managers to guide the
organisation as a whole towards desired goals and aims. Power in
this sense is little more than a neutral resource which oils the
wheels of the system as a whole. The pluralist view, on the other
hand, regards the power of various groups within the organisation
as a crucial variable for understanding what happens in everyday
affairs. Power is seen as the medium through which conflicts of
interest are settled. Organisational life, from a pluralist standpoint,
is a power-play between individuals and groups who draw upon
their various sources of power in order to control their work
situations and to achieve whatever objectives they value. The
organisation is viewed as a plurality of power holders who derive
their influence from a plurality of sources. The organisation is
regarded as a loose coalition which moves towards the achieve-
ment of its plurality of aims through an uncertain process of
bargaining and mutual adjustment of respective claims. Consider-
able emphasis is pla”ed upon the importance of devising a network
of rules and regulations which allow this process to occur in an
204 Sociolo~:ical Paradi~:ms and Or~:anisational Analysis
orderly fashion and without undue prejudice to the survival of the
organisation as a whole.
Thus, by way of summary, the two views of organisation can be
illustrated as in Table 5.1.
Table 5.1
1be unitary and pluralist views of interests, connict and power
laterests
Coafllct
Power
Th~ unitt1ry vi~w
Places emphasis upon the
achievement of common
objectives. The organisation
is viewed as being united
under the umbrella of com-
mon goals. and striving to-
wards their achievement in
the manner of a well integ-
rated team.
Regards connict as a rare and
transient phenomenon which
can be removed through
appropriate managerial
action. Where it does arise it
is usually anributed to the
activities of deviants and
troublemakers.
Largely ignores the role of
power in organisational life.
Concept~ such as authority,
leadership and control tend
to be preferred means of
describing the managerial
prerogative of guiding the
organisation tow;ords the
achievement of common
interests.
Th~ pluralist vi~w
Places emphasis upon the
diversity of individual and
group interests. The
organisation is regarded as a
loose coalition which has but
a remote interest in the for-
mal goals of the organisation.
Regards connict as an inher-
ent and ineradicable
characteristic of ·organisa-
tional affairs and stresses its
potentially positive or func-
tional aspects.
Regards power as a variable
crucial to the understanding
of the activities of an
organisation. Power is the
medium through which con-
nicts of interest arc alleviated
and resolved. The organisa-
tion is viewed as a plurality of
power holders drawing their
power from a plurality of
sources.
The unitary view of organisation is epitomised in the classical
theory of organisations which tends to view the organisation as a
machine geared to the achievement of formal goals. From this
point ofview the organisation is an instrument of purposive ration-
ality, which directs its members in an effective and efficient
Functio11alist Orgalli!illtion Th(•ory 205
manner. The members of the organisation are viewed as respond-
ing to incentives which secure their commitment to the formal
goals of the organisation. The enterprise is thus envisaged as a
unitary phenomena in which the goals of all members can be
simultaneously satisfied; the task of management is to ensure that
the organisation is appropriately structured. directed and con-
trolled so that effective operation is achieved.
The unitary view is also reflected in many of the other theories
which we have reviewed in earlier sections of this chapter.
Barnard’s view of an organisation as a ‘co-operative system’. the
human relations concern to integrate individual and organisational
needs and the open systems view of an organisation as being
geared to the process of survival. all in varying degrees reflect
elements of this perspective. Above all else the organisation is
viewed as a functionally integrated system, the operations of
which can be understood with reference to the organisational goals
which it is concerned to achieve. However, ever since the Haw-
thorne studies, increasing attention has been devoted to the role of
conflict within organisations, and it is now rare to find theoretical
perspectives which reflect the unitary view in an extreme sense.Jn
broad terms. developments in organisation theory over the last
fifty years have been away from the unitary and towards the
pluralist view of organisations. However, as we noted earlier, this
movement has been incomplete, so that many theories reflect
elements of a pluralist perspective but stop some way short of a
fully developed pluralist theory. To this extent many of the
theories which we have discussed in earlier sections of this chapter
are of a hybrid nature. Some are more pluralist than others. As a
means of developing the pluralist perspective in a little more detail,
therefore, it will be useful if we return to some of the theory and
research which we have already considered and examine the way
in which it has treated interests, conflict and power. We will then
proceed to examine the work of other theorists who have con-
tributed to the pluralist perspective.
Pluralist elements in social system theory
Many theories located within the bounds of social system theory
tend to move towards the pluralist perspective with regard to
conflict and, to a lesser extent, with regard to interests. But with
regard to power they remain firmly embedded within the unitary
standpoint. Conflict is recognised to occur in many forms. For
example, theorists in the human relations tradition, or those who
206 Soc·iological Paradigms and Or~:anisational Analysis
adopt a socio-technical systems perspective, have emphasised the
conflicts which can arise between human needs and the
characteristics of formal organisation structure (for example,
Argyris, 1952 and 1957), technology (Trist and Bamforth, 1951)
and the like. Other theorists and researchers have pointed towards
the conflicts which can arise between formal organisational roles
(for example, Dalton, 1959; Katz and Kahn, 1966) and to conflicts
between the different sub-units of an organisation (Lawrence and
Lorsch, 1967). Others have documented conflicts in the work
place between individual workers, work groups and their
supervisors (for example, Lupton, 1963; Whyte, 1955). Theorists
who have focused upon decision-making processes within
organisations have emphasised the conflicts which occur between
managers (for example, Cyert and March, 1963). Social system
theory thus contains many examples of theory and research which
treat organisational life as based upon a plurality of conflicts.
However, these theories do not always recognise organisations
as being characterised by a plurality of interests. The human
relations theorists, for example, in focusing upon human needs,
tend to underplay the fact that individuals may have goals which
are in conflict with those of the organisation. Their perspective is
based upon the premise that it is somehow possible to satisfy
individual needs through the achievement of wider organisational
goals. The emphasis upon needs thus tends to present the organisa-
tion as a unitary phenomena which has the capacity to operate as a
well integrated team. The potential divergence of goals is de-
emphasised as a consequence of the focus upon universal needs.
Again, those theorists who have been concerned with the study of
conflicts between organisational roles and sub-units often stress
the structural determinants of conflict as opposed to the plurality
of individual and group orientations and interests, which, as Dubin
(1956) and Goldthorpe and his colleagues (1968) have demon-
strated, may be brought into the organisation from outside.
Similarly, the organisation theorists who have focused upon
decision-making processes within organisations also often tend to
de-emphasise the plurality of interests. This is particularly evi-
dent, for example, in the work of Simon ( 1957), March and Simon
(1958) and Cyert and March ()963), and in the notions of ‘bounded
rationality’ and ·administrative man·. Such conceptualisations
attempt to reconcile the unitary view of organisation as a rationally
ordered enterprise with the observations that organisational
activities do not in practice follow the pattern that the rational
model would lead us to expect. Their theories favour a unitary
Functionalist Orl(anisation Theory 207
view of organisation. based upon a qualified principle of rational-
ity. as opposed to a pluralist view. which gives full recognition to
the variety of orientations and interests of individual members.••
Most social system theories completely ignore the issue of
power within organisations. As we have argued at some length,
these theories are usually based upon assumptions that organisa-
tions are social processes characterised by equilibrium or
homeostasis. Theories based upon an organismic analogy, for
example, tend to stress the functional interdependence and unity
of the system and emphasise the functions which are performed in
the interests of the survival of the whole. The exercise of authority
and control is thus seen as an essential process geared to the
achievement of this overall state of affairs. The emphasis upon
common purpose and functional unity tends to deflect attention
from a consideration of the power of constituent elements. Issues
involving the use of power tend to be interpreted as issues or
problems of authority and control which are of direct relevance to
the effectiveness of the organisation in the achievement of its
formal goals (see, for example, Tannenbaum, 1968).
Pluralist elements in theories of bureaucratic
dysfunctions ·
Moving on to consider the theories of bureaucratic dysfunctions,
we find that they usually reflect a pluralist view with regard to
interests and conflict and tend, to an extent, to recognise the
importance of power as a variable in organisational analysis. As we
have seen, the work of Merton (1968), Selznick (1949), Gouldner
(1954a and b) and Blau (1955) all demonstrated, in one way or
another, the unintended consequences of formal organisation. In
cases where these unintended consequences were dysfunctional
as far as the formal goals of the organisation were concerned, it
was usually because they were functional for other interests within
the organisation. Merton’s ‘bureaucratic personalities’ adopted a
defensive and ritualistic posture to protect themselves from the
possibility of criticism from outside the organisation; the dysfunc-
tions of specialisation and goal displacement revealed by Selznick
arose because the specialists sought to further their own interests;
the bureaucratic rules in Gouldner’s gypsum factory were used by
the workers and managers to serve their own quite different
purposes; Blau’s study of government agencies revealed
208 SocioloRical Paradigms and Organimtional Ana/pi.~
numerous examples of group and sectional interests. The very
notion of dysfunction inevitably raises questions such as. func-
tional or dysfunctional for whom’? Whose goals is the organisation
attempting to achieve? Whose interests are the rules rational for?
A theory of interests is thus a direct corollary of the theory of
dysfunctions. As Gouldner (1959) has noted, the notion of
dysfunctions directs attention towards issues such as the degree of
functional reciprocity which characterises the relationships
between system parts. To the extent that reciprocal relationships
are asymmetrical, interdependence of parts is less than perfect and
gives rise to various degrees of functional autonomy or inde-
pendence of parts within the context of the system as a whole. It is
this principle of autonomy which lies at the heart of the pluralist
theory of interests.
The role of conflict is also given considerable prominence in the
theories of Merton and his colleagues. These studies of
bureaucracy were, in many respects, stimulated by the Hawthorne
findings on the relationship between formal and informal
organisation, and they are permeated by the theme of conflict
between the rational and human aspects of organisation. Conflicts
between bureaucrats and their clients, between sectional groups
and coalitions within the organisation, and between management
and workers are all given prominence in one or more of these
studies. Conflict is central to the theory of bureaucratic dysfunc-
tions.
The work of Selznick ( 1949) and Gouldner (1954a and b), also
draws attention to the plurality of power relationships within
organisations, but the insights generated are not followed up to
their full extent. Selznick traces the struggle for control which
ensues from the different commitments and patterns of interest
within the organisation, and the process of co-option through
which they are brought within the bounds of the decision-making
system. However, his general orientation is the study of the
manner in which an organisationlimit.f the influence of its dysfunc-
tions and is not so much concerned with tracing them to their
source, as a fully developed view of power would require.
Similarly, Gouldner gives much attention to the process of subor-
dination and control within ‘punitive’ bureaucratic structures, but
stops short ofa full analysis of the power relationships between the
workers and managers under investigation. These studies both
point the way towards a pluralist view of power, but since they are
essentially orientated towards the specific study of the dysfunc-
tions of bureaucratic structures, they only treat the subject insofar
Functionalist Organisation Theory 209
as it has relevance to this purpose. Their focus upon bureaucratic
structure necessarily overemphasises the role and importance of
formal authority as opposed to other forms of power relationships.
Nonetheless, in terms of general orientation and approach their
overall theoretical stance has much in common with, and has
contributed immeasurably towards, more fully developed pluralist
views of organisation, notably that of Crozier (1964).
Pluralism and the action frame of reference
Theorists who adopt the action frame of reference as a basis for
their analysis of organisational situations usually do so in recogni-
tion of the fact that any social situation is characterised by a
plurality of interests. They also frequently point to the conflicts
which exist within the situations studied, and occasionally draw
attention to the role of power as a variable worthy of analysis.
However, their standpoint upon the last issue tends to be implicit
rather than explicit, and is not developed systematically to any
degree.
As will be clear from our earlier analysis, the action frame of
reference owes much to the Weberian view that explanations in
social science must be ‘adequate on the level of meaning’. It is
based on the view that the various actors in a social situation
interpret and define that situation in ways which have meaning for
them, and act accordingly. The idea that there will be a plurality of
such definitions is central to this standpoint; if this were not so,
then the action frame of reference would prove unnecessary. That
organisational situations are characterised by a plurality of
interests is clearly evident in the work of Goffman (1961), Turner
(1971), Goldthorpe et a/. (1968), and Silverman (1970), as dis-
cussed earlier. It is also evident in the work of many of the so-
called behavioural symbolic interactionists referred to in
Chapter 4.
The conflicts which arise as a result of the different definitions of
organisational situations have often provided the action theorist
with excellent case material for illustrating his particular point of
view. It is clearly evident in Goffman·s (1961) analysis of the
‘underlife of total institutions’ and in Eldridge’s analysis of
restrictive practices (Eldridge, 1971, pp. 45-9). Silverman’s
reinterpretation of Gouldner’s Wildcat Strike in terms of a social
action perspective also provides an excellent illustration of the
ways in which conflicts in expectations, modes of involvement in
210 Sociolol(ica/ Paradil(ms and Orl(anisational Analy.ris
an organisation and general conflicts in the definition of situations
can account for change within organisations (Silverman, 1970, pp.
155-63). Indeed, the scheme which Silverman suggests for the
comparative analysis of organisations from an action perspective
has many characteristics which emphasise the pluralistic nature of
organisations. He summarises the issues which ought to be
addressed as follows:
I. The nature of the predominant meaning-structure and associated
role-system in different organisations and the extent to which it
relies on varying degrees of coercion or consent.
2. The characteristic: pattern of involvement of the actors: differing
attachment to rules and definitions of their situation.
3. The typical strategies used by different actors to attain their
ends.
4. The relative ability of different actors to impose their definition
of the situation upon others. The nature and sources of the
symbolic ‘sticks’ (resources) available to the actors; their
relative effectiveness.
S. The origin and pattern of change of meaning-structures
(institutionalisation and de-institutionalisation of meanings) in
different organisations. (Silverman, 1970, pp. 171- 2)
Points I and 4 draw attention to the role of power within
organisations, which is seen from an action standpoint largely in
terms of the ability to impose one’s definition of a situation upon
others. Many action theorists have referred to this. GotTman’s
definition of ‘total institutions’, for example, emphasises that such
organisations assume much of their special character because
those in authority are able to impose their definitions of the situa-
tion upon inmates. However, action theorists do not tend to
involve themselves in an analysis of the nature and sources of
power as such. Power is often seen as a variable relevant to the
explanation of the ‘meanings’ which prevail but is rarely analysed
in detail. Nevertheless, the action theorists have much in common
with more fully developed pluralist views of organisation.
Other movements towards pluralist theory
Since the early 1960s an increasing number of social theorists have
concerned themselves with the development of theoretical
perspectives which are essentially pluralist in nature. The work of
Peter Blau ( 1964) on exchange theory, for example, provides a
Functionalist Organisation Theory 211
clear illustration of this. As will be apparent from our discussion in
Chapter4, Blau·s ‘Exchange and Power Model’ provides a theory
of social integration which is explicitly based upon the variables
which are central to pluralist theory. Following Simmel, Blau
focuses upon the emergent properties of human interaction and
attempts to account for the nature and patterns which exist within
society in terms of the process of exchange. Social exchange
geared to the satisfaction of different needs and interests is seen as
creating inequalities of power and as generating a host of cross-
cutting conflicts and oppositions which lie at the heart of changes
within society as a whole. Blau thus provides a processual theory
of social interaction which is firmly based upon pluralist principles
but which, as he recognises, allows for further development.49
Another step in the direction of a pluralist theory of organisation
has been taken by Michel Crozier( 1964). However, he approaches
the subject from a different direction. Whereas Blau has developed
his theory from an interactionist stance, Crozier’s theory repre-
sents a direct development in the mould of the theories of
bureaucratic dysfunctions discussed earlier. His analysis of the
bureaucratic character of two French administrative organisations
leads him to a theory of bureaucracy which identifies power as ‘the
new central problem of the theory of organisation’ (Crozier, 1964,
p. 145). His analysis traces the conflict of interests and the bargain-
ing process which characterise relationships between groups
within an organisation, particularly at different levels of the
organisational hierarchy. It demonstrates how the various groups
attempt to gain control of their work situations by drawing upon
the various sources of power at their disposal, and the way in
which this influences the organisation structure. In line with other
theorists in the pluralist tradition, Crozier sees the power struggle
within organisations as being limited by certain stabilising factors,
such as the need to maintain minimum standards of efficiency, and
other social factors which ensure that the organisation continues
as an ongoing concern. In the true tradition of conflict functional-
ism, therefore, contlict is seen as having its limits.
A third example of the move towards a pluralist perspective is
found in the work ofEtzioni (1961), whose comparative analysis of
organisations in terms of the ·nature of compliance’ focuses upon
the relationship between power and employee commitment. The
nature of compliance is viewed as being related to many other
organisational variables, such as the goals that organisations
pursue, the kind, location, power and interaction of elites, the level
of consensus attained, etc. Etzioni’s analysis has done much to
212 Sodolo~ical Parc~Ji~ms cmJ Or~tmi.wtional Analysis
draw attention to the role of power as a variable in organisational
analysis, but his treatment of the different ‘interests’ and ·con-
flicts’ within organisations falls well short of what a more fully
developed pluralist theory would require.
In the field of industrial relations pluralist-type theories have
become well established. The perspective is clearly evident, for
example, in the opening words of the Report of the Royal Com-
mission on Trade Unions and Employers’ Associations (1965-8;
Chairman, Lord Donovan), which describes the nature of the
business enterprise in the following terms:
The running of large businesses is in the hands of professional
managers … While in the long term shareholders, employees and
customers all stand to benefit if a concern flourishes, the immediate
interests of these groups often conflict. Directors and managers have to
balance these conflicting interests, and in practice they generally -.eek
to strike for whatever balance will best promote the welfare of the
enterprise as such.
This viewpoint is in line with an intellectual tradition which finds
expression in other literature in the industrial relations field such
as that of Clark Kerr and his colleagues ( 1964). Their view of
·pluralistic industrialism’ emphasises a movement towards a soci-
ety in which the state, organisations and employee associations
will be united through a web of rules which govern and settle
conflicts between interest groups. Others have built upon such a
perspective – notably Alan Fox ( 1966), who has been prominent in
advocating the pluralistic frame of reference as a means of under-
standing the nature of work organisations and. more recently ( 1973
and 1974), in emphasising its inherent weaknesses and
deficiencies. Within the context of the industrial relations field the
debate over pluralism has in many respects focused upon the
nature of power. Those advocating the pluralist perspective have
usually underwritten their views with the assumption that there is a
rough balance of power between the competing interest groups,
and that all groups are united in preserving the system as an
ongoing concern. It is also assumed that the survival needs ofthe
organisation, or those of society, impose limits on the degree and
nature of conflict.
A fifth line of development which moves in the direction of a
pluralist theory of organisations is witnessed in the increasing
number of research studies which have focused upon the study of
power as a variable in organisational analysis (for example, Kahn
Functionalist Organisation Theory 213
and Boulding, 1964; Zald, 1970, Hickson eta/., 1971). Most of
these studies are cast within the wider perspective of social system
theory but represent a temporary excursion outside the bounds of
the dominant model. As we have argued, power as a variable does
not figure prominently in functionalist systems theory, so the
fascination of these theorists with it can be seen as especially
significant. In many respects it can be understood as symptomatic
of a desire to forge a radical perspective within the context of the
functionalist paradigm akin to the movement towards conflict
functionalism described in Chapter 4. Organisation theory has
frequently attracted the charge of being conservative in orienta-
tion, unduly biased towards a managerial perspective and gener-
ally supportive of the status quo. A number of organisation
theorists who have wished to avoid this charge have directed their
attention to the study of power in organisational life. Yet other
theorists, more firmly committed to a managerial view, have
chosen to study power in the belief that an understanding of the
subject may facilitate better managerial control. Whatever the
reason, the result has been a series of studies in which power is the
focus of interest and its underlying definition essentially pluralist
in orientation.
A final trend in the direction of pluralist theory worthy of men-
tion here is found in the work of those theorists who have sought to
study decision making within organisations as an explicitly ·politi-
cal’ process. The recent study by Pettigrew ( 1973), for example, is
illustrative of this general trend and goes a long way towards
presenting a pluralist theory of decision making in which the rela-
tionships between interests, conflict and power are spell out in
some detail. In essence, it develops the elements of pluralism
which we have described as characterising the decision-making
theories of Herbert Simon and Cyert and March, taking them to
their logical conclusion. In Pettigrew’s theory man is accorded a
·political’ rather than an ‘administrative’ orientation, which is
consistent with the nature of the •political system’ within which he
operates.
Towards a clearer statement of pluralist
theory
In the previous sections we have sought to show how elements of
functionalist organisation theory converge upon various factors
214 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
which characterise a pluralist approach to the study of organisa-
tions. The movement to this position has been gradual and
piecemeal rather than the response to the various research findings
which have demonstrated that models based upon unitary assump-
tions are inadequate for an understanding of the dynamics of
modern organisations. We have thus arrived at a point at which
pluralist models of organisation have developed in advance of a
clear statement of the pluralist perspective as such, except in its
relationship to the unitary view.
The lack of a clear perspective is well illustrated in relation to
the way in which the concept of power is handled in pluralist-type
theories of organisation. Where it is recognised as a key variable,
the major concern is usually to locate its source and measure the
extent to which it exists. Relatively little attention is devoted to the
nature of power as such. Many theorists favour Dahl’s ( 1967)
conceptualisation of power, namely, that the power of a person A
over a person 8 lies in the ability of A to get 8 to do something that
he would not have done otherwise, and go hardly any further in
terms of an attempt to define the nature of the phenomenon under
investigation. Yet the problem of defining power seems to be a
crucial issue.
One ofthe few orthodoxies in the ‘What is power?’ debate is the
view that power refers to a ‘relationship’ rather than a ‘thing’. Ever
since the publication of Emerson’s influential paper, ‘Power-
Dependence Relations’ ( 1962), it has become fairly well
established that the concept ofpowerinevitably involves the ques-
tion: ·power over whom?’ However, this still leaves many issues
unresolved. Among the most important of these, we may cite the
following:
(a) Power or social control? Is it possible or meaningful to
identify power independently of a wider process of ongo-
ing social control? For example, processes of socialisation
have been shown to be important regulators of social
behaviour. Where does one draw the line between social
control and power? Is power utilised in the social control
of a child’s behaviour within the nuclear family? Is it
meaningful to equate this with the type of control
exercised by some form of elite through the mass media or
the control of workers through board-room decisions?
Wrong ( 1968) has suggested that it is necessary to restrict
the use of power to the intentional efforts of groups or
individuals to control others, and many pluralist theorists
FunL”Iionalist OrRalli.mtion Theory 215
follow his lead. However, the concept of social control
does undermine the utility of the notion of power. It shows
it to be at best a partial and incomplete conceptual tool for
the analysis of social affairs. The validity and utility of the
notion of power as a concept for organisational analysis is
thus worthy of much more detailed consideration and
attention than it has received up to now.
(b) /.f power ‘zero-sum’ or ‘non-zero-sum’? Assuming that
one accepts that it is valid to treat power as a variable in
organisational analysis, the question of whether it is
·zero-sum’ becomes an issue. Is power something which
benefits one group at the expense of another, or is it
something which can benefit everyone? Talcott Parsons
(1963) supports the latter view, arguing that power is a
resource generated by the social system in a manner akin
to the generation of wealth, and whilst some people may
have more of it than others, the use to which power is put
is of as much interest as its distribution. Giddens ( 1972a)
has referred to these as the ‘collective’ and ‘distributive’
aspects of power.
(c) Illegitimate or legitimate power? This distinction serves
to undermine the simplistic equation found in some work
that power equals coercion. Parsons (1963) has argued
that the use of open force is an indication of a shallow and
unstable power base. Where authority is pervasive, for
example, power (in a coercive sense) will not be in
evidence. Thus questioning of the relationship between
power and coercion immediately draws attention to the
distinction often made in the literature between authority
and power. The term ·power’ is often used simply to
characterise the non-legitimised use of power. A full
development of the concept of power must also concern
itself with the way in which it becomes legitimised in the
form of authority. Whilst organisation theory has paid
considerable attention to the notion of ·authority’, it has
paid relatively little to the concept of power in a wider
sense.
(d) Negative or po.fitive power? An important distinction can
be drawn between the notion of ‘positive power’ – the
ability to get things done – and ·negative power’ – the
ability to stop things being done. A focus upon negative
power is normally accompanied by an emphasis upon the
role of ‘veto groups’ in organisational life. A fully
216 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysi.f
developed conceptualisation of power must take account
of both positive and negative elements of power.
(e) Actual or potential power? Power does not have to be
exercised to be present. The distinction between actual
and potential power is fundamental at both theoretical and
methodological levels. Those who are concerned to
operationalise power often restrict their attention to the
visible use of objective manifestations of power. ignoring
essential background elements which, whilst extremely
potent in their effects, may be hidden from view. The
distinction which we have in mind here is clearly related to
Wrong’s (1968) view of power as an ‘episodic’ as opposed
to a “dispositional’ concept. The former refers to specific
behavioural events, whereas the latter refers to the way in
which situations are defined by the individuals concerned.
The distinction between actual and pot~ntial power is thus
very much influenced by the way in which the situation is
perceived by the actors involved.
(f) /ntercursive or integral power? Is power something which
is spread around? Or does it derive from one source or a
small number of sources? This distinction, which is again
found in Wrong’s discussion of power, is of crucial
relevance to the pluralist perspective. Pluralism is based
on the notion that power is intercursive and that no indi-
vidual or group dominates totally. It regards power as
deriving from many sources and as varying from situation
to situation and issue to issue. In other words, it assumes
that there are spheres of influence in which different indi-
viduals and groups have different degrees of power.
This brief and somewhat oversimplified overview of issues
relevant to a theory of power. serves to illustrate some of the major
problems facing pluralist organisation theory at the present time.
The foundations have simply not yet been fully explored. Pluralist
theory implicitly assumes that power is intercursive, and major
attention is devoted to an identification of relevant sources. The
classifactory scheme offered by French and Raven ( 1968), for
example, and the ‘strategic contingencies’ theory of power offered
by Hickson and his colleagues (1971), provide two prominent
examples of this endeavour. Their search for the bases of power
presumes answers to questions which they simply do not raise.
Future developments with regard to a pluralist theory of
organisation would thus seem to call for a much more systematic
Functionalist OrKanisation Theory 217
statement of the theory of power upon which it is based. so It also
calls for a much more systematic statement of the theory of
interests and the theory of conflict upon which it is founded. At the
present time assumptions with regard to these other two issues are
vague and underdeveloped. Interests tend to be equated with
individual. group or sub-unit goals; conflict tends to be seen as an
endemic but bounded and potentially constructive element of
organisational lire. These and other related assumptions are in
need of systematic elaboration, so that a systematic theory of the
relationships between interests, conflicts and power can be
developed.
Such an endeavour would lead to the consideration of some
major issues. A theory of interests, conflict and power at an
organisational level necessarily implies a theory of interests, con-
flict and power at a societal level. This focus would thus encourage
organisation theorists to form a clearer idea of the relationship
between organisations and society, within both a contemporary
and a historical context. It would bring them to a direct considera-
tion of the nature of the assumptions which define their location
within the functionalist paradigm as opposed to the radical
structuralist paradigm. As will become apparent from our dis-
cussion of radical structuralism in Chapters 10 and II. theorists
located there have also given consideration to a theory of interests,
conflict and power, and their stance is radically different from that
of the pluralist. At a sociological level, the confrontation of ideas
drawn from the work of Marx and Weber has produced a conflict
theory which offers a view of organisations substantially different
from those reviewed here within the context of the functionalist
paradigm.
So much, then, for our discussion of pluralist theory. Our review
of this perspective completes our analysis of contemporary
schools of thought located within the functionalist paradigm.
Clearly, they vary considerably in terms of general orientations
and underlying assumptions. In the concluding section of this
chapter we will examine briefly the way in which these differences
are reflected in terms of ongoing debate within the context of the
paradigm as a whole.
Debate Within the Functionalist Paradigm
Having completed our review of the different approaches to the
study of organisations characteristic of the functionalist paradigm.
218 SociolcJRica/ Paradigms and Orl(ani!wtional Antlly.’ii.’i
it will be useful by way of conclusion if we turn our attention to
examine some of the issues of debate within the paradigm. Anyone
familiar with the literature on organisational analysis cannot have
failed to notice the differences of opinion which exist between
members of different schools of functionalist thought. We intend
to argue here that much of this debate can be understood in terms
of the positions which its participants adopt in relation to the two
dimensions of our analytical scheme. Whilst they are committed to
the overall view of science and society which characterises the
paradigm, they differ in the degree and manner in which they
subscribe and address themselves to these common basic assump-
tions. It is these differences which underwrite the nature of the
debate.
We will take the dominant perspective within the paradigm,
social system theory and objectivism. as our starting point. Putting
aside for the moment debate concerning •levels of analysis’ (that
is, whether it is fruitful to focus upon individual: group, organisa-
tional or societal issues as topics of analysis), 5 1 we find that debate
within this perspective tends to focus upon points of detail. It is
usually •friendly’ and ·constructive’ in tone, and it focuses upon
the ways in which particular models can be refined and research
methods improved, and what the precise meaning and significance
of a particular set of empirical results might be. The debate is often
about the technical improvements which might be made within the
context of the perspective as a whole.
Criticisms that this dominant perspective is characterised by an
undue and extreme commitment to positivism and a na·ive empiric-
ism, and that it is characterised by a complete disregard for the
nature of the phenomena under investigation, tend to be of a
different order. Whilst such charges are often levelled from out-
side the paradigm by interpretive theorists or radical humanists,
they are also levelled within the paradigm by theorists who adhere
to a subjectivist position typical, for example, of the action frame
of reference. From the standpoint of action theory. the work of the
social system theorist and objectivist is dubious because it reflects
too strong a commitment to the models and methods of the natural
sciences as a basis for social analysis. These criticisms are often
founded on the charge that social system theorists and objectivists
•reify’ their subject of study.
The charge that social system theorists and objectivists are
overdeterministic in their view of human nature also arises from
the same source. The voluntarism which characterises the action
approach, for example, is often set in opposition to the technologi-
Functionalist Organisation Theory 219
cal or structural determinism characteristic of much of the theory
and research located in the more objectivist regions of the para-
digm.
Another charge levelled at social system theory and objectivism
is that it is ideologically biased in favour of a managerial view of
organisation. This charge has come from all directions. The action
theorists have claimed that the meanings which managers attribute
to organisations are given undue prominence and that the mean-
ings and orientations of other organisational actors are, relatively
speaking, ignored. The theorists who have focused upon
bureaucratic dysfunctions have stressed the non-managerial
interests which account for much of organisational activity. The
pluralists have criticised social system theorists for adopting a
unitary frame of reference and for ignoring the role of power as an
organisational variable. All in their various ways have contributed
to the view that social system theorists and objectivists are little
more than the handmaidens and functionaries of those in control of
organisational life.
For their part the social system theorists and objectivists are
often at a loss to understand the basis of such charges. They may
not be consciously aware of being managerially biased and may see
their overall endeavour as directed at increasing the effectiveness
of ‘the organisation’ or the satisfaction and productivity of the
work force in the interests of all. Such is the nature of the unitary
frame of reference which underwrites their approach. However,
the issue runs much deeper than this. Their conservative or
managerially orientated stance is rooted in the models which they
adopt for the purpose of analysis. We have already devoted con-
siderable space to a discussion of the assumptions which under-
write different approaches to the study of organisations, but it is
worth re-emphasising them here.
Social system theory and objectivist approaches to the study of
the organisations are built around the common-sense, ‘taken for
granted’ assumptions that organisations are purposive, goal-
seeking enterprises. The question ‘What is an organisation?’ is
rarely given very much attention; the answer is taken to be self-
evident. The problem of defining an organisation is usually tackled
in three or four lines, which form a convenient springboard for
moving on to the issues which are regarded as being of real con-
cern. Yet it is the question ‘What is an organisation?’ that should
lie at the heart of organisational analysis. Different paradigmatic
locations yield different answers to this question.
If a social theorist takes the definition of the phenomena which
220 Sodo/ogical Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
he is attempting to investigate as largely self-evident, it is also
likely that he will adopt a model for analysis which is similarly
unquestioned. It is hardly surprising, therefore, that the mechani-
cal and organismic models. particularly the latter. have proved
such popular analytical tools for the study of organisations. The
notion of equilibrium which characterises the mechanical analogy
is well suited for the study of organisations- which, by definition,
are tl.uumed to be relatively stable entities. The notions of func-
tional unity. homeostasis. adaptability and survival which
characterise the organismic analogy lend themselves well to the
study of organisations. if they are assumed to be rational.
purposive. goal-seeking, adaptive enterprises coping with the
demands of an environment. As we have argued in Chapter4, as a
result of the distinction drawn between ·cJosed’ and ·open’
systems, it has now become almost routine to view organisations
as ·open’ rather than ‘closed’ and to view the organismic analogy
as providing an appropriate basis for analysis. The adoption of an
open systems approach has been mistakenly regarded as
synonomous with the use of an organismic analogy. As a result the
use of organismic models for the study of organisations has been
regarded as being as self-evident and obvious as the common-
sense definition of the phenomenon which they are used to
analyse.
The upshot of our argument. therefore, is that the conservatism
or ideological and managerial bias which many theorists have
suggested characterises social system theory and objectivism is
built into the models which are used as a basis of analysis. For this
reason many theorists are not conscious of being biased one way or
another. This is nowhere better illustrated than in the work of
many socio-technical system theorists or human relations
theorists who, whilst attracting the charge of conservatism and
managerialism, actually see themselves as perhaps taking a ‘radi-
cal’ stand in favour of employees and their job satisfaction. What
they fail to realise is that their radicalism is constrained by the
nature of the models upon which their work is implicitly based.
Insofar as they adopt organismic models which presume a func-
tional unity of system parts, with certain imperative functions
which must be satisfied if the organisation is to survive, their
analyses are constrained by the requirements chacteristic of a
managerial point of view. It is this consonance between the nature
of the organismic analogy and the requirements of managerialism
which underwrites the dominance of organismic models within the
field of organisation theory.
Functionalist OrKanisation Theory 221
Notes and References
1. For an extended discussion of classical management theory.
see, for example, Massie ( 19655.
2. Taylor, hard, direct and abrasive in approach, soon became
embroiled in a battle with organised labour and was seen as
the arch-enemy of the working man. By 1912 his system of
scientific management had become the subject of a hearing
before a Special Committee of the House of Representatives.
3. For an overview of the early work and history of the
industrial psychology movement, see Rose (1975), pp.
6.5-100. For a discussion of some early research, see Mayo
(1933), pp. 1-54.
4. See, for example, Myers (1924).
5. See, for example, Schein (1970), pp. 55-76.
6. For a critical discussion of the human relations movement,
see Perrow ( 1972).
7. For a review of the research conducted, see Vroom (1964)
and Locke (197.5).
8. Part Ill of their book is devoted to this conceptual scheme
(1939, pp. 255-376).
9. As we have mentioned earlier, and will discuss further later
in this chapter, the model can be more accurately regarded as
the product of the Harvard School under Henderson and
Mayo. Mayo ( 1933) sets out some of the notions underlying
the model in a somewh~t crude and incomplete form.
Barnard ( 1938) also uses the notion of an equilibrating social
system, though his model is much more general in nature.
10. It is interesting to note that many early social researchers
were at pains to avoid attributing to social phenomena too
concrete a reality. See,forexample, Mayo(l933),pp. 33-4.
II. Roethlisberger and Dickson ( 1939), p. 272. Other significant
influences, in addition to those of Pareto and Durkheim,
included Freud, Piaget, Jung, Levy-Bruhl, Malinowski and
Radcliffe-Brown.
12. Roethlisberger and Dickson refer to Durkheim on only two
occasions in the whole of their work.
13. Many of the criticisms reviewed by Landsberger (19.58) are
launched from a pluralist perspective.
14. See, for example, the critique offered by Carey ( 1967). This is
subtitled ·A “Radical .. Critique’, but in addressing itself to
problems of methodology and interpretation of results op-
erates within the problematic set by the Hawthorne model.
222 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
15. For an overview see, for example, the following collections
of readings: Vroom and Deci (1970), Warr (1971), Davis and
Taylor ( 1972).
16. For a review of these, see Miner and Dachler (1973).
17. For a review of recent evidence, see, for example, Locke
(1975).
18. Most contemporary ‘expectancy’ models are based upon
that developed by Vroom (1964).
19. See. for example, Warner and Low ( 1947), especially pp.
66-89, and Homans (1950).
20. See, for example, Rice (1958 and 1963) and Trist et at. (1963).
21. The relationship between human and structural aspects of
organisation was also explored in a systematic fashion by
Merton, Selznick, Gouldner, Blau and others. Taking
their point of departure from the bureaucratic theory of
Max Weber. they sought to show how dysfunctions arise as a
result of the unanticipated responses of organisation mem-
bers. As will be apparent from our discussion of Mertonian
theory in Chapter 4, Merton’s and his colleagues’ study of
dysfunctions reflects a perspective which falls outside the
bounds of social system theory. We shall be considering this
important work in detail in a separate section later in this
chapter.
22. The non-rational or informal aspects of organisation are
given detailed attention in some of Selznick’s earlier works.
See, for example, Selznick (1943).
23. See, for example, Miller and Rice (1967).
24. See, for example, Rice’s discussion on the management of
change (Rice, 1958, pp. 248-54).
25. The notion of •appreciation’ is derived from the work of
Vickers (1966).
26. For a discussion of these terms, see Katz and Kahn (1965),
pp. 25-8.
27. Most open systems models for the study of organisations can
usually be expressed in terms of a series of assumptions
about ‘functional imperatives’. The apparent diversity of
such systems models usually disappears when they are
stripped down to the basic assumptions deriving from the use
of an organismic analogy.
28. In point offact, Woodward’s work also involved case studies
which incorporated the use of some interesting methodologi-
cal approaches. However, it is the hard quantitative results
of her survey which are given the most prominence in reports
Functionalist Organisation Theory 223
of the research and which have been most influential.
29. The references cited here are illustrative. The writers con-
cerned have produced a large number of publications in this
area.
30. It can be argued, for example, that in attempting to correlate
the technology and structure of organisations, researchers
are examining two aspects of the same variable – viz. the
method of control.
31. The notion of differentiation and integration of social
systems was utilised by Herbert Spencer, who, as we have
argued, was one of the earliest social theorists explicitly to
develop the implications of the biological analogy.
32. As we have already discussed, the general concerns of the
classical management school (structures) and those of the
human relations school (human and social factors) had
already been integrated within the context of a framework for
the study of organisations by both Simon and Selznick.
However, this synthesis did not reconcile the detailed pro-
positions with regard to what constituted ideal management
practice.
33. Administrative Science Quarterly contains numerous reports
on research testing various aspects of the Lawrence and
Lorsch model. See, for example, Osborn (1974).
34. Kast and Rosenweig ( 1973) present many good and relevant
ideas on the contingency approach in a book of readings
which brings together some of the well-known articles in this
area.
35. The utility of and reliance which can be placed upon these
studies is qualified later in this section in terms of the distinc-
tion which we draw between the importance of •process’ as
opposed to ·structure’.
36. The choice of these departments is arbitrary and an oversim-
plification. It is unlikely that a whole department – a struc-
tural manifestation of process – would comprise an element
on its own account. It is very easy to fall back upon structural
characteristics as a means of describing the differentiation of
an organisation, to the detriment of an overall systems view.
See below our qualifications on this point in our discussion of
the distinction between structure and process.
37. Even the research of Lawrence and Lorsch (1967) suffers
from this problem. They virtually ignore the processual
aspects of system and resort to hard quantitative measures of
structures and attitudes as a means of testing their scheme.
224 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
The methodology employed in this study is nowhere near as
sophisticated as the conceptual ideas which they present.
They equate subsystems with structural features within the
organisation: structure rather than system provides the start-
ing point for their analysis. The same problem is found in the
extension of the contingency approach presented in Lorsch
and Morse ( 1974); this study does little to advance the con-
cepts and methods presented in the earlier work. Insofar as it
is presented under the guise of systems theory as opposed to
determinism, the work of Pugh and Hickson (1976) and Hall
(1972) also stands as abstracted empiricism.
38. A similar point of view is presented in the work of Burns and
Stalker(l961), Rice(l963), Tristet a/. (1963) and Child (1972).
However, it could be argued that the choice available to the
strategic decision makers is, in fact, fairly restricted,
bounded by the structural constraints imposed by the envi-
ronment.
39. For an excellent presentation of some of the central features
of the work of Merton, Selznick. and Gouldner, see March
and Simon (1958), pp. 36-47.
40. The work of these writers diverges quite considerably after
the publication of these case studies on bureaucracy. We
have already referred to the way in which Selznick follows
the implications of a fairly traditional structural functionalist
approach to organisation. Peter Blau makes a specific break
with the case study as a method of organisational analysis in
favour of empirical studies of formal organisational struc-
tures, as referred to in an earlier section of this chapter. In
essence this line of development reflects an attempt to follow
Merton’s call for ‘middle-range’ activities linking theory to
research. We would argue that much ofBiau’s recent work in
this area represents a form of abstracted empiricism, in
which methods dominate theoretical perspectives. We also
referred in Chapte:- 4 to Blau’s theory of exchange and
power, which reflects another ‘middle-range’ investigation
characteristic of a different region of the functionalist para-
digm – that of interactionism. Blau’s work is thus charac-
teristic of a number of distinct areas. Blau presents a useful
outline on the development of his general research interests
in the introductory chapter of his book of essays On the
Nmure of Organi.o;ations ( 1974).
The work of Alvin Gouldner demonstrates the greatest
change of all. Since his early work on bureaucracy. Gouldner
Functionalist Organisation Theory 22.5
has ranged very considerably in general orientations. From
the cautious but potentially radical critique offunctionalism
presented in his ‘Reciprocity and Autonomy in Functional
Theory’ published in 1959, he has moved to what constitutes
an all-out attack upon the functionalist perspective. This is
most clearly illustrated in The Coming Crisis of Western
Sociolol(y (1970), which provides a somewhat rambling
·reflexive sociology’ characteristic of the general trend to
individualism and subjectivism in sociology during the 1960s.
It is a perspective which, whilst moving towards the view of a
radical humanist seems much more concerned to develop a
subjectivist attack upon functionalism than to focus upon a
sociology of radical change. This dimension is much more
evident in The Ditllectic of Ideology and Technology ( 1976).
41. See, for example, our discussion of radical organisation
theory in Chapter 11.
42. Schutz and Weber are discussed elsewhere in this text. The
work of Berger and Luckmann, The Social Construction of
Ret~lity (1966), presents a strange mixture of sociological
positivism and phenomenological sociology in the neo-
idealist mould. Their ideas have influenced many theorists
located in this area of the functionalist paradigm, including
David Silverman, whose work we shall be considering in a
later section.
43. See also. the collection of ethnographic accounts of work
presented in Fraser (1968).
44. As we argue below,the action frame of reference only figures
as an element in their overall work, which viewed in its
totality draws heavily upon much more objectivist
methodologies. We include it here as an example of the
action framework with considerable qualification and,
indeed, reservations. It is often cited as an example of the
action approach, but its links with the Weberian perspective
are at times very tenuous.
45. Silverman (1970), pp. 3-4. This view of the systems
approach implies that it is necessarily associated with the use
of a biological analogy. Whilst this is true in relation to the
majority of systems applications within the field of organisa-
tion theory, it is not a necessary characteristic of the systems
approach as such. Please see our discussion in Chapter 4 for
further elaboration of this point.
46. Silverman acknowledges the influence of the following
writers: Weber ( 1947), Schutz ( 1964), Berger and Luckmann
226 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
(1966), Berger and Pullberg (1966), Rose (1962), GotTman
(1959), Cicourel (1964) and Cohen (1968).
47. The distinction between ‘unitary’ and “pluralist’ frames of
reference has come into prominence through the work of Fox
(1966). It is also possible to introduce a third category – the
‘radical’ frame of reference (Fox, 1973, 1974a, 1974b). We
are excluding the radical perspective from our discussion
here because it belongs to a different intellectual tradition,
one characteristic of the radical structuralist paradigm. See
Chapter 11 for a discussion of this radical organisation
theory.
48. The view put forward in March and Simon ( 1958), for exam-
ple, is that whilst members of an organisation have different
goals and values, the major implication for a theory of
organisations is that they have to be motivated to produce
and to remain members of the organisation. Hence their
elaboration of the ‘inducement-contribution’ theory first
introduced by Barnard (1938).
49. For a review of some ofthese developments, see Chadwick-
Jones ( 1976) .
.SO. An extensive literature on the theory of power does already
exist upon which organisation theorists can draw. See, for
example, the wide range of articles in Olsen ( 1970) and the
discussion presented by Lukes (1974). Lukes’ distinction
between different views of power has much in common with
the distinction which we have drawn between the
functionalist and radical structuralist paradigms.
Sl. We will return to this in our concluding chapter.
6. Interpretive Sociology
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The interpretive paradigm embraces a wide range of philosophical
and sociological thought which shares the common characteristic
of attempting to understand and explain the social world primarily
from the point of view of the actors directly involved in the social
process. Its history is firmly rooted in the German idealist tradi-
tion, and in the view that the ultimate reality of the universe lies in
•spirit’ or •idea’ rather than in the data of sense perception. This
tradition, which runs counter to that of sociological positivism,
owes much to the work of Immanuel Kant (1724-1803), who was
one of the first philosophers to articulate its basic ontological and
epistemological foundations. Kant, whose philosophy is open to a
wide range of interpretations, posited that a priori knowledge must
precede any grasp or understanding of the sense data of empirical
experience. He argued that there must be inherent, in-born
organising principles within man’s consciousness by which any
and all sense data is structured, arranged and thus understood. A
priori knowledge was seen as independent of any external reality
and the sense data which it ·emits’; it was seen as the product of
·mind’ and the interpretive processes which go on within it. Whilst
the world in which men live may be the product of a complex
interrelationship between a priori knowledge and empirical reality,
for Kant the starting point for understanding this lay in the realm of
•mind’ and ‘intuition’. It is this basic, uncomplicated assumption
which underlies the whole of German idealism.
The development of idealism has, however, been far from
uniform. Subject to diverse influences ranging from the ·romantic’
writings of Goethe and Schiller to the somewhat dogmatic philoso-
phy of Hegel, its fortunes have been mixed. From a period of
ascendency in European thought during the later eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries, it was thereafter more or less forced
into a secondary place by the •practical’ achievements of sociolog-
ical positivism. However, by the end of the nineteenth century a
revivial of interest was underway, giving rise to the so-called
neo-idealist, or neo-Kantian movement.
228 Sodolo!(ical ParadiRms and OrRanisational Analysis
As H. Stuart Hughes has so clearly argued, the period
1890-1930 was a time of considerable intellectual ferment
characterised by a concern with the subjective aspects of scientific
enquiry. The major intellectual figures of the 1890s ‘were
obsessed, almost intoxicated, with a rediscovery of the non-
logical, the uncivilised, the inexplicable’ (H. S. Hughes, 1958, p.
35). This interest in the subjective and irrational was reflected in
the work of writers as widely diverse as Freud, Weber and
Husser!, each of whom responded in his own distinctive fashion.•
In addition to focusing attention upon the essentially complex and
problematic nature of human behaviour and experience, the work
of this generation of theorists returned to the basic problems of
epistemology identified by Kant, which confronted both the
natural and social sciences. The positivist position came to be seen
as increasingly unsatisfactory and problematic on at least two
counts. First, within the natural sciences (Naturwissenschaften) it
became clear that human values intruded upon the process of
scientific enquiry. It was evident that scientific method could no
longer be regarded as value-free; the frame of reference of the
scientific observer was increasingly seen as an active force which
determined the way in which scientific knowledge was obtained.
Within the realm of the cultural sciences (Geisteswissenschaften)
a second set of difficulties were also seen as arising, since their
subject matter was distinguished by its essentially spiritual charac-
ter. It was realised that man as an actor could not be studied
through the methods of the natural sciences, with their concern for
establishing general laws. In the cultural sphere, it was held, man
was ‘not subject to law in the physical sense, but was free. An
intellectual apprehension of his life and action could be attained
only by the speculative methods of philosophy, especially by a
process of the intuition of the total wholes (Gestalten) which it was
illegitimate to break down by “atomistic” analysis’ (Parsons,
1949, p. 475). As a result of this disenchantment with sociological
positivism, idealism assumed a new lease of life. In short, there
was a distinctive shift in the focus of intellectual attention along the
subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme, which
involved certain theorists in clarifying the intellectual foundations
of what we describe as the interpretive paradigm.
Among the theorists who have contributed to these intellectual
foundations, we identify Wilhelm Dilthey, Max Weber and
Edmund Husser) as having been particularly influential. In
fundamentally distinct ways they have done much to define the
character and issues which have commanded the attention of
Interpretive Sociology 229
interpretive sociology during the twentieth century.
Dilthey (1833-1911) and Weber (1864-1920) were particularly
concerned to bridge the gulf between idealism and positivism, or at
least place the cultural sciences upon a firm foundation in terms of
their ‘objective validity’. 2 If the cultural sciences were defined by
their spiritual character. then the ·spirit’ of a social situation or
type of institution was of key importance. This posed considerable
problems for social philosophers, who were concerned to provide
explanations of social and historical affairs without reverting to the
methods of positivism. The idealist process of’the intuition of total
wholes’ provided a means of organising the historical process but
got no closer to an understanding of it. It often resulted in an
entirely relativistic view of history as a series of unique and essen-
tially unconnected systems. Explanations in the idealist tradition,
it seemed, could only be provided through recourse to intuition or
metaphysics.l
Dilthey’s solution to the problem was found in the notion of
verstehen (understanding). In drawing a distinction between the
natural and cultural sciences, he maintained that the difference
between them was essentially one of substance, and that the two
types of science addressed themselves to fundamentally different
kinds ofsubject matter. Whereas the natural sciences investigated
external processes in a material world, the cultural sciences were
essentially concerned with the internal processes ofhuman minds.
Even though these processes may be translated into relatively
tangible cultural phenomena such as art, poetry, institutions and
the like, it was maintained that they could only be fully understood
in relation to the minds which created them and the inner experi-
ence which they reflected. Cultural phenomena were, in essence,
seen as the external manifestations of such inner experience and
hence, it was argued, could only be fully appreciated with this
reference point in view. In these situations the approach and the
methods of the natural sciences, with their emphasis upon the
search for general laws and causal explanations, were deemed
inappropriate. The cultural sciences needed a new analytical
method based on verstehen, through which the investigator could
seek to understand human beings, their inner minds and their
feelings, and the way these are expressed in their outward actions
and achievements. In short, the outward manifestations of human
life needed to be interpreted in terms oft he inner experience which
they reflected through the method of verstehen.
We wish to place emphasis here upon the word method since, as
conceptualised by Dilthey and later by Weber, this was its essen-
230 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
tial status. Verstehen was viewed as a method which could be used
in the cultural sciences to generate scientific knowledge of an
objectivity comparable with that obtained in the natural sciences.
The notion of verstehen provided a means of studying the world of
human affairs by reliving or re-enacting the experience of others.
As we shall see, Dilthey”i view ofverstehen has had an important,
direct and formative influence upon the hermeneutic school of
thought which we discuss later in this chapter. In more general
terms, his social philosophy had a marked but indirect influence
upon the development of many other elements of thought
characteristic of the interpretive paradigm. Indeed. the notion of
‘understanding’ in one form or another is a defining characteristic
of all theories located within this paradigm.
Despite Dilthey’s importance and underlying formative influ-
ence. it is through the work of Weber that the notion ofverstehen
as method has had the greatest impact on sociological thought. and
nowhere is the bridge-building exercise between idealism and
positivism more evident. 4 As Hughes ( 1958), Runciman ( 1972) and
others have suggested, Weber was fighting a war on at least two
fronts. He was dissatisfied with the superficialities which he
regarded as characterising positivist explanations of society, and
also greatly concerned with the subjective and ‘unscientific’
nature of idealist thought. His solution to the problem is found in
his methodological writings, in which he develops the view that
explanations of social affairs must be ·adequate on the level of
meaning’, and that the essential function of social science is to be
‘interpretive’, that is. to understand the subjective meaning of
social action. He defines sociology as ·a science which attempts
the interpretive understanding of social action in order thereby to
arrive at a causal explanation of its courses and effects … Action
is social insofar as, by virtue ofthe subjective meaning attached to
it by the acting individual (or individuals). it takes account of the
behaviour of others, and is thereby oriented in its course’ (Weber,
1947. p. 88). 5
This definition clearly reflects the attempted fusion of idealist
and positivist perspectives. He adheres to the positivists’ concern
for providing causal explanations of social phenomena but insists
that such explanations must be reduced to the level of the indi-
vidual. As Schutz notes, ‘Weber reduces all kinds of social rela-
tionships and structures, all cultural objectifications. all realms of
objective mind, to the most elementary forms of individual
behaviour’ (Schutz, 1967, p. 6). His view of sociology is thus one
which is concerned to provide causal explanations of social
Interpretive Sociology 231
phenomena whilst avoiding the pitfalls of reification. He is con-
cerned to build an objective science of sociology upon the founda-
tions of subjective meaning and individual action.
In this task Weber’s notion of the ‘ideal type’ plays a central
part. 6 Indeed, Weber insists that objectivity in the social sciences
is only made possible through the use of ideal types, which allow
for the ordering of elements of reality. Through the use of these
constructs Weber attempts to reconcile the method of verstehen
with the need to develop an objective social science. Ideal types
incorporate the ·spirit’ which characterises individual phenomena
into a wider generalised whole. In certain important respects,
therefore, the method ofverstehen is assimilated into a typological
scheme of analysis whit:h provides a means of ordering and
explaining human action.
Weber thus seeks to balance and reconcile the potentially
divergent perspectives of idealism and positivism. Whilst stressing
the importance of subjective meaning in explanations of social
affairs, he at the same time seeks to contain and limit the role of
these subjective factors. This is clearly evident, for example, in his
classification of behaviour into different types such as ·rationally
purposive’. ·rationally value-orientated’, ’emotional’ and ‘tradi-
tional’. Although the central task of his sociology is to understand
and interpret social action, he constrains this endeavour by the
implicit assumption that behaviour can be causally explained with
reference to fairly narrowly defined typologies of action.
Viewed critically. therefore, Weber’s stand with regard to
‘interpretive sociology’ can be seen as reflecting certain strains
and tensions. Interpretation and the notion of verstehen in
Weber’s hands acts as little more than a methodological tool for
overcoming obvious deficiencies in positivist method. Essentially,
Weber is interested in developing a causal theory of social explana-
tion rather than in pursuing the full implications of the idealist view
of the nature of social reality. As Schutz (1967) has observed,
Weber was most concerned with confronting concrete problems
and was interested in the more fundamental epistemological issues
only insofar as they had a contribution to make towards this end.
Weber can be seen as a ·sociologist of regulation •, in that one of
his central concerns was to provide a thorough-going analysis of
social order. In this the notion of rationality was accorded a central
role. Whether he can be more appropriately described as a
positivist rather than an idealist will no doubt continue to be
debated. 7 As far as the four strands of the subjective-objective
dimension of our analytical scheme rs concerned, he appears to
232 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
occupy an intermediate and somewhat incongruent position. In
terms of methodology, his interpretive perspective would suggest
a location on the boundary of the interpretive paradigm, along with
Dilthey’s hermeneutics. His position with regard to ontology,
epistemology and human nature would appear to be more
objectivist. For Weber, the objective reality of the social world is
not a central issue. It is the way in which it is interpreted by human
actors that is important. In this his position directly parallels the
theoretical perspective which we have described as behavioural
symbolic interaction within the context of the functionalist para-
digm. As we have suggested, theory and research based upon the
action frame of reference, which derives more or less directly from
Weber’s explorations in methodology, is most appropriately
located there, and it would seem that a similar case can be made in
relation to much of Weber’s other work.
What, then, is Weber·s significance as far as the interpretive
paradigm is concerned? We argue that it arises from his role as a
point of departure for other writers, notably Schutz, who have
taken Weber’s work as a base from which to develop a much more
subjectivist view of sociology. It will be apparent from our dis-
cussion later in the chapter that the notion of verstehen in other
hands has assumed a significance beyond that of mere method. As
Giddens has noted, from a phenomenological point of view •it is
the very ontological condition of human life in society as such’
(Giddens, 1976, p. 19). This ontological status of verstehen is
clearly evident, for example, in the work of Edmund Husserl, and
it will be helpful if we conclude our discussion of the origins and
intellectual traditions of the interpretive paradigm with a brief
review of his work. The extremely subjectivist position which he
adopts will also serve to illustrate the essentially intermediate
perspective reflected in Weber.
Edmund Husser) ( 1859-1938) is widely regarded as the founder
and leading exponent of the phenomenological movement in
philosophy. As will become apparent from our discussion later in
the chapter, it is not altogether a coherent movement and does not
lend itself to any simple and straightforward definition. Maurice
Natanson, one of phenomenology’s leading contemporary
spokesmen, offers the following characterisation:
Phenomenology is a presuppositionless philosophy which holds con-
sciousness to be the matrix. of all phenomena, considers phenomena to
be objects of intentional acts and treats them as essences, demands its
own method, concerns itself with prepredictative experience, offers
Interpretive Sociology 233
itself as the foundation of science, and comprises a philosophy of the
life world, a defence of Reason. and ultimately a critique of philosophy.
(Natanson, 1973b, p. 19)
Husserlian phenomenology is based upon a fundamental ques-
tioning of the common-sense, ‘taken for granted’ attitudes which
characterise everyday life and the realms of natural science. As
Natanson has suggested, ‘the central endeavour of phenomenol-
ogy is to transcend [what Husserl calls] the natural attitude of daily
life in order to render it an object for philosophical scrutiny and in
order to describe and account for its essential structure’
(Natanson, 1966, p. 3). The view that there is an objective external
world which exists in space and time and is real for all men is
subjected to thorough scrutiny. The presuppositions of science are
reduced to implicit metaphysical commitments. In the process the
external world is shown to be an artefact of consciousness;
phenomena are shown to be willed into existence through
intentional acts. Man is shown to live in a world created through
consciousness.
Husserl thus adopts an extremely subjectivist position in rela-
tion to the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme. Ontologically, the world constitutes a stream of con-
sciousness; it is experiential; the subjective is the source of all
objectivities. The task of epistemology is to explore and reveal the
essential types and structures of experience. Phenomenology
studies essences and clarifies the relationships between them; it
seeks to delve into experiences and clarify the very grounds of
knowledge. In this endeavour the methods of ‘direct intuition’ and
‘insight into essential structures’ are offered as the principal means
of penetrating the depths of consciousness and transcending the
world of everyday affairs in search of subjectivity in its pure form.
The procedure of epoche – whereby the phenomenologist
suspends his complicity and participation in the ‘natural attitude’
– also plays a central role. As Natanson puts it, ‘believing-in-the
world is the paradigm of normality. The philosopher’s task is not to
ridicule it but to understand it and point out its implications. Any
attempt lo examine such believing will be prejudiced, however, by
the philosopher’s own believing unless he finds a way to free
himself of the very attitude he seeks to elucidate’ (Natanson,
1973b, p. IS). Epoche, or suspended complicity, provides a
means of entering the realm of subjectivity which phenomenology
seeks to analyse and describe.
Compared with the philosophy of Husserl, Weber’s
234 SocioloKical ParadiKms mrd Orflanisational Am1lysis
‘interpretive sociology’ thus emerges as a very limited excursion
into the realm of the subjective. It is perhaps fair to say that it does
little more than attribute an element of voluntarism to the indi-
vidual’s interpretation of his world which more positivist theories
typical of the functionalist paradigm tend to deny, or at least
ignore.
Interestingly enough, Husser!, like Weber, began to articulate
his distinctive intellectual position as a result of his dissatisfaction
with conventional science. He began his academic career as a
mathematician and physicist but soon became concerned with
what he regarded as defects in their essential foundations.• He was
passionately committed to the ideal of a ‘rigorous science’ and
looked to philosophy and logic for answers to what he saw as the
fundamental problems. Disappointed with what he found, his
desire to penetrate to the sources of science led him to an increas-
ingly subjectivist position, and the conclusion that philosophy
required a phenomenological reorganisation which would •assist
even the objective scientist in the clarification and critique of his
unclarified fundamental concepts and assumptions’ (Spiegelberg,
1965, p. 79).
Like Weber, Husserl was highly dissatisfied with positivist sci-
ence, with its uncritical study of mere facts and its inability to cope
with problems of ultimate truth and validity. However, whilst
Weber concerned himself with the refinement of methodology and
addressed himself to what he saw as the fundamental problems of
social science, Husser! travelled in another direction. Addressing
himself to fundamental problems of ontology, epistemology and
methodology, he embarked upon an intellectual journey leading to
a radically subjectivist form of transcendental phenomenology.ln
so doing he laid the foundations for further exploration in the
highly subjectivist region of the interpretive paradigm.
The Structure of the Paradigm
Whilst its intellectual roots can be traced back to the work of the
early German idealists, the interpretive paradigm has been most
decisively shaped and influenced by the works of Dilthey, Husser!
and Weber. For the most part, therefore, it can be regarded as a
twentieth-century phenomenon.
Interpretive Sociology 235
We argue that the paradigm can be considered in terms of four
distinct but related categories of interpretive theory, distinguished
for the most part by their degree of ‘subjectivity’ in terms of the
four strands of the subjectiv~objective dimension of our analyti-
cal scheme. 9 We identify them as (a) solipsism; (b) phenomenol-
ogy; (c) phenomenological sociology; (d) hermeneutics. Their
location within the paradigm is illustrated in Figure 3.3.
The Hermeneutic school occupies the least subjectivist region of
the paradigm. Deriving largely from the work of Dilthey and the
notion ofverstehen, it first evolved as a method of study especially
adapted to an idealist view ofthe world. More recently, under the
influence of Gadamer, it has assumed a new dimension and has
developed in broader theoretical terms, particularly in relation to
the role and influence of language in social life. Its contemporary
importance within the context of the interpretive paradigm is
rapidly increasing, though up to now has been largely over-
shadowed by its use in critical theory within the context of the
radical humanist paradigm. We identify solipsism in the most
subjectivist region of the paradigm. It belongs to the realm of
metaphysics rather than sociology and is included here to highlight
the ultimate dilemma facing all philosophical and sociological
perspectives which emphasise the subjective in an extreme form.
Phenomenology occupies the middle ground of the paradigm.
We distinguish between the transcendental phenomenology of
Husserl and the existential phenomenology of Schutz. The latter
attempts to link themes drawn from the sociology of Weber and the
philosophy of Husserl.
aosely related to phenomenology, but distinct from it, we
identify two branches of sociological thought which combine the
phenomenological perspective with elements drawn from
elsewhere. Ethnomethodology fuses phenomenology and ele-
ments of ordinary language philosophy. particularly that typical of
the work of the later Wittgenstein and Winch. Phenomenological
symbolic interactionism interprets the work of G. H. Mead from a
phenomenological perspective, in the manner discussed in an
earlier chapter.
We will examine each broad category and school of thought in
tum.
Hermeneutics
Hermeneutics is concerned with interpreting and understanding
the products of the human mind which characterise the social and
236 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
cultural world. Ontologically, its proponents adopt an ‘objective
idealist’ view of the socio-cultural environment, seeing it as a
humanly constructed phenomenon. Human beings in the course of
life externalise the internal processes of their minds through the
creation of cultural artefacts which attain an objective character.
Institutions, works of art, literature, languages, religions and the
like are examples of this process of objectification. Such
objectifications of the human mind are the subject of study in
hermeneutics.
As we have already noted, it is largely through the work of
Dilthey that hermeneutics has achieved the status of a school of
thought within the context of contemporary social theory. 10 In
Dilthey’s hands it was essentially a methodology for studying the
objectifications of mind. It played a central role in his overall
scheme for generating objectively valid knowledge in the
Geisteswissenschaften through the method of verstehen.
Verstehen, we recall, was the means by which we comprehend the
meaning of a historical or social situation or cultural artefact. It
was a method of understanding based upon re-enactment. In order
to be comprehended, the subject of study needed to be relived in
the subjective life of the observer. Through this process, Dilthey
claimed, objective knowledge could be obtained.
Dilthey argued that one of the main avenues for verstehen was
through the study of empirical life assertions -institutions, histor-
ical situations, language, etc. – which reflected the inner life of
their creators. The study of these social creations was seen as the
main avenue to an understanding of the world of objective mind.
The method was that of hermeneutics. As he puts it,
Re-creating and re-living what is alien and past shows clearly how
understanding rests on special, personal inspiration. But, as this is a
significant and permanent condition of historical science, personal
inspiration becomes a technique which develops with the development
of historical consciousness. It is dependent on permanently fixed
expressions being available so that understanding can always return to
them. The methodical understanding of permanently fixed expressions
we call exegesis. As the life of the mind only finds its complete,
exhaustive and, therefore, objectively comprehensible expression in
language, exegesis culminates in the interpretation of the written
records of human existence. This method is the basis of philology.
The science of this method is hermeneutics. (Dilthey, 1976, p. 228)
Dilthey singled out hermeneutics as a key discipline and method
in the human sciences. He advocated that social phenomena of all
Interpretive Sociology 237
kinds should be analysed in detail, and interpreted as texts, to
reveal their essential meaning and significance. The method of
hermeneutics thus involved human scientists adopting the style of
literary analysts rather than natural scientists. Textual analysis of
meaning and significance was regarded as more appropriate than a
scientific search for knowledge of general laws. Oil they was con-
cerned that the basic rules of hermeneutics should be defined, so
that the insights of interpreters of rare genius could be utilised by
others.
Dilthey’s overall approach to hermeneutics is clearly illustrated
in the notion of the so-called ‘hermeneutic circle’. He recognised
that the social whole cannot be understood independently of its
parts, and vice versa. Words in a sentence have to be understood in
terms of their total context. Whilst one can attribute a particular
meaning to words on their own account, they may assume a
different meaning in the context of other words. So, too, with
social phenomena. Dilthey recognised that this part-whole rela-
tionship was characteristic of the social world and that a
systematic approach was necessary. The desire to formulate
methodical rules of interpretation, therefore, was accompanied by
a recognition that ‘there are no absolute starting points, no self-
evident, self-contained certainties on which we can build, because
we always find ourselves in the middle of complex situations which
we try to disentangle by making, then revising, provisional
assumptions’ (Rickman, 1976, p. II). In this way the methodolog-
ical rules of hermeneutics were seen to move in a circular and
iterative fashion towards an increased understanding of the
objectifications of mind.
In recent years the hermeneutic tradition has assumed a new line
of development particularly through the work of Gadamer
( 1965). 11 He argues that the circle of understanding, as envisaged,
for example, by Dilthey, is not a ‘methodological’ circle, but
describes an ontological structural element in understanding. Tak-
ing Heidegger’s description and existential account of the
hermeneutic circle as a point of departure, he argues that we
cannot relate, for example, to a historic tradition as if it existed as
an object apart from us, since there is an interplay between the
movement of tradition and the interpreter. In order to understand
social or cultural phenomena, the observer must enter into a
dialogue with the subject of study. As Giddens puts it,
Understanding a text from a historical period remote from our own, for
example, or from a culture very different from our own is, according to
238 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Gadamer. essentially a creative process in which the observer, through
penetrating an alien mode of existence. enriches his own self-
knowledge through acquiring knowledge of others. Ver:uehen consists,
not in placing oneself “inside” the subjective experience of a text’s
author, but in understanding literary art through grasping, to use
Wittgenstein’s term, the “form of life” which gives it meaning. (Gid-
dens, 1976, p. 56)
With Gada mer, verstehen is not so much concerned with ·re-
living’ or entering into the subjective experiences of others as it
was for Dilthey. It is more concerned with appreciating the
interchange of the frames of reference of the observer and the
observed.ln this process the role oflanguage is given a central role
•as the medium ofintersubjectivity and as the concrete expression
of “forms of life”, or what Gadamer calls traditions’ (Giddens,
1976, p. 56). Language is the mediator between frames of reference
or traditions, and is thus central to the process of understanding.
Extended and developed in this way, hermeneutics in
Gadamer’s hands becomes relevant to all areas of. enquiry: ·a
universal mode of philosophy’ and not just a methodological
foundation for the cultural sciences. The role of language assumes
ontological status and brings Gadamer’s view of hermeneutics
close to a phenomenological perspective. Language, for Gada mer,
is more than a system of symbols for labelling the external world; it
becomes an expression of the human mode of ‘being in the world’.
As Gadamer says, ‘Being is manifest in language’. 12
From the perspective of sociology as opposed to that of philoso-
phy, the hermeneutic school of thought has as yet received
relatively little attention within the context of the interpretive
paradigm. Its main impact has been upon the radical humanist
paradigm, where the insights of Gadamer have generated interest
in the role of language within the context of critical theory,
particularly as developed by Habermas.
Solipsism
Solipsism represents the most extreme form of subjective ideal-
ism, in that it denies that the world has any distinct independent
reality. For the solipsist, the world is the creation of his mind.
Interpretive Sociology 239
Ontologically, it has no existence beyond the sensations which he
perceives in his mind and body . 13
The solipsist view is most often associated with the work of the
Irish cleric Bishop Berkeley (1685-1753), though in point of
fact he did not adhere to such an extreme standpoint himself. 14
Berkeley questioned the common-sense belief that man is sur-
rounded by a world of external objects such as trees, mountains,
tables, streams, chairs, etc .• and suggested that they may be
merely the products of our perception. He argued that they may
have no distinct existence, being no more than our ideas. They
may exist only in our mind. What we mean when we say that a
thing exists is that it is perceived. An object may have no existence
beyond this ideal perception.
The solipsist perspective often attracts scorn and ridicule from
those who wish to continue to subscribe to a common-sense view
of an everyday world with a hard and fast external reality. How-
ever, Berkeley’s argument is often equal to the challenge and not
easily refuted. Boswell reports how Berkeley’s contemporary, Dr
Johnson, kicked a nearby stone saying, ‘I refute it thus’ (Boswell,
1953, p. 333). Dr Johnson’s experience, however, in Berkeley’s
terms, was reducible to the perception of pain and bodily sensa-
tions which Johnson may have located in his toe. The attempted
refutation was thus consistent with Berkeley’s thesis that the
world is no more than what we perceive it to be.•s
The solipsist position results in a complete relativism and scep-
ticism. Given that there is no external point of reference, knowl-
edge must be limited to what we as individuals experience. It is an
entirely individual and personal affair; there is nothing beyond
oneself and one’s ideas. The solipsist position is thus one which is
logically permissible but inward-looking and self-sustaining, and it
offers no scope for the development of a philosophy or social
theory which can be shared in any realistic sense.
We characterise solipsism as occupying the most subjectivist
region of the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme. The notions of regulation and radical change clearly have
no significance within a solipsist perspective; solipsism is thus
consistent with both the interpretive and radical humanist para-
digms. Its significance within the context of each is, for the most
part, a negative one, in that it presents a potential danger to social
theorists who wish to develop social theories with a subjective
emphasis. Subjectivist philosophic~ run the danger of being
grounded upon Sartre’s •reef of solipsism’, of entering an entirely
individualistic and subjectivist view of reality in which no mean-
240 Socioloxical Paradixms and Orxanisational Analysis
ingful discourse is possible. As we shall find in later discussion, the
‘reef of solipsism’ has been seen as a potential threat to a number of
social philosophers, notably Husser!.
In a more positive sense, in emphasising extreme sub_iectivism
solipsism defines the essentially intermediate and more moderate
status of other subjectivist philosophies. In adopting a completely
relativist position it illustrates the extent to which other views of
social reality and knowledge of the world are based essentially
upon shared meanings. It also highlights the equally extreme
nature of the common-sense notion of a world of hard-and-fast
objective reality.
Solipsism is thus located within the context of the interpretive
and radical humanist paradigm as a logically tenable position, but
one which is of little importance within the context of contempor-
ary sociology.
Phenomenology
As we have already noted, the phenomenological movement is not
altogether a coherent one, since it reflects a number of lines of
development. Taking the work ofHusserl as a point of departure, it
branches off in a number of directions according to the perspective
of its particular exponent. Writers such as Scheller, Heidegger,
Schutz, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty have all made significant and
distinctive contributions towards its overall development. 16
We will discuss phenomenology here under two broad headings.
First, we shall devote attention to what is known as ‘transcenden-
tal’ or ·pure’ phenomenology. which is most often associated with
the work ofHusserl. Second, we will consider a derivative of this,
‘existential’ phenomenology, particularly as reflected in the work
of Schutz.
Transcendental phenomenology
It will be recalled that Husser! was a mathematician and physicist
who. early in his career. became concerned with what he regarded
as the precarious foundations of logic and science. It was
characteristic of the man that he should decide to investigate the
sourceofthesefoundations.ln so doing he embarked upon a life’s
Interpretive SocioiORY 241
work, throughout which he was preoccupied by the problem of
foundations.
One of his earliest observations was that science was
characterised by ‘intentionality’. Despite the fact that the results
of science were always approximate and imperfect, the scientist
was guided by the intention of absolute objectivity. It was this aim
of science, this idea of science rather than its results, that was
important in distinguishing it as a discipline worthy of its name.
In his quest for the objective foundations of science, Husser!
attempted to open up a new direction in the analysis of conscious-
ness. Bringing a mathematical mind to the subject, he contented
himself with the manipulation of ideal essences. Rather than
bother with factual realities or the formulation of hypotheses, he
addressed himself to the central question of meaning. He put
reality aside (or in his term, •in brackets’) and sought to penetrate
to the level of the phenomenon. In other words, he sought to
practise phenomenology. As Thevenaz puts it.
Phenomenology is never an investigation of external or i’nternal facts.
On the contrary. it silences experience provisionally. leaves the ques-
tion of objective reality or of real content aside in order to turn its
attention solely and simply on the reality in consciousne.u, on the
objects insofar as they are intended by and in consciousness, in short
on what Husser! calls ideal essences. By this we must not understand
mere subjective representations (which would leave us on the plane of
psychology) nor ideal realitie.~ (which would ‘reify’ or hypostasise
unduly the data of consciousness and would put us on the level of
metaphysics), but precisely the ‘phenomena’ … The phenomenon
here is that which manifests itself immediately in consciousness: it is
grasped in an invitation that precedes any reflexion or any judgement.
It has only to be allowed to show itself, to manifest itself: the
phenomenon i.~ that whkh Rive.~ itu/f (Se/b.
pure and simple intentions (t·i.fee.v) of consciousness, as meanings, to
render them visible and manifest as such. In this We:ft’n.~dwu, the
es’>ence (We.ft’ll) is neither ideal reality nor psychological reality. but
ideal intention (l”i.\’ee), intentional object of consciousness. immanent
to cono;ciouo;ness. (Thevenaz, 1962, pp. 43-4)
Such is the nature of the phenomenon which Husser! sought. In
his quest for the source, for the foundations of logic and the
sciences and eventually the whole of philosophy, Husserl began to
242 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
develop his phenomenological analysis. In his search he quickly
realised that phenomenological analysis had to penetrate way
beyond superficial description of appearance or intuition. With
Husser!, knowledge, which in ordinary pre-philosophical thought
is the most natural thing in the world, assumes the status of a
·mystery’. The search was for the primary. absolute evidence
which, like the phenomenon, was complete. clearly established
and in need of nothing outside itself to give it form.
In this endeavour the method of epoche, to which we have
already referred, was to play a central role, opening the way for the
‘phenomenological reduction’ and the exploration of a new and
fundamental level of meaning – the transcendental field. In this
transcendental philosophy Husser! attempts to grasp ‘the world as
phenomenon’ – to grasp it not as an object. but as pure meaning.
The fundamental. original and essential purpose of the reduction is
to ‘bring to light [the) essential intentional contact between con-
sciousness and the world’ (Thevenaz, 1962, p. 47).
The phenomenological reduction thus leads to a conjunction
between pure consciousness and the world phenomenon. All the
assumptions of everyday life are brushed aside in the pursuit of
pure subjectivity, of transcendental consciousness, the intention-
ality of which is the source of all meaning. This notion of intention-
ality – the idea that consciousness always has an object that con-
stitutes it- plays a crucial role in Husserl’s philosophy. It denies
the possibility of there being an independent reality of any kind. At
the same time, reality is not constructed by consciousness; it is
revealed to it through the act of intentionality. This pursuit of
transcendental consciousness brought Husser! perilously close to
solipsism. As the external everyday world was swept away in
search of the transcendental, pure consciousness was left in splen-
did isolation, its intentionality the sole link with any semblance of a
wider reality. It occupied an isolated and self-contained realm of
its own. All else was a product of its intentional nature. Accord-
ingly, there was no external means of validating its existence. The
·reef of solipsism’ loomed near.
This was a problem which greatly concerned Husser! during his
later years, and he fought hard to find a way out of this solipsist
dilemma, particularly through the notion of’intersubjectivity’. He
sought ‘to show how the transcendental ego constitutes other egos
as equal partners in an intersubjective community, which in turn
forms the foundations for the ‘objective’ (that is, the intersub-
jective) world. His arguments in this direction were not altogether
convincing, given that the transcendental aspects of his
lnterpreth·e Sociology 243
philosophy were to be maintained intact, but, as we shall see, they
laid important foundations for the development of ‘existential
phenomenology’, particularly as developed by Shutz. Most of
Husserl’s followers were content to dwell on the lived-in world of
experience. 17 They were not prepared to follow the road to tran-
scendentalism and largely abandoned this aspect of Husserl’s
philosophy. As far as the interpretive paradigm is concerned, tran-
scendental phenomenology has been the subject of very little
further development. Occupying a position towards the sub-
jectivist extreme of the paradigm, its main significance has been as
a springboard, or at least a point of departure, for less subjectively
orientated brands of phenomenology. We will discuss the most
important of these in the next section.
Interestingly enough, Husserl’s transcendental notions have
been adopted to a certain extent by theorists operating within a
perspective characteristic of the radical humanist paradigm.
Transcendence, from their point of view, has been seen as indicat-
ing a potential for release from the bonds of everyday life. The
work of Sartre, in particular, reflects the direct influence of
Husser!, and we will return to a discussion of this in a later chapter.
Existential phenomenology
The existential wing of the phenomenological movement is most
often associated with the work of Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty,
Sartre and Schutz. They share a common concern for what
Husserl called the •Jife-world’ (Lebenswelt), for the world of
everyday experience as opposed to the realm of transcendental
consciousness. However, apart from this concern with the •Jife-
world’ and the way in which men exist within it, it is misleading to
view their work in similar terms. Each develops a theoretical
perspective which, whilst adhering to a roughly similar position in
terms of the various strands of the subjective-objective
dimension of our analytical scheme, addresses itself to quite
different issues and problems. 18 We will confine our discussion of
existential phenomenology here to the work of Schutz who, in his
attempt to develop a ·phenomenology of the social world’. brings
the subject down from the realm of philosophical discourse to
something approaching a sociological perspective.
The work of Alfred Schutz ( 1899-1959) can be characterised as
a sustained effort to relate the idea of phenomenology to the
problems of sociology. In essence, it seeks to link the perspectives
244 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analy:~is
of Weber and Husser!, drawing also upon the philosophy of
Bergson.
Schutz commences his classic work The Phenomenology of the
Social World, first published in 1932, by stating that it is based
upon an intensive concern of many years’ duration with the
theoretical writings of Max Weber. Whilst convinced that Weber’s
approach was correct and that it provided •a proper starting point
for the philosophy of the social sciences’, Schutz felt sure that it
‘did not go deeply enough to lay the foundations on which alone
many of the problems of the human sciences could be solved’
(1967, pp. xxxi).
Driving down to these foundations, in the manner of Husser!,
Schutz identified a number of ambiguities in Weber’s position and
subjected them to thorough philosophical analysis. While agree-
ing with Weber that the essential function of social science was to
be interpretive, that is, to understand the subjective meaning of
social action, he felt that Weber had failed to state the essential
characteristics of •understanding’ (verstehen), ·subjective mean-
ing’ and ·action’. For Schutz, a thorough-going analysis of these
concepts was essential in order to place the subject matter and
methods of the social sciences upon a firm basis.
Schutz embarks upon a phenomenological analysis of meaning,
searching for its origins in the ‘stream of consciousness’. This
notion, which he derives from Bergson, is crucial to his analysis,
since it introduces the temporal dimension which underlies the
concept of ·renexivity’. Schutz argues that consciousness is
fundamentally an unbroken stream of lived experiences which
have no meaning in themselves. Meaning is dependent upon
renexivity- the process of turning back on oneself and looking at
what has been going on. Meaning is attached to actions
retrospectively; only the already-experienced is meaningful, not
that which is in the process of being experienced.
Schutz also argues that this process of attributing meaning
renexively is dependent upon the actor’s identifying the purpose
or goal which he or she is supposedly seeking. This introduces
the notion of being able to attribute meaning. in advance, to future
experiences. The concept of meaningful action thus contains ele-
ments of both past and anticipated future; intrinsically it has a
temporal dimension. Schutz’s analysis of this ·constituting pro-
cess in internal time consciousness’ is a direct application of the
•phenomenological reduction’ as described by Husser!. The
natural attitude towards the ‘world-given-to-me-as-being-there’ is
suspended in the manner ofthe epoche, in an attempt to penetrate
Interpretive Sociolo~y 245
to the essence of consciousness and meaning. Whilst appropriate
for the above purpose. Schutz specifically recognises that the
analysis of meaning in everyday social life does not require the
transcendental knowledge yielded by the phenomenological
reduction. As he proceeds to the study of the social world. there-
fore, he abandons the strictly phenomenological method. He
accepts the existence of the social world as presented in the natural
attitude and focuses upon the problem of intersubjective under-
standing, ‘by-passing a whole nest of problems’ identified by
Husser! in relation to the issue of transcendental subjectivity and
intersubjectivity· (Schutz, 1967, p. 94).
Schutz’s analysis of intersubjectivity is thus principally
informed by a sociological as opposed to a phenomenological
perspective. It reflects a predilection for the ‘life-world’ as
opposed to that of transcendental philosophy. Basically, Schutz is
concerned to throw light upon the way in which we come to know
the lived experience of others. In this he makes a fundamental
distinction ‘between the genuine understandin~ of the other
person and the abstract conceptualisation of his actions or
thoughts as being of such and such a type’ (1967. pp. xxv). Genuine
understanding means the intentional grasping of the experience of
the other. in a manner akin to looking into the other’s stream of
consciousness. It reflects the true comprehension of subjective
meaning. The abstract conceptualisation does not refer so much to
understanding. as to ‘self-elucidation’; it is merely an ordering of
one’s own experience into categories. Genuine understanding is
possible in face-to-face ‘we-relations’; it depends upon direct
exchange and interaction. As we pass from these situations of
direct interaction to modes of indirect experience of others, we
have to resort to more and more abstract conceptualisation.
For Schutz, the process of understanding the conduct of others
can be understood as a process of typification. whereby the actor
applies interpretive constructs akin to ‘ideal types’ to apprehend
the meanings of what people do. These constructs are derived from
the experience of everyday life and the stock of knowledge or
common-sense understandings which comprise the natural
attitude. It is through the use of typifications that we classify and
organise our everyday reality. The typifications are learned
through our biographical situation. They are handed to us accord-
ing to our social context. Knowledge of everyday life is thus
socially ordered. The notion of typification or ideal type is thus not
a merely methodological device as envisaged by Weber, but an
inherent feature of our everyday world. 1″
246 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Schutz argues that the stock of knowledge which we use to
typify the actions of others and understand the world around us
varies from context to context. We live in a world of ·multiple
realities·. each of which is defined in terms of ‘finite provinces of
meaning·. The social actor shifts between these provinces of mean-
ing in the course of his everyday life. As he shifts from the world of
work to that of home and leisure or to the world of religious
experience, different ground rules are brought into play. Whilst it
is within the normal competence of the acting individual to shift
from one sphere to another, to do so calls for a ‘leap of conscious-
ness • to overcome the differences between the different worlds. 20
For Schutz, therefore, the problem of understanding the mean-
ing structure of the world of everyday life was a central concern.
‘To see this world in its massive complexity. to outline and explore
its essential features. and to trace out its manifold relationships
were the composite parts of his central task. the realization of a
philosophy of mundane reality. or. in more formal language, of a
phenomenology of the natural attitude’ (Schutz, 1962, p. xxv). The
central task of social science. according to Schutz. was to under-
stand the social world from the point of view of those living within
it, using constructs and explanations which are intelligible in terms
of the common-sense interpretation of everyday life. 21
Schutz thus attempts to link phenomenology and sociology in an
analysis of the world of everyday affairs. His attempt, whilst
generating many insights, is only partially successful. The sub-
stantive links with the transcendental philosophy of Husserl are at
times very tenuous. particularly with regard to the issue of
intersubjectivity. This notion is crucial to Schutz•s analysis, yet
extremely problematic within the context of transcendental
phenomenology, for reasons which we have already discussed.
The inner world of intentional consciousness and the outer
manifestations of the world of everyday life are at times uneasy
bedfellows. The phenomenological enterprise per se encounters
serious difficulties in attempting to deal with any reality outside the
individual’s consciousness, and Shutz’s work reflects this
dilemma.
Judged from the standpoint of his other major intellectual point
of departure – the theoretical work of Max Weber – Schutz’s
phenomenology of the social world must be considered a major
advance in social theory. In essence. Schutz pursues the ontologi-
cal assumptions implicit in Weber’s methodology and develops an
overall approach which reflects a consistent and coherent stance in
terms of the four strands of the subjective-objective dimension of
Interpretive Sociology 247
our analytical scheme. Schutz demonstrates that the notions of
subjective meaning, understanding and social action have much
wider ramifications than those reflected in Weber’s work. In com-
parison with Schutz, Weber’s location within the context of the
functionalist as opposed to the interpretive paradigm becomes
clearly evident.
Phenomenological Sociology
Both schools of thought identified in this category of interpretive
theory occupy a similar position in relation to the two dimensions
of our analytical scheme. We distinguish between them largely
because they have developed from parallel but somewhat different
phenomenological traditions. Ethnomethodology derives largely
from the phenomenology of Schutz, and phenomenological
symbolic interactionism from the work of G. H. Mead.
Ethnomethodology
Ethnomethodology is grounded in the detailed study of the world
of everyday life. Essentially, it seeks •to treat practical activities,
practical circumstances, and practical sociological reasoning as
topics of empirical study, and by paying to the most commonplace
activities of daily life the attention usually accorded extraordinary
events, seeks to learn about them as phenomena in their own right’
(Garfinkel. 1967, p. 1). It is concerned to learn about the ways in
which people order and make sense of their everyday activities and
the ways in which they make them ·accountable’ to others, in the
sense of being ·observable and reportable’. Interactions between
people in everyday life can be regarded as ongoing accomplish-
ments, in which those involved draw upon various assumptions,
conventions, practices and other types of resources available
within their situation to sustain and shape their encounters in
various ways. Ethnomethodology seeks to understand such
accomplishments in their own terms. It seeks to understand them
from within.
The term •ethnomethodology’ was invented by Harold
Garfinkel as a result of his work on a •jury project’ (Garfinkel,
1968). The proceedings of a jury had been bugged. It was
248 Soc:iological PaTlldit.:m.f and Orgturi.wtional Analysis
Garfinkel’s job to listen to the tapes, to talk to the jurors and to
consider the broad question ‘What makes them jurors?’ Garfinkel
and a colleague were interested in establishing ‘how the jurors
knew what they were doing in doing the work of jurors’. They
recognised that the jurors, in going about their work, were adopt-
ing various methods for making their activities as jurors account-
able to themselves and to others. They were engaged in a process
of ‘making sense’ of the practice of jury work. They were con-
cerned with such things as ‘adequate accounts’, ‘adequate descrip-
tion’ and ‘adequate evidence’. They sought to avoid being
‘common-sensical’, they sought to act in the manner that they
thought jurors should act. The term ‘ethnomethodology’ was
coined to characterise the jurors’ engagement in a methodology
relating to a specific area of common-sense knowledge. They were
engaged in a process which called upon them to use a specific set of
practices for making sense of a particular social a.ctivity. However.
ethnomethodology has come to mean many different things. As
Garfinkel ( 1968) has noted, ‘it has turned into a shibboleth’. and he
frankly disclaims any responsibility for what persons have come to
make of ethnomethodology. 22 Many would not accept Garfinkel’s
disclaimer. His writings are unnecessarily obscure and convoluted
and they stand in a somewhat paradoxical relationship to the fact
that ethnomethodology is concered with understanding the every-
day world of simple practical activities and the realm of common-
sense knowledge.
The work of ethnomethodologists is very much concerned with
identifying the ‘taken for granted’ assumptions which characterise
any social situation and the ways in which the members involved,
through the use of everyday practices, make their activities ·ration-
ally accountable’. In this analysis the notions of ‘indexicality’ and
·reflexivity’ play an important part. Everyday activities are seen
as being ordered and rationally explicable within the context in
which they occur. The way in which they are organised makes
use of expressions and activities which are shared and not
necessarily explicitly stated (indexicality): this depends upon the
capacity to look back on what has gone on before (reflexivity). The
social situation is viewed as a process of accountable action which
is sustained by the efforts of the participants; the participants are
seen as attempting to order their experience· so as to sustain the
everyday, common-sense suppositions which characterise the
routine of everyday life.
Following Douglas ( I970b), it is convenient to distinguish
between two types of ethnomethodologists, linguistic and situa-
Interpretive Sociolo(ly 249
tiona!. The linguistic ethnomethodologists (for example. Cicourel.
1972; Schegloff and Sacks. 1973) focus upon the use of language
and the ways in which conversations in everyday life are
structured. Their analysis makes much of the unstated, ‘taken for
granted’ meanings, the use of indexical expressions and the way in
which conversations convey much more than is actually said. The
situational ethnomethodologists (McHugh, 1968, for example)
cast their view over a wider range of social activity and seek to
understand the ways in which people negotiate the social contexts
in which they find themselves. They are concerned to understand
how people make sense of and order their environment. As part of
their method ethnomethodologists may consciously disrupt or
question the ‘taken for granted’ elements in everyday situations, in
order to reveal the underlying processes at work.
Ethnomethodology is thus firmly committed to an understand-
ing of the ‘life-world’. Garfinkel acknowledges an intellectual debt
to Husser!, Schutz and Parsons, and his work can perhaps be best
understood as a particular type of response to Schutz’~ concern for
analysing the natural attitude. As Giddens notes, Garfinkel
is concerned with how the ‘natural attitude’ is r’trli.~~d as a
phenomenon by actors in day to day life … This leads him away from
phenomenology. with its Cartesian emphasis upon the (essential or
existential) primacy of subjective experience. towards the study of
·situated actions· as ·publicly’ interpreted forms. It is not hard to see
that the direction of movement is toward Austin and toward the later
Wittgenstein. For the notion of illocutionary acts. or as Wittgenstein
says, ‘that the words are also deeds’. although serving descriptive
rather than philosophical ends. fits fairly closely with Garfinkel’s
preoccupations. (Giddens. 1976. p. 36)
Giddens makes much of the convergence of interest in
phenomenology and ordinary language philosophy (as expressed
in the work of the later Wittgenstein and his followers) upon the
everyday world, and we shall have more to say of this in the
concluding section of this chapter.
Garfinkel’s debt to Parsons is expressed through his concern for
the problem of social order. Ethnomethodology is clearly geared to
providing explanations of the ordered nature of the social world,
and it is largely for this reason that, along with phenomenologists
and symbolic interactionists, the ethnomethodologists have been
labelled the ·new conservatives’ in sociology (McNall and
Johnson, 1975). However, the ethnomethodological approach to
order differs significantly from that which characterises the Parso-
nian scheme and other schools of thought characteristic of the
250 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
functionalist paradigm. The concern is not to explain any ordered
structure or patterning of events or regularities in human
behaviour; rather. it is to provide an explanation of the way in
which individual actors appear to order their world through the use
of various ·accounting’ practices. The ethnomethodologists are
interested in the way in which actors make evident and persuade
each other that the events and activities in which they are involved
are coherent and consistent. They are interested in understanding
the methods which characterise this accounting process. From the
ethnomethodological point of view, ·order’ in human affairs does
not exist independently of the accounting practices employed in its
discovery. 23
Many ethnomethodologists resist very strongly any attempt to
link their work with the conventional problems and concerns of
academic sociology. For them. every man is his own sociologist,
committed to an understanding of his everyday life. In this connec-
tion, Garfinkel draws the distinction between •Jay’ and •pro-
fessional’ sociologists, the activities of both being open to
ethnomethodological analysis. The sociology of the professional,
like that of his lay equivalent, can be regarded as a particular type
of accounting practice. As Giddens puts it, ·social science is a
practical accomplishment like any other rationally accountable
form of social activity, and can be studied as such· (Giddens, 1976,
p. 39). Many ethnomethodologists specifically dissociate
themselves from orthodox sociology as such. particularly from its
orientation towards “constructive analysis’, and confine their
efforts to studying the indexicality of everyday accounts and the
ways in which they are made rationally accountable.
The substance of ethnomethodology thus largely comprises a set
of specific techniques and approaches to be used in the study of
what Garfinkel has described as the ·awesome indexicality’ of
everyday life. It is geared to empirical study. and the stress which
its practitioners place upon the uniqueness of the situations
encountered projects an essentially relativist stance. A commit·
ment to the development of methodology and field-work has
occupied first place in the interests of its adherents. so that related
issues of ontology, epistemology and human nature have received
less attention than they perhaps deserve.
Phenomenological symbolic interactionism
It will be recalled from our discussion in Chapter 4 that it is
possible to distinguish two strains of symbolic interactionism –
Interpretive Sociology lSI
behavioural and phenomenological. The latter is typified by its
emphasis upon the emergent properties of interaction, through
which individuals create their social world rather than merely
reacting to it. Meaning is attributed to the environment, not
derived from and imposed upon individual actors; action is built up
instead of being a response or mere release mechanism. Both
groups of interactionists normally acknowledge their principal
intellectual debt to the work of G. H. Mead, though, as we have
argued, they tend to interpret this in fundamentally different ways.
The differences between the phenomenological and the
behavioural interactionists is not always as clear as it might be,
since the former have often been attracted by positivist research
methods which go against their basic theoretical orientation. As
Douglas has noted, •the general problem of the interactionist tradi-
tion of thought and research in sociology is that its practitioners
have rarely seen clearly and consistently the fundamental theoret-
ical and methodological differences between a positivistic
(absolutist) sociology and a phenomenological or existential
sociology’ (Douglas, 1970, p. 18).
This confusion is also reflected in the debate over whether there
can be a genuine synthesis between symbolic interactionism and
ethnomethodology. Norman Denzin, a prominent symbolic
interactionist, has argued that a synthesis is possible; Don
Zimmerman and Lawrence Wieder, two prominent
ethnomethodologists, have argued that it is not. 24 Interpreting
interactionism from a phenomenological rather than a behavioural
perspective, Denzin’s case rests largely on the view that both
symbolic interactionism and ethnomethodology cover largely the
same ground. As he puts it,
symbolic interactionism encompasses a large number of the problems
and peculiarities now taken as the special province of ethnomethodol-
ogy – namely, that the study of human conduct, within any type eX
social order, demands consideration of how interacting selves co-
operate in the construction of a routine, and for the moment a taken-
for-granted set of meanings necessary for joint action For the
interactionist any social order emerges through the process of interac-
tion in a situation where selves take the point of view of one another.
The foundation of such orders is to be found in the meaning interacting
selves bring to the objects and acts at hand. ·Meaning arises out of
interaction, and not the other way around. The task of the interactionist
is to discover how interacting selves come to agree upon certain mean-
ings and definitions for co-ordinated action. The central role of the self
in shaping such definitions is of paramount importance. • • It is
2.52 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
necessary to note only that such a conception of the interaction process
demands a special view of empirical research … a cardinal feature of
interactionist research is the casting of the researcher’s self into the
position of those he is studying. (Douglas, 1970, pp. 295-6)
The ethnomethodologists claim that one of the primary ways in
which they differ from this standpoint is that they have a funda-
mentally different view of the problem of social order and its
analysis. Zimmerman and Wieder claim that whilst the interaction-
ist treats the point of view of the actor as only one aspect of the
problem of order, seeking to relate it to a wider context in terms of
scientifically valid description and explanations, the
ethnomethodologist limits his activities to the actor’s world. He is
not very interested in going beyond this. As they put it, ‘the
ethnomethodologist is not concerned with providing causal
explanations of observably regular, patterned, repetitive actions
by some kind of analysis of the actor’s point of view. He is
concerned with how members of society go about the task of
seeing ,describing, and explaining order in the world in which they
live’ (Douglas, 1970, pp. 287-9). The ethnomethodologist sees
himself as being much more fully committed to the perspective of
the actor than the interactionist is – there is a much greater
commitment to studying the actor on his own ground. Denzin
disputes that there is any radical difference between the two
approaches on this point and the debate remains inconclusive.
For our purposes here it would seem that the similarities
between the two approaches are of the utmost importance, since
they clearly define the way in which both ethnomethodology and
phenomenological symbolic interactionism differ from other
schools of thought. Both follow the phenomenological tradition of
attributing to social reality a very precarious ontological status. It
is recognised that social reality comprises little more than a com-
plex set of typifications which may be intersubjectively shared.
The notion of the ‘ideal type’, which in Weber’s approach to
interpretive sociology is offered merely as a methodological tool,
assumes ontological status within the context of phenomenologi-
cal sociology. Phenomenological sociologists recognise that social
reality is created and sustained through the use of typifications or
‘ideal types’, as individuals attempt to order and ·make sense’ of
the world in which they live. Linguistic ethnomethodologists
attempt to focus upon this by understanding the way in which
‘accounting practices’ develop, and they emphasise language as
the central medium through which people see and create their
Interpretive Sociology 253
social world and through which intersubjectively shared meanings
may arise. The ·situational ethnomethodologists’, like the
phenomenological symbolic interactionists, are more concerned
to study the way in which social reality reflects a precarious
balance of intersubjectively shared meanings, which are con-
tinually negotiated, sustained and changed through the everyday
interaction of individual human beings. Social reality is for them
either reaffirmed or created afresh in every social encounter.
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
Theorists of all schools of thought within the interpretive paradigm
tend to share a common perspective, in that their primary concern
is to understand the subjective experience of individuals. Their
theories are constructed from the standpoint of the individual actor
as opposed to the observer of action; they view social reality as an
emergent process – as an extension of human consciousness and
subjective experience. Insofar as a wider social env.ironment is
accorded ontological status, it is regarded as the creation and
extension of the subjective experience of the individuals involved.
Ontologically, theories characteristic of the interpretive paradigm
are indisputably nominalist; with regard to human nature, they are
essentially voluntarist.
All theories constructed in the context of the interpretive para-
digm are anti-positivist. They reject the view that the world of
human affairs can be studied in the manner ofthe natural sciences.
In the context of the interpretive paradigm the central endeavour is
to understand the subjective world of human experience. To retain
the integrity of the phenomena under investigation, an attempt is
made to get inside and to understand from within. The imposition
of external form and structure is resisted, since this reflects the
viewpoint of the observer as opposed to that of the actor directly
involved. Ideographic rather than nomothetic methods of study
are favoured from this point of view.
In these respects theories characteristic of the interpretive para-
digm are significantly different from those of the functionalist
paradigm. Though certain theorists within the latter have
attempted to incorporate ideas and insight5 from the former,
particularly in terms of method (for example, Weber and his use of
the notion ofverstehen), the two types of theory remain fundamen-
tally distinct. The ontological assumptions of a truly interpretive
theory do not permit a functionalist perspective; the two types of
254 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
theories are based upon fundamentally different assumptions with
regard to the ontological status of the social world.
At the same time there are points of similarity between
interpretive and functionalist theories – similarities which become
clearly evident when these theories are compared with their
counterparts in the radical humanist and radical”structuralist para-
digms. Interpretive and functionalist theories reflect a common
concern for the sociology of regulation. By and large, interpretive
theories concentrate on the study of ways in which social reality is
meaningfully constructed and ordered from the point of view of the
actors directly involved. They present a perspective in which indi-
vidual actors negotiate, regulate and live their lives within the
context of the status quo. The fact that interpretive theories are
cast in the mould of the sociology of regulation reflects the frame of
reference of their proponents rather than basic ontological and
methodological assumptions. As will be seen in Chapter 8,
hermeneutics in the hands of Habermas and phenomenology in the
hands of Sartre are directed towards quite different ends within the
context of a socioiQJlY of radical chanJte.
If one were required to draw a single li11e of division between the
theories located within the context of the interpretive paradigm,
perhaps the most significant would be that between the highly
subjectivist orientation of solipsism and transcendental
phenomenology on the one hand and existential phenomenology,
phenomenological sociology and hermeneutics on the other.
Whereas the former embark upon a journey into the realm of pure
subjectivity and remain within the bounds of purely philosophical
discourse, the latter are more concerned with the ‘life-world’ and
are amenable to study from a more sociological perspective.
Within the context of the latter it is worth noting a convergence of
interest upon the role of language as a medium of practical social
activity. Existential phenomenology. ethnomethodology and
hermeneutics have features in common with the theory oflanguage
as developed in the work of the later Wittgenstein (1963) and his
followers. 25 All of these areas of analysis emphasise the
importance of meaning in context. As Wittgenstein puts it, •an
expression only has meaning in the flow of life. ‘In language, as in
other areas of social activity, the process of communication is an
ongoing accomplishment characterised by indexicality and
reflexivity. All human activity takes much for granted, and what
constitutes reality depends upon the rules which underlie what
Wittgenstein calls ‘forms of life’.
These notions have fundamental implications for our view of
Interpretive Sociology 255
science, since it follows that what poses as science is no more than
a particular form of life or language game. Science is based on
‘taken for granted’ assumptions, and thus, like any other social
practice, must be understood within a specific context. Traced to
their source, all activities which pose as science can be traced to
fundamental assumptions relating to everyday life and can in no
way be regarded as generating knowledge with an ‘objective’,
value-free status, as is sometimes claimed. What passes for sci-
entific knowledge can be shown to be founded upon a set of
unstated conventions, beliefs and assumptions, just as everyday,
common-sense knowledge is. The difference between them lies
largely in the nature of the rules and the community which
recognises and subscribes to them. The knowledge in both cases is
not so much ‘objective’ as shared.
This view has close parallels with the view of science articulated
by Kuhn ( 1970) and the notion of paradigm. In essence, his work
represents a theoretical perspective characteristic of the
interpretive paradigm – a theory in the tradition of Schutz’s
analysis of multiple realities and Wittgenstein’s ‘forms of life’.
Scientific knowledge here is in essence socially constructed and
socially sustained; its significance and meaning can only be under-
stood within its immediate social context.
This view of science is explicitly recognised in the work of
phenomenologists and ethnomethodologists operating within the
interpretive paradigm. It explains in large measure their
indifference to the functionalist and radical structuralist para-
digms, or the deep-seated scepticism with which they view the
work of theorists operating within these contexts, and their
vigorous efforts to construct social theories based upon a
fundamentally different view of the role and nature of science.
Notes and References
I. Hughes identifies the generation of writers influential during
the period 1890-1930 as follows: Freud (born 1856), Durk-
heim ( 1858), Mosca ( 1858), Bergson ( 1859), Meinecke ( 1862),
Weber ( 1864), Troeltsch ( 1865), Croce ( 1866), Benda ( 1867),
Pirandello (1867), Alain (1868), Gide (1869), Proust (1871),
Peguy ( 1873), Jung ( 1875), Mann ( 1875), Michels ( 1876),
Hesse ( 1877).
To this list he adds Dilthey (1833), Gramsci (1891),
Spengler ( 1880), Wittgenstein ( 1889) and Mannheim ( 1893).
256 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
He could well have added Simmel (1858) and Husserl ( 1859),
who were also very much influenced by the German idealist
tradition.
The responses of these writers to the problem of the ‘sub-
jective’ has indeed been diverse. Durkheim, for example,
found a solution consistent with a functional orientation;
Sorel veered in the direction of Marxism and Freud into the
realm of psychoanalysis. As Hughes notes, most of these
theorists concerned themselves ‘with the irrational only to
exorcise it. By probing into it they sought ways to tame it, to
canalise it for constructive human purposes’ (Hughes, 1958,
p. 36). For the most part they addressed the irrational from a
standpoint characteristic of the sociology of regulation.
2. The contribution to the development of modern Western
philosophy and social theory made by Wilhelm Dilthey is
coming increasingly to be seen as of importance. He has
made a considerable contribution to basic issues of epis-
temology and methodology, and his work has had a signifi-
cant influence upon social theorists such as Weber, Husser!,
Heidegger and others. The similarities between the
methodological contributions of Dilthey and Weber are
particularly striking. Unfortunately, the major part of
Dilthey’s work is still not available in English. For a sample
of what is available so far, see Rickman ( 1976).
Dilthey was concerned to explore the epistemological
problems of the cultural sciences, particularly history, and
devise ways of generating objective knowledge that would
meet the traditional requirements of science. For a clear
discussion of his attempt, see Tuttle (1969). For a general
discussion of his work and influence, see Hodges ( 1952) and
Makkreel ( 1975).
3. For a further discussion of some of these issues, see Parsons
( 1949), vol. II, pp. 473-87 and Hughes ( 1958), pp. 183-200.
4. Weber’s principal works on methodology can be found in
Weber ( 1949).
S. To this definition it may well be useful to add a further
comment on Weber’s view of ‘action’: ‘In “action” is
included human behaviour when and insofar as the acting
individual attaches a subjective meaning to it. Action in this
sense may be either overt or purely inward or subjective; it
may consist of positive intervention in a situation, or if delib-
erately refraining from such intervention, or passively
acquiescing in the situation’ (Weber, 1947, p. 88).
Interpretive SocioiORY 2S1
6. Hughes conveniently summarises the essential characteris-
tics of the ‘ideal type’ construct in the following terms:
An ideal type is formed by the one-sided accentuation of one or
more points of view and by the synthesis of a great many diffuse,
discrete, more or less present and occasionally absent t.·om·rete
individual phenomena, which are arranged according to those
one-sidedly emphasised viewpoints into a unifiedanalytical con-
struct. In its conceptual purity, this mental construct cannot be
found empirically anywhere in reality. It is a utopia …
It has the significance of a purely ideallimitinl( concept with
which the real situation or action is compared and surveyed for
the explication of certain of its significant components. Such
concepts are constructs in terms of which we formulate relation-
ships by the application of the category of objective possibility.
By means of this category, the adequacy of our imagination,
orientated and disciplined by reality, is judged. (Hughes, 1958, p.
312)
The notion of an ‘ideal type’ thus represents a heuristic
which can be used as a means of analysis in many realms of
scientific enquiry. Concepts such as bureaucracy, economic
man and capitalism are examples of ‘ideal types’ – useful
fictions against which the real world can be compared.
7. For a perspective on some of the issues involved here, see
Runciman (1972), pp. 16-19 and Gerth and Mills (1948), pp.
S5-61.
8. For a full discu~sion of the life and work of Husserl, see
Natanson (1973b) and Spiegelberg (1965), vol. I, pp.
73-167.
Spiegelberg’s analysis indicates quite clearly how
Husserl’s thought progresses in successive stages to an
increasingly subjectivist position. Only after 1906 does
Husserl’s philosophy become that of a pure phenomen-
ologist.
9. We have chosen to present the interpretive paradigm in terms
offour broad categories of theory to reflect the key divisions
from a sociological perspective. since this is what is central
to our present task. At a philosophical level, it would perhaps
be more appropriate to characterise it in·terms of three broad
categories, solipsism, subjective idealism (comprising
phenomenology and phenomenological sociology) and
objective idealism (comprising hermeneutics). These three
categories of philosophical thought are discussed in the text.
2S8 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
10. For an analysis of the hermeneutic tradition, see, for exam-
ple, Palmer (1969).
11. Unfortunately, most of Gada mer’s work is not yet available
in English. For a useful discussion of his work, see Giddens
(1976).
12. Quoted in Giddens ( 1976), p. 57. As Giddens notes, there are
remarkable parallels between Gadamer’s hermeneutics and
post- Wittgensteinian philosophy as developed by Winch in
The Idea of a Social Science ( 1958). Both lines of enquiry,
which appear to have developed independently of each
other, arrive at similar views on the nature and significance of
language in social life (Giddens, 1976, pp. 54-5).
13. For a comprehensive discussion of the phenomenological
basis of solipsism and its variations, see Todd ( 1968).
14. Berkeley’s own position can perhaps be more accurately
described as that of an ‘immaterialist’ rather than a solipsist.
He did not deny that there was an external world; he asserted
that everything is relative to mind; see Berkeley ( 1962) (this
work was originally published in the early eighteenth
century).
15. In a similar vein of levity, it is also said that Berkeley, on a
visit to the house of Dean Swift, was left standing on the
doorstep on the pretext that if immaterialism was a tenable
position, he would be able to walk through the door without
its being opened for him.
16. For a full discussion of the phenomenological movement,
including an analysis of the intellectual debt of Husser! to his
teacher, Franz Bretano, and fellow pupil. Carl Stumpf. see
Spiegelberg (1965), vols I and II. The essay by Thevenaz
(1962) presents a very clear account of the development of
the central notions. See also Husserl’s own account of
phenomenology in the Encyc/optzdia Britannica, 14th ed.
(1929).
17. In his later writings Husser! also devoted increased attention
to the idea of the Lebenswelt (‘life-world’), in the hope that it
would throw light on intentionality in action. This notion was
taken up by Husserl’s followers, in line with their increased
interest in the lived-in world as opposed to the transcenden-
tal. We shall have more to say of this in the next section.
18. Heidegger interested himself primarily in the meaning of
‘being’. He saw in phenomenology a means of establishing
the categories of human existence for a ‘fundamental ontol-
ogy’. Towards this end he developed a ‘hermeneutic
Interpretive Sociology 259
phenomenology’ designed to interpret the ontological mean-
ings of various human conditions (being in the world, anxi-
ety, etc.).
For a comprehensive discussion ofHeidegger’s version of
phenomenology, see Spiegelberg (1965), pp. 271-357 and
Thevenaz (1962), pp. 53-67.
Merleau-Ponty has played a key role in the development of
the phenomenological movement in France. For a discussion
of his work, see Spiegelberg (1965), pp. 516-62. The work of
Sartre will be discussed in Chapter 8.
19. For a full discussion of the role of typification in Schutz’s
analysis, see Schutz (1964), part I.
20. For a full discussion of multiple realities, see Schutz (1967),
pp. 207-59.
21. For an overall perspective on Schutz’s methodology, see
Schutz (1967), pp. 3-47.
22. As will be clear from our discussion below,
ethnomethodology has developed in a number of directions.
For some useful reviews of the subject as a whole, see
Douglas (1970b), Dreitzel (1970), Filmer et al (1972) and
Giddens (1976).
23. For a discussion of an ethnomethodologist’s view of the
problem of order. see the article by Zimmerman and Wieder
in Douglas ( 1970b). pp. 286-95.
24. The debate is presented in Douglas (1970b). pp. 259-84,
285-98; see also Meltzer el al. (1975).
25. It is important to note that the work of the early and later
Wittgenstein is based upon fundamentally different ontologi-
cal assumptions. Although we are unable to consider this at
length here, it is interesting to note that Wittgenstein’s early
philosophy reflects assumptions consistent with the
functionalist paradigm; the later philosophy reflects the
assumptions of the interpretive paradigm. Wittgenstein.like
a number of other social philosophers discussed here (for
example, G. H. Mead, Husser!, Marx), embarked during his
lifetime upon an intellectual journey which involved a change
in basic paradigm.
7. The Interpretive Paradigm
and the Study of Organisations
As will be clear from our discussion in the previous chapter, the
intellectual history of the interpretive paradigm is as complex and
conceptually as rich as that of the functionalist paradigm. The
underlying assumptions of the interpretive paradigm with regard to
the ontological status of the social world reject the utility of con-
structing a social science which focuses upon the analysis of
·structures’ .It rejects any view which attributes to the social world
a reality which is independent of the minds of men. It-emphasises
that the social world is no more than the subjective construction of
individual human beings who, through the development and use of
common language and the interactions of everyday life, may create
and sustain a social world of intersubjectively shared meaning.
The social world is thus of an essentially intangible nature and is in
a continuous process of reaffirmation or change.
Such a view does not allow for the existence of ‘organisations’ in
any hard and concrete sense. Whilst certain schools of thought
accept the concept of organisation and its use as an ‘accounting
practice’ by which people attempt to make sense of their world,
they do not recognise organisations as such. From the standpoint
of the interpretive paradigm, organisations simply do not exist.
Strictly speaking, therefore, the notion of there being a theory of
organisations characteristic of the interpretive paradigm is some-
what contradictory. However, in recent years a number of
theorists located within this paradigm have involved themselves in
a debate about various aspects of organisational life. They have
done so as sociologists concerned to demonstrate the validity of
their point of view as against the prevailing orthodoxy
characteristic of the functionalist paradigm. As will be apparent
from our discussion in ChapterS, most organisation theorists tend
to treat their subject of study as a hard, concrete and tangible
empirical phenomenon which exists ·out there’ in the ·real world’.
The interpretive sociologists are firmly opposed to such ‘structural
absolutism’, arguing that social science should be based upon
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 261
fundamentally different assumptions about the ontological status
of the social world. In order to demonstrate this point, they have
engaged in research designed to illustrate the fallacy of the
functionalist standpoint. They have sought to show how the
supposedly hard, concrete, tangible and ‘real’ aspects of organisa-
tional life are dependent upon the subjective constructions of
individual human beings. In doing this they have produced a cer-
tain amount of literature which has considerable relevance for our
analysis here, since it opens up a debate about the assumptions
which underwrite the contemporary orthodoxy in organisation
theory. This literature, however, is not without its problems, since
in attempting to undermine the notions informing more orthodox
functionalist approaches to the study of organisational life, the
interpretive sociologists have often been drawn into a battle fought
upon their opponents’ ground. In adopting a reactive stance they
often endorse, by implication, the validity of certain background
assumptions which define the functionalist problematic. Con-
sequently, their stance is often somewhat contradictory, and there
tends to be a divergence between theoretical pronouncements and
the assumptions reflected in empirical research.
In this chapter we hope to move some way towards clarifying the
issues involved here. We shall review some of the literature and we
shall attempt to evaluate it in terms of the assumptions upon which
it is based. This literature is confined to the perspectives described
in the previous chapter as ethnomethodology and phenomenologi-
cal symbolic interactionism, though, as we have suggested, we do
not wish to place too much emphasis upon the importance of this
distinction.
Ethnomethodological Approaches to the
Study of Organisational Activities
One of the earliest ethnomethodological critiques of functionalist
organisation theory is found in Egon Bittner’s article, ‘The Con-
cept of Organisation’, first published in 1965. In this article Bittner
argues that organisation theorists, who define organisations as
‘stable associations of persons engaged in concerted activities
directed to the attainment of specific objectives’, tend to take the
concept of organisation structure as unproblematic. He argues that
this notion of structure represents no more than a common-sense
assumption of certain actors within a given situation. To take this
262 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
common-sense assumption at face value, and use it as a basis for
organisational analysis, is thus fraught with difficulty. He argues,
in effect, that the sociologist who uses such a concept as a
·resource’ for explaining organisational activities is committing a
fundamental error, and that such concepts should be the ‘topic’
rather than the tool of analysis. In the course of his argument
Bittner illustrates his case in relation to the work of Selznick and
Weber, and suggests that their theories are based upon a whole set
of unstated presuppositions and theoretical shortcuts which build
a protective mantle around the subject of study. The concept of
bureaucracy. for example, builds upon background information
that normally competent members of society take for granted as
commonly known. In building upon this Bittner suggests that
Weber is in collusion with those about whom he theorises. He
summarises his views very forcefully in the following terms: ‘If the
theory of bureaucracy is a theory at all. it is a refined and purified
version of the actor’s theorising. To the extent that it is a refine-
ment and purification of it, it is, by the same token, a corrupt and
incomplete version of it; for it is certainly not warranted to reduce
the terms of common-sense discourse to a lexicon of culturally
coded significances to satisfy the requirements of theoretical pos-
tulations’ (Bittner, 1974, p. 74).
In the place of this ·corrupt’ and ‘incomplete’ version of the
actor’s theorising about organisational structures. Bittner suggests
the study of organisation as a common-sense construct in which
the ·methodologist’ must be concerned with the procedures and
considerations which actors invoke in the construction of their
world. In the last part of his paper Bittner goes on to develop an
explicitly ethnomethodological approach to the rational construc-
tions subsumed under the concept of organisation, which reflects a
programme of enquiry rather than a specific interest in producing a
theory of organisations as such. In this Bittner assumes that the
actor in an organisation is not a disinterested bystander but a
toolsmith using the concept of organisation in a certain relatively
specific way and for certain variable reasons. He suggests that
organisational actors can, for example, use the concept of rational
organisation as a ‘gambit of compliance’, in which certain rules of
conduct are invoked simply by using the term. On the other hand,
there is an ‘open realm offree play’ within and outside these rules
which presents us with the opportunity ‘to attain a grasp of the
meaning of the rules as common-sense constructs from the
perspective of those persons who promulgate and live with them’.
Moreover. the concept of ‘formal organisation • acts as a ‘model of
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 263
stylistic unity’ and as a ‘corroborative reference’, two interrelated
notions concerned with the regulation and discipline of behaviour
in organisational contexts. Taken together with the ·gambit of
compliance’, they form three ways within organisations in which
‘competent users’ of the term ‘formal organisation’ utilise it as a
mechanism for control. In these ways Bittner’s analysis points
towards an understanding of the manner in which the organisa-
tional world is constructed by the actors involved.
The main thrust of Bittner’s article lies in its suggestion that the
concept of organisation, and related issues such as structure,
hierarchy and efficiency, are problematic social constructs. He
argues that these constructs should be the topic of research in
sociological analysis and should not be taken for granted. In sub-
sequent work, however, Bittner and his followers have not always
proved true to these requirements. His article ‘The Police on Skid
Row’ (1967), for example, illustrates this very clearly.
Bittner’s research with the police departments of two large
urban areas used the accounting practices of the police officers as
its analytical focus of attention. By centring attention on Skid
Row, which is seen by the police as a special area, divorced from
society at large, characterised by gratuitous violence, uncertainty
in human behaviour and a shifting, uncommitted population of
deviant misfits, Bittner is able to depict the policeman as the
‘definer of the situation’ par excellence. The ‘peace-keeping’ role
adopted by the police on Skid Row allows them considerable
freedom of action, relatively unconstrained by the judiciary and
central authority, as a result of which they are free to define local
people’s behaviour, motivation and past actions in terms of their
expectations only.
Bittner, nevertheless, is at pains to point out that Skid Row is
unusual, in that the men who patrol it are not subject to ·any
systems of external control’. Implicitly, then, and by the back door
of his analysis, the notion of social and organisational structure
appears on the stage. At one point in his analysis Bittner
introduces the concept of ‘structural determinants’ but attempts to
define them in a subjective way as ‘the typical situations that
policemen perceive as demand conditions for action without
arrest’ . 1 What he seems to be implying, here and throughout the
article, is that structural factors at both social and organisational
level tend to have less impact in the role performance of policemen
on Skid Row than elsewhere. The article does not question the
problematic nature of the concepts of ‘external control’. ‘society
in general’, ·normalcy’ and ‘superiors’. Somewhat paradoxically,
264 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
therefore, rather than the study of Skid Row representing an
ethnomethodological refutation of the importance of structural
factors, its very unusualness seems to underline the crucial impact
of structure upon ·normal’ everyday life. Bittner”s research is of
importance in demonstrating the role of accounting practices in the
social construction of ‘reality’, but it is presented in such a way as
to rekindle the probing reader’s belief in the existence of
·structure’ within the vast segment of society which is not Skid
Row. Thus, whilst Bittner’s theoretical article ‘The Concept of
Organisation’ warns about the danger of ‘collusion’ or complicity
within the subject under investigation, the empirical work of some
two years later seems to fall into the self-same trap. The article’s
own schema of background assumptions is predicated upon a
series of organisational and societal relationships which seem to be
accepted unquestioningly.
This discrepancy between theoretical pronouncement and
empirical research also characterises the work of Don Zimmerman
and his associates. In certain articles Zimmerman adheres to a
nominalist ontology characteristic of the interpretive paradigm,
but in others he veers in a much more objectivist direction. In the
article wrinen with Wieder ( 1970), for example, the social world is
regarded as the direct product of human consciousness. The
authors specifically reject the notion that there exist
intersubjectively shared meanings, norms and values to which the
activities of individuals are orientated. Instead they account for
the seeming presence of such phenomena by suggesting that
human beings ‘continuously rely on, and if pressed, insist upon,
the capacities of others to find a presumptively shared sense in
what they are saying’ (Zimmerman and Wieder, 1970, p. 294). In
other words, they emphasise that the social world is created
through the accounting practices of individuals as they engage in
the routine activities of everyday life. The nominalist ontology
reflected in this point of view is perfectly consistent with the
assumptions which characterise the interpretive paradigm.
In two articles presenting the results of empirical work
Zimmerman takes a different line. We have in mind here ‘The
Practicalities of Rule Use’ (1970a) and ‘Record Keeping and the
Intake Process in a Public Welfare Organisation’ (1970b). Both
pieces of work are based upon research at the offices of a State
Bureau of Public Assistance, the first looking at the ·reception
function’, not so much in terms of the prescribed work, but from
the point of view of the receptionists themselves. As a paper it
examines certain aspects of the work activities of these
The Interpretive ParadiRm and the Study of OrRani.fations 265
bureaucratic actors. particularly their role in inducting applicants
for public assistance into their organisational routine. Following
Bittner, Zimmerman attacks the notion that a formal organisa-
tional structure is an unproblematic facticity. pointing out that ‘the
issue of what rules. policies, and goals mean for the bureaucratic
actor upon the concrete occasion of their use (for example, to
guide, to account for, or to justify action) must be treated as
problematic’ (Zimmerman, 1970a, p. 224). The piece shows quite
clearly that individuals use the rules ofthe organisation to relate to
their work and for reconciling organisational and individual
requirements. For Zimmerman, it is the receptionist’s interpreta-
tion which is crucial rather than the supposed fact that rules and
regulations exist ‘outside’ the individuals involved in any fixed,
unbending, objectively defined sense. The ‘competent use’ of a
rule, which in itself can never be fully determinate of behaviour,
lies behind the reproduction of a day-by-day, ·normal’ state of
affairs. However, Zimmerman clearly accepts the facti city of
organisational structures and the existence of externally imposed
rules. What he suggests as Bittner did before him, is that move-
ment within this structure is possible. Ontologically, this stands in
stark contrast to the theoretical article written with Wieder ( 1970).
Although a marked measure of voluntarism is common to both
articles, since human beings as ·competent rule users’ are
relatively free to create their own social world, the ontological
foundations seem to differ between the theoretical and empirical
works. In the former the social world is largely a product of
consciousness: in the latter a vague disquieting ambience of
‘structure’. dark and threatening but not quite fully discernible, is
felt to be the ‘real’ core of social reality.
A structural ‘presence’ is also evident in Zimmerman’s other
empirical piece on ‘sensible intake work’ ( 1970b). The social
welfare caseworker, like the receptionist, is engaged in an ongoing
process of interpretation of how much of a client’s story is fiction
and how much ‘fact’. Documentation is crucial here, and the case
record is of particular importance as an example of an attempt to
assemble the world of a client, which is inherently rule-governed
and made accountable through post facto reconstruction in a way
reminiscent of Schutz’s notion of reflexivity. These documented
sets of ‘facts’ then assume a concrete facticity and immutability,
and are seen as objective, detached and inherently reliable. For the
caseworker the world is viewed as non-problematic, indeed as
‘obvious’, and the case records come to reflect this assumption.
Zimmerman admits that external constraints are important. For
266 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
example, he states that speed and verification are central to the
caseworker’s role, but the reader is left to infer that this is because
of the caseworker’s position within an organisational hierarchy
with its own rules and disciplinary procedures. This acceptance of
the ontological status of organisational structures is not consonant
with the nominalist ontology characteristic of Zimmerman’s more
theoretical work.
The theory and research of both Bittner and Zimmerman is thus
characterised by what may be usefully described as a form of
‘ontological oscillation’. Analytically, they stress a highly sub-
jectivist stance which denies the existence of social structures and
concrete social reality of any form. Yet the attempt to operational-
ise their ideas within an empirical context frequently leads them to
admit a more realist form of ontology through the back door.
Whilst this is unintended, it does pose great difficulties for students
attempting to understand their work and to distinguish it from
research typical, for example, of the action frame of reference and
the interactionism characteristic of the functionalist paradigm. Yet
this ontological oscillation is prevalent in all forms of
phenomenological sociology which attempt to illustrate its basic
propositions through the empirical study of situations drawn from
everyday life.
It is characteristic, for example. of the work of David Silverman
who, since his advocacy of the action frame of reference
(Silverman. 1970), has produced work with a significantly different
orientation. As we have argued in Chapter 5, Silverman,like many
other theorists who have adopted the action frame of reference as
a basis of analysis, has frequently drawn inspiration from the
writings of more phenomenologically orientated theorists, partic-
ularly Schutz. However, following Weber, they have used the
action framework as a tool for studying a relatively ·realist’ social
reality, largely ignoring the ontological implications which their
framework reflects. As we have shown in Chapter 6, the true
significance of phenomenological sociology rests in its recognition
of the ontological status of typifications or ‘ideal types· which
comprise the core of social reality. In The Theory of Organisations
(1970), Silverman recognises that reality is socially constructed,
socially sustained and socially changed, yet he interprets this
essentially as indicating the need for social· theories to adopt a
more voluntaristic theory of action and to avoid the reification of
social phenomena. In other words, as we have argued at length in
Chapter 5, Silverman ( 1970) adheres to a highly voluntaristic view
of human nature but to an ontology, an epistemology and a
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 267
methodology characteristic of the subjectivist region of the
functionalist paradigm. The Theory of Organisations is addressed
to organisation theorists who hold to a functionalist view of social
reality; its main contribution lies in its advocacy of a particular
methodology for studying that reality.
In his more recent work (Filmer eta/ .• 1972; Silverman, 1975a,
1975b; Silverman and Jones, 1973, 1976), Silverman has pursued
the latent phenomenological issues which occupy a background
role in The Theory of Organisations and has adopted a theoretical
position firmly located within the context ofthe interpretive para-
digm. A comparison of this body of work with The Theory of
Organisations clearly illustrates the implications of a paradigm
change. To organisation theorists located within the functionalist
paradigm, Silverman’s recent work usually appears confusing, if
not unintelligible, and is largely dismissed as unhelpful, if not
irrelevant. Yet from the standpoint of the interpretive paradigm, it
contains many genuine insights and has contributed a great deal to
the debate in contemporary circles interested in phenomenological
sociology.
Silverman’s recent work seeks to provide an ethnomethodologi-
cal interpretation of various activities within the context of
organisational situations. 2 The publication of New Directions in
Sociological Theory (1972), written in conjunction with Filmer et
al, marks an explicit move to an ontology characteristic of the
interpretive paradigm. In this work Silverman and his colleagues
seek to shift sociological perspectives away from the functionalist
orthodoxy and towards more phenomenologically inspired
approaches. Chapter 6 is of particular interest, since it partly
concerns itself with the specific study of organisational activities.
In it Silverman attacks functionalist organisation theory for its
excessive belief in ·social facts’ and, by drawing upon the work of
Bittner (1965), Zimmerman (1970a) and Sudnow (1965), argues
that organisational “rules’ are, in point offact, the ‘ongoing practi-
cal accomplishments’ of organisational members. Silverman is at
pains to reject the ‘structural absolutism’ of most sociological
theorising, particularly for ignoring the ‘processual relationship
between subject and object in the social world, i.e. acknowledge-
ment of the intersubjective character of social life’ (Filmer et al.,
1972, p. 168). In this piece of work Silverman sees phenomenologi-
cal sociology as concerned not so much with ‘unique experience’
as with the commonalty of ·raw materials’. notably language,
which underpin social experience as a whole. Silverman
appears to accept that there is an intersubjectively shared reality
268 Sociolol!ical Paradigms and Or!!anisational Analysis
which offers itself for investigation by the phenomenological
sociologist.
In ‘Getting In: The Managed Accomplishments of “Correct”
Selection Outcomes’ (Silverman and Jones, 1973), a shift of atten-
tion is evident, in that considerable emphasis is placed not so much
upon the commonality of raw materials which underpin social
experience, but upon the conflicting views of reality which
characterise any given situation. The stud}’ presents a preliminary
report of empirical research on staff selection interviews within a
large organisation. It shows the manner in which the interview
situation is built around verbal and non-verbal exchanges in which
motives and personal qualities are attributed to others through the
use of typifications. and how the interview can be seen as an
accounting process influenced by the need for ‘authoritative
accounts’ through which it can be made accountable to others.
Silverman and Jones demonstrate how the interview situation is
characterised by multiple realities. as people attempt to make
sense of the situation. As they note. their theoretical focus is the
idea that ·an account of any reality derives its rationality not from
its direct correspondence with some objective world but from the
ability of its hearers (readers) to make sense of the account in the
context of the socially organised occasions of its use (and thereby
to treat it as corresponding to an objective world)’ (Silverman and
Jones. 1973, pp. 63-4). This focus clearly reflects a nominalist
ontology characteristic of the interpretive paradigm, with Silver-
man and Jones emphasising how reality is specific to particular
social contexts. However, as with so many other phenomenologi-
cal studies, the presence of structure in the form of hierarchical
influence and ‘scientific peer groups’lurks in the background as a
force influencing the need for ·authoritative accounts’ of events
and the achievement of ‘correct’ selection outcomes.
In ‘Accounts of Organisations’ Silverman returns to a position
approaching that reflected in his 1972 piece. with a critique
of functionalist conceptions of organisation from an
ethnomethodological standpoint. In this he stresses the need, for
example, to understand organisational activities in terms of
accounting practices and to understand bureaucracy as not ‘in
itself .. an object” but a language-category which provides for the
object-like qualities of an activity’ (Silverman, 197Sa, p. 296). Its
ontological premises, whilst consistent with a position within the
interpretive paradigm, are not as subjectivist as those reflected in
‘Oetting In’ (Silverman and Jones, 1973).
Organisational Work (Silverman and Jones, 1976) bears witness
The Interpretive ParadiRm and the Study ofOrRanisations 269
to yet another change. This book presents the final report of their
empirical work on the staff-selection process within an organisa-
tional situation and focuses upon the power and authority relations
reflected in the language used in organisational contexts. Silver-
man and Jones report how a ‘fresh look’ at their interview tapes
revealed that organisational members in their interaction and
accounting procedures had ‘lay’ conceptualisations of a
‘hierarchy’. Whilst this is seen as providing evidence in fa.vour of
the phenomenological construction and reconstruction of
organisational structure (that people create structure through their
accounting practices), Silverman and Jones argue that it is not ‘to
be construed as a solipsistic denial of the factual character of
organisational structures’, for their reality is ·undeniable’ (Silver-
man and Jones, 1976, p. 20). Such an assertion on the ontological
status of structures, which attributes to them an existence on their
own terms, is quite out of keeping with the positions articulated in
the earlier work referred to above and testifies to what appears to
be a major change in theoretical orientation. Whilst Silverman and
Jones do not deny the role which individuals play in the construc-
tion of their social world, they proceed to argue that the nature of
accounting practices sustain ·our all too real technologi-
cal/bureaucratic community’, and that our speech and language of
discourse tends to lock us into a relatively passive role as ·mere
functionaries’ within our present society. They illustrate their
point of view through the evidence of their empirical research on
interviews, demonstrating ‘the grading of language’ in which
speech and written reports come to reflect the hierarchical nature
of the context in which they are located. The hierarchical or
grading element in the interview process, for example, is seen as
being linked to ‘the canons of rationality’ in which there are (I)
premises all can accept, (2) steps all can follow and (3) conclusions
all must accept. These canons come to be used within organisa-
tions as legitimate devices for defining the ·seriousness’ or
authentication of community accounts. The parallels between this
analysis and Habermas’s theory of ‘communicative distortion·,
which we discuss in the next chapter, is particularly striking,
though the authors do not specifically acknowledge the link. They
do, however, identify parallels with the work of Heidegger and
Marx. Silverman and Jones argue that selection interviewing is a
form of evaluation, and that this involves stratification within a
society whose ‘form of life’ is seen, in essence, as a market in
which language and speech constitute commodities. Both Heid-
egger and Marx are seen as having recognised this in their different
270 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
ways. Grading and accounts of grading become, for Silverman and
Jones, alienated labour, ‘in which men are related to their mode of
speech as to an alien object; in which they use speech to do things
(like grading) but in using it are mastered by it since the form of life
which makes that speech intelligible dehumanises human activities
(makes them something)’ (Silverman and Jones, 1976, p. 172).
Alienated labour then forms a nexus with the hierarchical nature of
our mundane existence and with the predominance of ‘exchange
value’ as the standard of discourse within our society. Thus
Silverman and Jones conclude that our present social structure
requires a grading of language, which itself affirms ·market
hierarchy and a separation of Being from Writing’. ‘What,’ they
ask, ‘might it be like to write no longer merely as a functionary?’
(Silverman and Jones, 1976, p. 180).
In discovering the power and authority relationship within
accounting practices, language and ‘speech acts’, Silverman and
Jones are, in effect, articulating a perspective characteristic of the
hermeneutic approach to critical theory within . the radical
humanist paradigm. As we have noted above, it has much in
common with the work of Habermas and must be regarded as a
m~or change in theoretical orientation. The ontological oscillation
characteristic of the earlier work is resolved, perhaps unwittingly,
through the recognition of a dimension of power and domination
beneath the ongoing process through which social reality is created
and sustained. This power dimension is able to account for the
seeming presence of structural factors in the background of reports
on empirical work, but it is not entirely consistent with the
phenomenological sociology characteristic of the interpretive
paradigm, since it implies that the social construction of reality is
underwritten by a pervasive form of ideological domination. The
essentially conservative orientation of interpretive sociology, with
its concern for understanding how individuals create and impose
order upon their world, is displaced along the regulation-radical
change dimension of our analytical scheme by the radical humanist
concern for understanding how individuals become trapped as
‘mere functionaries’ within the context of a social formation alien
to the nature of their true being.
Phenomenological Symbolic Interactionism
and the Study of Organisational Activities
The focus of interest of the phenomenological symbolic
interactionist differs from that of the ethnomethodologist in the
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 271
degree of attention devoted to the manner in which social reality is
negotiated through interaction. Whereas the ethnomethodologist
usually focuses upon the way in which individual actors account
for and make sense of their world, the phenomenological symbolic
interactionist focuses upon social contexts in which interacting
individuals employ a variety of practices to create and sustain
particular definitions of the world. They demonstrate how ‘reality’
and ‘facts· are essentially social creations. negotiated through
the interaction of various competing themes and definitions of
reality. We will consider here, two studies which illustrate this
approach.
David Sudnow in ‘Normal Crimes’ (1965), attempts to demons-
trate the way in which criminal sentences in certain courts in the
USA are negotiated through interaction between the District
Attorney, the Public Prosecutor, the Public Defender and the
defendant. Sud now explains how, in an attempt to speed up prog-
ress through the courts and reduce the work load, the defendant
may be persuaded to plead guilty in exchange for a red_uced charge
and sentence. This occurs in the context of a deal consisting of an
offer from the District Attorney to alter the original charge. How-
ever, such an offer is shown to depend on whether the crime
committed by the defendant fits one of the ‘typifications • classified
by the legal parties in their mental case-files as a ·normal crime’.
The legal process, which is usually regarded as governed and
bound by the nature of the penal code, is thus shown to operate
through a process of interaction and negotiation mediated by the
socially constructed realities adhered to by the parties involved. It
thus demonstrates that the legal code and criminal statistics, which
are commonly treated as hard ‘social facts’, are by no means
reliable and clear-cut descriptions of particular social realities. The
implication is that social reality is socially negotiated and socially
sustained, even within the context of rule-bound and tightly con-
trolled bureaucratic situations.
A similar perspective is evident in Joan Emerson’s ‘Behaviour
in Private Places’ ( 1970). In this article Emerson seeks to illustrate
how a dominant definition of reality may be invaded by counter-
realities which oppose or qualify the dominant definition in various
ways. The gynaecological examination presents a situation in
which different realities are precariously balanced. The situation is
characterised by an impersonal, clinical and medical definition on
the one hand, and a personal, intimate, sexual definition on the
other. Emerson clearly demonstrates how the sexual aspect can
unintentionally invade the clinical definition, so that the parties
272 SocioloRical ParadiRms and Orflanisational Analysis
involved have continually to strive to define the situation as a
‘gynaecological examination going right’, a situation in which no
one is embarrassed and no one is thinking in sexual terms. She
demonstrates very clearly how this occurs, with the gynaecologist
and nurse acting in concert to sustain the dominant definition
through a particular kind of language and technique. When the
dominant definition breaks down (through, for example, the
patient blushing. or refusing to co-operate through modesty), a
whole battery of interventions and techniques is brought into play
to restore the balance. The reality of the gynaecological examina-
tion is shown to rest upon a complex and sustained series of
negotiations between all the parties involved.
Emerson maintains that the precarious balance of competing
realities found in the gynaecological examination represents but an
extreme case illustrative of the ongoing process which
characterises a wide range of situations in everyday life. It merely
exaggerates the internally contradictory nature of definitions of
reality which are found in everyday situations, at work, in social
encounters, or whatever. The study emphasises how individuals
have to involve themselves in a deliberate effort to maintain a
balance between the connicting themes reflected in any given
social situation, and how the social reality which emerges is essen-
tially negotiated by the actors directly involved.
As in the case of Sudnow’s study, Emerson’s work, whilst
distinctly phenomenological in its basic orientation with regard to
the socially created status of reality, does admit of a more concrete
form of social organisation in the background. Reality in each case
is constructed upon what appears to be a pre-set stage by actors
who have already been allocated roles. In neither study is this
background subjected to scrutiny; the focus is upon the ways in
which the actors construct the scene in which they find
themselves.
As in the case of the ethnomethodological studies considered
earlier, certain ontological problems are reflected in this research.
Later in this chapter we will consider the dilemma which
phenomenological sociologists face in engaging upon empirical
work of this kind. For the moment, however, we will turn to
consider the implications which this type of phenomenologically
orientated research, despite its problems, has for organisation
theorists located within the functionalist paradigm.
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 273
The Phenomenological Challenge to
Contemporary Organisation Theory
The challenge which phenomenological sociology presents to con-
temporary organisation theory is clearly of a very fundamental
kind. 3 It suggests that the whole enterprise of’ organisation theory’
is based upon very dubious foundations. The ontological assump-
tions which characterise the functionalist paradigm stand in
fundamental opposition to those which underwrite the
phenomenological perspective. For phenomenologists, organisa-
tions as tangible and relatively concrete phenomena simply do not
exist; the social world is essentially processual and emerges from
the intentional acts of human beings acting individually or in con-
cert with one another. The social reality ‘created’ in the course of
this process consists of little more than images of reality which can
be understood in terms of a network of typifications. They do not
comprise a solid definition; they gloss over complexity; the com-
plex nature of social reality only emerges when individuals are
forced, through the pressures of interaction with one another, or in
attempting to make sense oftheir world, to dive deeper and deeper
for new or modified typifications to account for and make sense of
their situation. The complex and tangible nature of reality ·out
there’ is, from this point of view, a socially constructed
phenomenon of dubious intersubjective status and as transient as
the moment in which it is viewed.
Organisations, therefore, are seen, from the phenomenological
perspective, as social constructs; an organisation stands as a con-
cept which means different things to different people. As a univer-
sal concept, its intersubjective status is extremely dubious.
Organisation theorists are seen as belonging to a small and self-
sustaining community which believes that organisations exist in a
relatively tangible ontological sense and theorises about them.
From the phenomenological standpoint, organisation theorists
theorise about concepts which have very little significance to
people outside the community which practises organisation theory
and the limited community which organisation theorists may
attempt to serve.
For the phenomenologists, organisation theorists sustain their
enterprise by colluding with those whom they· attempt to serve, or,
more appropriately, those to whom they feel they need to make
their activities rationally accountable. It is for this reason that
contemporary organisation theory is accused of having a manager-
ial bias. It uses managerial concepts in order to construct its
274 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
theories. These concepts are used as a ‘resource’, whereas, as
Bittner ( 1965) suggests, from the phenomenological point of view
they should provide the ‘topic’ of analysis.
The phenomenological challenge to contemporary organisation
theory is total and complete, because the issue at dispute is that of
ontology. It follows from this that all the concepts which the
organisation theorist uses to construct his view of organisational
reality are open to criticism. The concepts of organisation
structure, job satisfaction, organisational climate, etc., are all
reifications which are often confused with social reality. Should
the organisation theorist claim that they are merely of heuristic
value, then the question of • ownership’ arises, and the unwitting or
conscious collusion which this implies. Much of the
phenomenological research which we have considered in this
chapter can be understood as an attempt to demonstrate to theor-
ists located within the functionalist orthodoxy that they are over-
concretising the social world. The studies which have demon-
strated, for example, how individuals create the rules within an
organisational context, negotiate the nature of ‘crime’ and hence,
of criminal ‘statistics’, demonstrate that to view reality in terms of
these rules, structures and statistics is to view the world in terms
which are all too simple. The core of social reality lies in what
Garfinkel ( 1967, p. II) has described as ‘the awesome indexicality’
of everyday life. Reality does not exist on the surface of human
affairs, offering itself for straightforward study as the functionalist
organisation theorist so often assumes. Social reality lies deep
within the network of typifications which individuals, if pressed,
will summon to make sense of the situation in which they find
themselves.
The implications of a phenomenological sociology true to the
ontological assumptions of the interpretive paradigm are com-
pletely destructive as far as contemporary organisation theory is
concerned. The phenomenological sociologist and the organisa-
tion theorist occupy different social realities to all intents and
purposes; they live in different intellectual worlds. The con-
temporary organisation theorist cannot build his theories within
the context of the interpretive paradigm.
What, then, can the contemporary organisation theorist learn
from the phenomenologist? What can he incorporate within the
bounds of the functionalist paradigm? It would seem that here
there is some scope for integration – a potential which others have
already tried to explore. It will be recalled from the previous
chapter that the concern to integrate the perspectives of idealism
The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations 215
and positivism was a preoccupation of many social theorists in the
years of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. It was
one ofthe major problems to which Dilthey and Weber addressed
themselves, for example, and, as we have suggested, social action
theory and certain varieties ofinteractionism can be understood as
the direct products of this concern. In many respects these schools
ofthought represent the functionalist reaction to the idealist view
of social reality which underwrites the phenomenological perspec-
tive, and offer scope for further development within organisational
theory. Silverman’s book The Theory of Organisations (1970), for
example, suggests one possible line of development.
Clearly, there is much more that can be done within the context
of functionalism to explore the implications of studying a social
reality which is far less clear-cut, certain and solid, and more
processual, than has been envisaged in theory to date. There is
more scope for recognising the role of individuals in interpreting
and sustaining particular views of social reality than is generally
recognised. There is scope for adopting an epistemology, a view of
human nature and a methodology consonant with this revised view
of the ontological status of the social world. In short, contempor-
ary organisation theory can usefully assess and reappraise its basic
orientation with regard to its assumptions on each of the four
strands of the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme.• Such action would represent a response which meets the
phenomenological challenge upon the functionalist’s own ground.
As far as the phenomenologist is concerned, it would be an
inadequate response. At heart, the basic challenge of
phenomenology to functionalist theory is to respect the nature of
the social world and, for the phenomenologist, this is just not
possible within the bounds of the functionalist problematic. s
Phenomenological Approaches to the Study
of Organisational Situations: Problems and
Dilemmas
Adopting the standpoint of the phenomenological sociologist
rather than that of the functionalist organisation theorist, what
implications emerge from the discussion and analysis presented in
earlier sections of this chapter? Clearly, there are many problems
for the phenomenological sociologist concerned to study the
nature of organisational situations, since he is often unwittingly led
276 SocioloRical ParadiRms and OrRanisational Analysis
to recognise and acknowledge features within any given situation
which, if pressed, he would be forced to deny. We have made
much of this point in our discussion of the ‘ontological oscillation’
between theoretical and empirical work.
It would seem that many of these problems arise because the
researchers concerned have not been sufficiently explicit about
what they are attempting to demonstrate, Focusing upon the four
elements of the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical
scheme, it is unclear whether the empirical work of these theo1ists
aims to illustrate a particular view of ontology, to demonstrate the
superiority of a particular approach to epistemology and
methodology, or merely to emphasise the voluntarism which they
see as characterising human affairs. No doubt some of the studies
attempt to achieve all these aims, though their success is question-
able.
If the concern of the phenomenological sociologist is to tackle
the problem of ontology, as his theoretical perspective requires,
then it is important that he be explicit about this. It is important to
emphasise that the reality which his work reflects is fundamentally
different from that conceptualised by, for example, the
functionalist theorist. Insofar as he confines himself to illustrating
movement within organisational rules or against the background of
a bureaucratic structure, as some of the studies discussed earlier
have sought to do, then his work tends to affirm the basic existence
of the reality upon which functionalist theory, for example, is
based. The choice of unusual situations for research such as Skid
Row, which are far removed from the realm of everyday life for the
majority of people, also tends to reaffirm the concrete status of
everyday reality in situations which are not Skid Row. If the
phenomenologist is concerned to tackle the problem of ontology, it
would seem that it is necessary to study situations in which people
are typically regarded as having relatively little discretion in the
way in which they mould their reality. Up to now phenomen-
ological research has focused upon what the functionalist theorist
would regard as high-discretion roles, such as those of the
receptionist, district attorney, police officer, gynaecologist, etc.
Phenomenological studies of what are usually seen as low-
discretion situations (characteristic of the assembly line, for
example) tend to be conspicuous by their absence.
A focus upon the ontological problems involved here would
require the phenomenological sociologist to take a firm stand on
the precise status of the concepts of organisation, hierarchy,
bureaucratic rules, etc., and other background features inherent in
The Interpretive ParadiRm and the Study of OrRanisations 211
much of the empirical work produced to date. It would clarify
whether they actually intend to dispute the realist ontology which
characterises the functionalist orthodoxy, or whether they are
merely attempting to illustrate the complex and voluntaristic
nature of human actions and the inadequacies of positivist
epistemology and nomethetic methodology for developing an
adequate understanding of this process. It would bring them face
to face with the basic assumptions which underwrite the
interpretive paradigm, since they would be obliged to be specific
about the precise status of social reality and the form which it
takes. As we noted in our discussion on the work of Silverman and
his colleagues, the attempt to deal with a socially contructed and
socially sustained reality which appears all too ·real’ has
introduced a new dimension into his work consonant with ·critical
theory’ within the radical humanist paradigm. The attempt to
handle the seeming presence of pattern and structure reflected in
the social construction of reality has led to a focus upon ideological
issues intimately related to the regulation-radical change
dimension of our analytical scheme. Phenomenological sociology
characteristic of the interpretive paradigm is underwritten by the
basic assumption that there is a tendency towards order in social
affairs. Insofar as a part of this order is reflected in a pattern and
structure which provides a context within which reality is created,
it needs to be explained. It is precisely this concern which has led
many social theorists who wish to continue to subscribe to a
nominalist perspective characteristic of the idealist tradition to
forge alternative frameworks.
As we shall find in the next chapter, this concern is very much
reflected in the work of Hegel and in the problem of the dialectical
relationship between subject and object worlds. It is also reflected
in the work of the young Karl Marx, Jean-Paul Sartre and, more
recently, Habermas. In their different ways they have sought to
demonstrate that the socially created world can become all too real
and provides a framework which constrains the actions and
orientations of human beings, as if it had an existence on its own
account. We do not wish to imply here that phenomenological
sociology can only be further developed within the context of the
radical humanist paradigm. Our intention is to pose the issues
which arise if phenomenological sociologists acknowledge the
seeming presence of structure which hangs in the background of
their current work. By confronting the basic ontological problem
which this involves, they will clarify the nature of their enterprise.
For those who remain convinced that social reality is entirely the
278 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
creation of autonomous human beings involved in the flow of
everyday life, the problem will be to develop epistemologies and
methodologies adequate for studying the nature of this world. For
those for whom structure and pattern in social reality appear all too
‘real’, a consideration of the power dimension inherent in the
ability of the individual to create his reality is likely to prove a
major issue and, pursued to its logical end, will undoubtedly call
for a major reorientation in theoretical perspective. It will call for a
perspective which has much more in common with radical human-
ism than with the sociology of regulation which characterises the
interpretive paradigm.
Notes and References
1. Silverman, in defence of Bittner’s view, has suggested that
he uses ‘structural determinants’ in a highly specific sense
(Silverman in McKinlay, 1975, p. 282).
2. We shall not consider here Silverman’s book Reading
Castaneda (l975b), which seeks to provide an
ethnomethodological analysis of Castaneda ( 1970) and thus
does not focus upon practices within organisational contexts.
3. We shall confine our discussion here to the implications of
phenomenology for theories characteristic of the
functionalist paradigm. It is clear that there are also implica-
tions for theories located in the other paradigms.
Unfortunately, it is beyond the scope of our present
endeavour to address these here.
4. For a discussion of some of the epistemological and
methodological implications of phenomenological sociology,
see, for example, Blumer (1969), Cicourel (1964), Douglas
(1970b). Many of their arguments are conveniently brought
together in Mennell ( 1974).
S. We wish to emphasise here the point made in note 3 above.
The nature of the concept of paradigm, as used here,
necessarily implies that the legitimacy of the world view
reflected in a particular paradigm is fundamentally opposed
by the perspectives characteristic of the other three.
8. Radical Humanism
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The intellectual origins of the radical humanist paradigm can be
traced back to the tenets of German idealism and the Kantian
notion that the ultimate reality of the universe is spiritual rather
than material in nature. It thus derives from the same intellectual
source as the interpretive paradigm, though the essentially subjec-
tivist orientation which the two paradigms have in common are
made to serve fundamentally different ends.
The interpretive and radical humanist paradigms are both
founded upon the notion that the individual creates the world in
which he lives. But, whereas the interpretive theorists are content
to understand the nature of this process, the radical humanists
subject it to critique, focusing upon what they regard as the essen-
tially alienated state of man.
This critique proceeds along two avenues of discourse. One of
these is associated with a ‘subjective idealist’ position, which
derives from the same source as the philosophy of Husser! and
other phenomenologists discussed in Chapter 6. Although the
roots of the subjective idealist tradition can be traced back to the
philosophy of Kant and earlier, it is in the work of Fichte
(1762-1814) that it first receives its most explicit and coherent
expression.’ Fichte was a follower of Kant, and his brand of
subjective idealism rested upon the assumption that individual
consciousness is a continuously creative entity generating a per-
petual stream of ideas, concepts and perspectives through which a
world external to mind is created. From Fichte’s point of view, any
understanding of this created reality involved understanding the
nature, structure and functioning of conscious mind. However, he
was at pains to distinguish between this internal domain of con-
sciousness and what was created by it and thu·s made external to it.
In so doing he was able to steer clear of the solipsist perspective by
recognising the existence of an external world, thus establishing a
position some way between the immaterialism of Bishop Berkeley
and the perspective of ‘objective idealism’ as, for example,
280 Sociolo~:ical Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
reflected in the work of Hegel ( 1770-1831). For Fichte, the exter-
nal world was to be understood in terms of the projection of
individual consciousness. Fichte saw human beings as externalis-
ingtheirexperiences into a form of reality which in turn is reflected
back upon them, and through which they became conscious of
themselves and their actions. As noted above, this perspective has
had a widespread influence upon contemporary philosophy and
social theory through the work of Husser! and other
phenomenologists. Its influence upon the radical humanist para-
digm is most clearly evident in the work ofSartre and his followers
within the French existentialist movement. In essence, they have
radicalised the phenomenological perspective which characterises
the subjective idealist’s position, viewing the individual as trapped
within the mode of existence which he creates. Ontologically, they
view the world as the product of individual consciousness: con-
sciousness is seen as being projected onto the. external through
acts of intentionality, thereby creating it. The subjective idealists
within radical humanism focus upon the pathology of intentional-
ity. whereby, in creating the external world, man separates himself
from his true ‘Being’.
The second avenue of discourse within radical humanism is
based upon the tradition of ‘objective idealism·, which received its
earliest and most comprehensive expression in the work of Hegel. 2
The Hegelian system of thought rests upon his first and perhaps
most significant work, The Phenomenology of Mind, which
investigates the ontological status of human knowledge. In this
book Hegel seeks to demonstrate how knowledge passes through a
series of forms of consciousness until a state of ‘absolute knowl-
edge’ is reached, wherein the individual is at one with the ‘absolute
spirit’ which pervades the universe. For Hegel. the ultimate reality
rests in ‘spirit’ (Geist). ‘Absolute knowledge’ rests upon the real-
isation that consciousness is ‘spirit’ and that the object of con-
sciousness is nothing other than itself. Hegel presents human
beings as living in a world characterised by a constant interplay
between individual consciousness and its objectification in the
external world. Consciousness and the external world are viewed
as two sides of the same reality. They are locked in a dialectical
relationship in which each defines and influences the other. 3 For
Hegel, everything is its own opposite. The truth lies on both sides
of every question in an antagonistic relationship to itself. As a
method of analysis the dialectic stresses that there is a basic
antagonism and conflict within both the natural and the social
world which, when resolved, leads to a higher stage of develop-
Radical Humanism 281
ment. This dialectical process is seen as a universal principle,
which generates progress towards the state of ·absolute knowl-
edge’ in which the distinction between subject and object is over-
come and human consciousness becomes aware of its location
within ‘absolute spirit’.
Hegel, like Fichte, saw individual consciousness as a focal point
for the understanding of the nature ofthe social world. However,
whereas in Fichte’s brand of subjective idealism, the individual
creates his world, in Hegel’s brand of objective idealism, indi-
vidual consciousness is subservient to an external pattern of uni-
versal reason which reflects the existence of a universal force or
spirit above and beyond the individual. Human consciousness and
human history, for Hegel, are to be understood in terms of the
unfolding of the universal spirit which will lead with certainty to
the perfect society. In his later years, Hegel increasingly saw the
Prussia of his day as the embodiment of the ‘absolute spirit’, the
perfect society in which the individual became subservient to the
state.
Hegel’s philosophy thus became wedded to a very conservative
political creed, and has been subjected to a wide range of inter-
pretation. Early on a deep cleavage of opinion arose between the
perspectives of the so-called ‘Right Hegelians’, who more or less
accepted Hegel’s system of philosophy in its entirety, and the
views of the ‘Left’ or ‘Young Hegelians’, who directed Hegel’s
system of thought to fundamentally different ends.
Prominent among the ‘Young Hegelians’ was the young Karl
Marx (1818-1883), who in essence inverted the Hegelian system
and united it with a critique of the society of his day. 4 1n sodoinghe
laid the basis for the development of a radical humanism in the
objective idealist mould. Marx employed Hegel’s historical per-
spective and dialectical method of analysis within the context of a
philosophy which placed the individual rather than ·absolute
spirit’ at the centre of the stage. Marx, along with the other Young
Hegelians. particularly Feuerbach, 5 argued that there was no abso-
lute above man. They argued that religion and the State were the
creations of man rather than reflections of any ‘absolute spirit’.
They emphasised that all objectifications encountered in the social
world were humanly created and pointed the way to an emancipat-
ory philosophy which stressed how individuals, through self-
consciousness, could create and thus change the society in which
they Jived. Marx, in particular, started from the premise of the
alienation of man. He saw the society of his day as dominating
human experience; objectified social creations reflected back
282 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
upon man as an alienating force, dominating his essential being and
nature. This point of view is expressed most forcibly in Economic
and Philosophical Manuscripts ( 1844), in which Marx demon-
strated how the capitalist system of production lay at the heart of
man’s alienation. 6 Whereas for Hegel alienation was a necessary
phenomenon on the path to self-realisation and ·absolute
knowledge’, for Marx it became a concept wedded to an attack
upon the status quo and the shortcomings of the totality of capital-
ism.
In later work Marx moved away from the idealist perspective to
one rooted in a more realist interpretation of the nature of the
social world. In The German Ideology ( 1846), written with Engels,
Marx sought to settle accounts with German idealism, and this
work is often seen as defining the so-called ‘epistemological break’
in Marx’s thought (Aithusser, 1969). From the point of view ofthe
analytical scheme presented here, it signifies Marx’s break with
radical humanism, and the beginning of a move towards radical
structuralism. The perspectives characteristic of the latter para-
digm, which are explored in Chapter 10, receive increasing atten-
tion in Marx’s Grundrisse and Capital.
Despite these early origins, the radical humanist perspective
remained dormant until the early 1920s, when Lukacs, under the
influence of neo-idealism, sought to re-emphasise the influence of
Hegel upon Marx. The discovery of the lost Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts some ten years later reinforced, and in
some ways legitimated, this interest, which found its expression in
a radical humanist critical theory. The growth of critical theory,
along with French existentialism, its subjective idealist
counterpart, can largely be understood as the radical response to
the renewal of interest in the idealist tradition which, as we have
seen from Chapter 6, emerged at the turn of the twentieth century.
The Structure of the Paradigm
As will be apparent from the above discussion, the radical human-
ist paradigm comprises the subjective and objective idealist strains
of thought, both of which have their origins in German idealism.
These constitute the principal philosophical perspectives. In addi-
tion, it is possible to identify the shaping influence of solipsism and
a category of anarchist thought which, though deriving largely
from Hegelianism, must be regarded as having followed a different
Radical Humanism 283
line in terms of detailed development. We may consider the work
located within this paradigm under four broad headings: (a) solips-
ism; (b) French existentialism; (c) anarchistic individualism; (d)
critical theory.
The broad interrelationships between these four categories of
social theory are illustrated in Figure 3.3.
Solipsism characterises the most subjectivist region of the para-
digm,just as it does within the interpretive paradigm. As we have
argued, it represents a philosophical position without sociological
equivalent, although some social theories, when taken to their
logical extremes, run dangerously close to what Sartre (1969) has
described as the ·reef of solipsism’. Since we considered this
perspective in Chapter 6, we will not discuss it further here.
French existentialism occupies the middle range of the para-
digm. It represents a perspective in the tradition of subjective
idealism. Deriving largely from the work of Fichte and Husser!, it
receives its clearest expression in the work of Sartre. This variety
of existentialism has influenced literary interpretation and some
psychiatry, as well as philosophy.
Anarchistic individualism, most usually associated with the
thought of Max Stirner, occupies a position in the least subjectivist
and most change-orientated region of the paradigm. It is a category
of thought which few subscribe to, but it is worthy of consideration
as an example of an extreme social theory which advocates radical
change, focusing upon individual consciousness as the basic unit
of analysis.
Critical theory represents the principal line of development in
the objective idealist tradition and is located in the least subjectiv-
ist region of the radical humanist paradigm. Within critical theory
we recognise three broad schools of thought based upon Lukac-
sian sociology, Gramsci’s sociology and the work ofthe Frankfurt
School. These differ considerably at a substantive level but are all
predicated upon Marx’s inversion of the Hegelian system of
thought.
We begin our detailed consideration of these categories of
thought with ‘Critical Theory’.
Critical Theory
Critical theory represents a category of sociological thought built
explicitly upon the work of the young Marx. 7 As a term it is often
284 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
used as a synonym for the work of the Frankfurt School of social
theorists, but we wish here to expand its usage to cover three
interrelated yet discrete schools of thought. The Frankfurt School
owes much to the work of Lukacs, which, in turn, bears a remark-
able similarity to that of Gramsci, so that these approaches have
substantial areas of overlap. Critical theory is a brand of social
philosophy which seeks to operate simultaneously at a philosophi-
cal, a theoretical and a practical level. It stands firmly in the
idealist tradition of critique deriving from Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason; its proponents seek to reveal society for what it is, to
unmask its essence and mode of operation and to lay the founda-
tions for human emancipation through deep-seated social change.
It is an overtly political philosophy, in that it stresses the need to
follow the logic of one’s philosophical and sociological analysis
with practical action of a radical kind. Lukacs, Gramsci and the
Frankfurt School, whilst sharing this overall aim, differ in the
nature and methods of their specific critiques. We will examine
each in turn.
Lukacsian sociology
In the early 1920s Georg Lukacs (1885-1974) sought to develop a
critical theory which offered an alternative to the orthodox Marx-
ism of his day. 8 In essence, he was concerned to overhaul its
socio-philosophical foundations, by emphasising and restoring the
strong Hegelian influence which characterised Marx·s work
before the so-called ‘epistemological break’ .In particular. Lukacs
sought to develop a theory of revolution which laid strong
emphasis upon the role of the proletariat and its class conscious-
ness in the overthrow of capitalist society. For Lukacs, as we shall
see, the proletariat provided a solution to the epistemological,
theoretical and practical issues facing Marxism in the 1920s.
Lukacs’s influence, like that of his one-time teacher Simmel, is
dissipated and fragmented. Lukacsian sociology consists not so
much of Lukacsians who are dogmatically faithful to his key texts,
problems and conceptualisations, as of a widely constituted body
of thought which uses, to a greater or lesser extent. Lukacs’s key
notions. This influence has been felt internationally. so that in
France Lukacs’s work has been developed by Lucien Goldmann,
in Britain by Meszaros and in the USA by Alvin Gouldner, who has
gone so far as to describe Lukacs as ‘the greatest Marxist theorist
of the twentieth century’ (Gouldner, 1976, p. x).
Radical Humani.~m 285
It is important to note, however, that Lukacs’ influence stems
from his early work and that his later output is steadfastly ignored.
In fact, Lukacs is a thinker whose work can be located on at least
three points on the subjective-objective dimension of our analyt-
ical scheme. He began his career in Hungary with the publication
of a series of books connected with the theory of the novel, in
which he acknowledges his position to be that of subjective ideal-
ism. Lukacs had been attracted to subjective idealism under the
influence of Dilthey’s approach to the Geisteswissenschaften and
Husserl’s phenomenology through his studies at Berlin and later
Heidelberg. At Heidelberg Lukacs was introduced to Hegel’s
work and by 1923 had produced a collected series of essays entitled
History and Class Consciousne.u. Based upon Hegelian objective
idealism, this work represented an attempt to emphasise the
humanist, more subjective aspects of Marxism some ten years
before the rediscovery of Marx’s Economic and Philosophical
Manuscripts of 1844. The reaction against History and Class Con-
sciousness within orthodox Marxism was such that Lukacs was
labelled an ultra-Leftist and a heretic insofar as Engels’ interpreta-
tion of dialectical materialism was concerned. 9 As a result, he
retracted his views on the link between Hegel and Marx and moved
to a position of middle-of-the-road materialism. This was done,
one might suggest without exaggeration, in order to survive in
Stalinist Russia at a time when the life expectancy of heretical
intellectuals was not high. In our terms, Lukacs made a complete
paradigmatic shift in the face of this threat. So total was his
embrace of materialism, and so unexceptionable his treatment of
it, that Lichtheim maintains that Lukacs’s writings in the thirties
were ‘the work of a man who had performed a kind of painless
lobotomy upon himself, removed part of his brain and replaced it
by slogans from the Moscow propagandists’ (Lichtheim, 1970, pp.
83-4).
In the sixties, however, relations with the West were ‘normal-
ised’ and Stalirl’s intellectual and political influence explicitly
rejected. Lukacs could assert again that History and Class Con-
sciousness, although flawed, was a book he was prepared to dis-
cuss and see republished under his name. This book has had a quite
crucial impact upon Marxism and is significant in that ‘material-
ism’ and the ideas of Engels play only a ·minor role. Lukacs
stresses the role ofsuperstructural factors within society and their
part in its transformation. Emphasis is placed upon consciousness,
ideology, literature and art, which are seen not as epiphenomenal
to the relations and means of production, but as quite central to any
286 Socio/()gical Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
understanding of capitalism. Consciousness, in particular, is
assigned key importance, for proleterian consciousness was cru-
cial to both Lukacs’s philosophy and his political methodology.
Class consciousness was central for Lukacs, because he saw it
as the escape route from a fundamental problem associated with
Hegel’s notion of alienation. For Hegel, alienati9ns occurred as a
result of the objectification of ‘ideas’ in the external world which
reasserted themselves within man’s consciousness. The ability to
move beyond alienation within this dialectical loop was provided
by the existence of an ‘identical subject-object’ which is ·at one’
with itself and not internally alienated. Hegel explained this
through the notion of ‘absolute spirit’; Lukacs replaced this notion
with that of the proletariat, which becomes an ‘identical subject-
object’ not alienated within itself if and when it acquires true or
‘imputed’ consciousness of the reality of capitalism and of its
ability to transform and overthrow it. 10 The class consciousness of
the proletariat then both provides a philosophical solution to one of
the Hegelian puzzles and represents the means whereby existing
society can be overthrown. By this device Lukacs seeks to evade
some of the primary epistemological and practical problems facing
Marxism.
The proletariat represents an identical subject-object not only in
its ability to transcend alienation, but also in its position in the
centre of the world historical stage, from which it can comprehend.
more than any other group or class, the ‘totality’ of capitalist
society. 11 Lukacs’s notion of ‘totality’ serves to unify His tory and
Class Consciousness, but it is a difficult concept to comprehend.
In a most general sense it refers to the Hegelian and Marxist view
that everything must be grasped as a whole; the whole dominates
the parts in an all-embracing sense. Marx used the notion of
‘totality’ to conceptualise the process of social change. ‘Stages’ in
societal development represent specific ‘totalities’, so that each
transformation of society replaces one totality by another. Capital-
ism is one such totality, quite distinct from feudalism or commun-
ism, and it is one in which objective and subjective elements are
combined within a complex, dynamic, structured process which
can only be comprehended holistically. This implies that one
cannot understand any aspect of capitalism without first under-
standing capitalism itself in its entirety. As we have seen, for
Lukacs it is the proletariat which has the ability to comprehend
society, to see the internal connections of the parts within
it and the whole network of relationships in the total social
structure. Once this totality is subjected to analysis it is unmasked
Radical Humanism 287
and stands revealed to all men in the moments of history before its
overthrow.
A central aspect of this notion of totality lies in the intimate
connection, first postulated by Hegel, between objective and sub-
jective dimensions within social reality, which are synthesised,
according to Lukacs, within the class consciousness of the pro-
letariat. The process whereby these dimensions are made falsely
discrete and differentiated, so that they are no longer seen as
‘identical’, Lukacs calls ‘reification’. This has clear links with both
Hegelian and Marxist views of alienation, which revolve in differ-
ent ways around the separation of objective and subjective factors.
Arguably, ·reification’ is one of the central concepts of History and
Class Consciousness, for it provides the focus for Lukacs’s
critique of the capitalist form of society. Reification, of course,
refers to the fact that whilst men in their day-to-day productive
activities create their social world, these activities and what results
from them are seen as divorced from men, as independent,
objectified ‘things’. Whilst objectification of man-made artefacts is
probably necessary and inevitable in all forms of social life,
Lukacs, like Marx, seeks to stress the political, constraining
aspects of reitication and the effective barrier it provides to the
comprehension, by the working class, of the totality in which they
live. Put simply, for Lukacs alienation in the form of reification is
something to be overcome, since it is the key to the release of the
explosive energies of the proletariat, which is so necessary for the
transformation and reconstruction of capitalist society.
In terms of our major analytical dimensions, Lukacsian
sociology occupies a position on the least subjectivist wing of the
radical humanist paradigm. Ontologically, it invokes the
omnipresent dialectic, since social processes are seen to consist of
the ‘objective’ acting upon the ·subjective’ and of the ·subjective’
acting in its turn upon the ‘objective’. For Lukacs, then, the
ontological nature of the world is neither crudely nominalist nor
crudely realist. Lukacsians invoke the dialectic to meet the need to
synthesise objective and subjective factors within an integrated
harmonious socio-philosophical approach. However, since
revolutionary proletariats have rarely, if ever, succeeded, and
since they have rarely understood the totality which is capitalism,
the achievement of the ‘identical subject~object’ through the
dialectic has remained an unfulfilled promise. 12
Epistemologically, Lukacs takes up an interesting position. He
maintained that Marxism was a revolutionary methodology rather
than a set of laws or truths. For Lukacs, truth was always histori-
288 Sociological Paradigms and Or!fanisational Analysis
cally specific, relative to a given set of circumstances, so that one
did not search for generalisations or the laws of motion of capital-
ism. For example, success within a revolution was not guaranteed
by the immanent dynamics of the capitalist system; there was no
law of nature or history which said that it would be so. Revolution
depended upon the actions of the working class and the tactics
developed by its leaders. Lukacsians, then. are not epistemolog-
ical positivists seeking general laws of societal development.
They are tacticians and methodologists of revolt and revolution
stressing the scope of action open to the proletariat. They indicate
the voluntarist aspects of life within capitalism, not the determinist
ones, continually pointing to the freedom of choice in the type of
class consciousness the proletariat accepts. Almost by an act of
will, the ·actual’ class consciousness of the vast majority of the
proletariat could become ‘true’ class consciousness through an
intellectual grasp of the totality of capitalism. Lukacsians seek to
change the world; their epistemology and methodology blend to
form a body of thought which seeks not general laws for future
contemplation but practical methods for radically transforming
society here and now.
Gramsci’ s sociology
The influence of Antonio Gramsci ( 1891-1937), an Italian Marxist
theoretician and political activist, has been rapidly increasing in
Western academic circles since the early 1960s, when English
translations of his work started to become more readily available.
His ·philosophy of praxis’ represents not only a rigorous social
theory, but also a political methodology for the working class.
Gramsci’s Marxism,like that of Lukacs, presents a radical human-
ist critique of capitalism and also a methodology for achieving its
overthrow. As Boggs has noted, ‘the Marxism that emerges from
the pages of Gramsci’s Prison Notebooks can be defined as a
critical theory that fuses elements of structure and consciousness,
science and philosophy, subject and object – a conception which,
however unsystematically formulated, is a marked advance upon
what, until the 1920s, was the paradigm of orthodox Marxism’
(Boggs, 1976, p. 32).
Gramsci’s ideas, which developed independently of Lukacs, are
extremely similar to the Hungarian’s. While studying at Turin,
Gramsci became influenced by the Hegelianism of Benedetto
Radical Humanism 289
Croce, which stood opposed to orthodox Marxism. Gramsci
believed that the Marxism of his day had lost its revolutionary zeal
through a misguided incorporation of positivist notions and a crude
almost mechanistic determinism which totally ignored the
voluntarist, practical aspects of working-class radical
potentialities. 13 He felt that what was needed was a truly dialecti-
cal theory which transcended the classical philosophical anti-
nomies of voluntarism-determinism, idealism-materialism and
the subjectiv«:>-objective. Such a theory would constitute a
‘philosophy of praxis’ which would represent a total world view, in
that it would transcend in itself, all previous philosophical
dichotomies and the philosophies based upon only one element
within them. As Gramsci put it, ‘the philosophy of praxis is “suffi-
cient unto itself’ in that it contains in itself all the fundamental
elements needed to construct a total and integral conception of the
world, a total philosophy and theory of natural science and not
only that but everything that is needed to guide life to an integral
practical organisation of society, that is, to become a total integral
civilisation’ (Gramsci, 1971, p. 406).
This ‘philosophy of praxis’, this truly ‘critical theory’, sought to
introduce into orthodox Marxism comprehension of and sympathy
for an understanding of ‘superstructural’ factors within capitalist
societies. Gramsci believed that power and domination in capital-
ism rested not only with the materially located means of coercion
and oppression, but also within men’s consciousness, through
‘ideological hegemony’ . 14 The ruling class, it was maintained,
always seeks to legitimate its power through the creation and
perpetuation of a belief system which stresses the need for order,
authority and discipline, and consciously attempts to emasculate
protest and revolutionary potential. For Gramsci, it was precisely
in the area of ideological hegemony in the schools, family and
workshop that capitalism was most likely to develop and increase
the unseen power of the ruling class, by attacking or infiltrating the
consciousness of the individual worker. But this is the crucial
weakness of ideological hegemony, too. For whilst hegemony
creates alienation, the individual worker is still his own theorist,
his own source of class consciousness, and is therefore the most
able to resist the forces of hegemony. It is from such ideological
resistance in the day-to-day life of workers that, for Gramsci,
revolutionary struggle and victory would first come. Conscious-
ness was not treated as being abstract and spiritual; it was a
concrete force for a political end.
Gramsci’s ·philosophy of praxis’ stressed practical involvement
290 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
in politics, and he, more than any of the other critical theorists,
became engaged in revolutionary activity. He aimed to produce
within Italian society a ·network of proletarian institutions’,
mainly factory councils, which were to be the foundations upon
which the workers’ State could be built. This activity of his
declined in the years after 1920, as the factory occupations which
had taken place were gradually ended. In 1926 Gramsci was
imprisoned by the Fascists for his role in the Communist Party,
and whilst in prison he wrote his Prison Notebooks, upon which
his reputation stands today.
Gramsci’s sociology is clearly orientated to action and radical
change. More than any other critical theorist, Gramsci stresses the
importance of ·praxis’ – the unification of theory and practice.
Whilst his conceptualisation of the critical problems within society
differs from those of other critical theorists, his location in terms of
the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme is
much the same. Like that of Lukacs, Gramsci·s approach to Marx-
ism stresses the Hegelian influence. Reality does not exist on its
own account in a strict materialist sense. but it exists in a historical
relationship with the men who modify it. His position reflects an
objective idealism in the tradition of critical theory and the work of
the young Karl Marx.
The Frankfurt School
The Frankfurt School’s claim on critical theory as its own property
owes much to Horkheimer’s famous essay of 1937 (reprinted in
Horkheimer, 1972), which drew a distinction between traditional
science and critical theory. In this, Horkheimer attempted to relate
Marx’s Critique of Political Economy to the German idealist tradi-
tion. Just as Marx attacked bourgeois political economy, so Hork-
heimer differentiated between the traditional approach to social
science and the critical theory perspective. Whereas traditional
science rested upon the distinction between the observer and his
subject and the assumption of value freedom, critical theory
emphasised the importance of the theorist’s commitment to
change.
The ‘Frankfurt School’ is now used as a generic title for a
well-known group of German scholars who have shared,
through their links with the Institute for Social Research, common
academic and political interests over a number of decades and in a
Radical Humanism 291
number of places. Under the influence of members such as Hork-
heimer. Adorno. Benjamin, Fromm. Kirschheimer, Lowenthal,
Marcuse, Habermas and many others, critical theory has
developed in many directions. 15 Based upon the ontological and
epistemological foundations reflected in the theories of the ‘Young
Hegelians’ particularly Marx, these critical theorists have forged a
wide-ranging perspective which has consistently aimed to reveal
the niiture of capitalist society for what it is. They have sought to
lay bare its underlying nature and set the basis for social change
through a revolution of consciousness. In this endeavour they
have subjected a wide range of social practice to critique in the
tradition of critical theory: they have provided thorough-going
Kulturkritik of the superstructure of capitalism. Positivist science,
modes of rationality, technology, the legal system, the family
unit, patterns of bureaucracy, language, art, music, literature,
the authoritarian personality and psychoanalysis have all been
subjected to critique from a radical humanist perspective. Thus
critical theory in the Frankfurt tradition embraces a polymathic
critical philosophy geared to emancipatory aims. As in the case of
Lukacsian sociology and that of Gram sci, it developed in reaction
to developments within orthodox Marxism, with its emphasis
upon historical determinism, and the general trend towards
totalitarianism in the USSR and Nazi Germany. It has also
developed in reaction to the positivist tradition in a more general
sense, particularly as reflected in the sociology of the functionalist
paradigm. In many respects, critical theory inverts the functional-
ist problematic, subjecting its tools and basic concepts to
thorough-going analysis. The antithetical stances of critical theory
and the functionalist paradigm are clearly illustrated, for example,
in the philosophical debates between Adorno and Popper, 16 and
the writings of the social theorists to be considered in this section
and the following chapter. In recent years critical theory has also
developed in opposition to trends in interpretive sociology and, as
we shall see, has sought to incorporate central notions in the
hermeneutic tradition within the bounds of its critical philosophy.
In contrast to the work of Lukacs and Gramsci, critical theory in
the Frankfurt tradition places far less emphasis upon political
action. Its proponents tend to be theoreticians rather than activ-
ists, and with the passage of time, the School has moved increas-
ingly towards philosophy and intellectual criticism rather than
revolutionary practice. Interestingly enough, after playing a rel-
atively minor role from the 1930s to the early 1960s, it came into
increasing prominence in the wake ofstudent revolution in France
292 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
and the counter-culture movement in the USA. Critical theory in
the Frankfurt tradition provided the ideal intellectual counterpart
to the ·revolution through consciousness’ sought by the idealists of
the early 1970s. Within the limited context of our present work it is
impossible to provide a detailed overview and analysis of the work
of the Frankfurt School as a whole. In the rest of this section,
therefore, we will focus upon the ideas of Herbert Marcuse and
Jfirgen Habermas, two of the School’s leading contemporary
theorists, whose work may be regarded as illustrative of the critical
theory perspective.
Marcuse has become well known for his scathing attack upon
the ‘one-dimensional’ nature of modern technological society,
particularly under capitalism. His work stands in the true
Hegelian-Marxist tradition of critical theory, and represents a
conscious attempt to present an emancipatory philosophy which
stands against both the phenomenology and the sociological
positivism characteristic of the sociology of regulation. For
Marcuse, phenomenology is inadequate, in that it ignores the
scope for, and influence of, human potentiality: positivism is also
inadequate, because of its false assumptions with regard to value
neutrality and its role as an instrument of control in the interests of
the status quo. Marcuse’s special contribution to critical theory
lies in his auempt to incorporate the ideas and insights of Freud
and Weber within the Hegelian-Marxist perspective characteristic
of much of the radical humanist paradigm. 17 His critique is most
forcibly expressed in two of his major works -Eros and Civilisa-
tion (1966; first published in 1955) and One-Dimensional Man
(1964).
In Eros and Civilisation Marcuse, following Adorno and
Fromm, seeks to develop the links between human personality and
the totality in which it is located, taking the Freudian concepts of
the ‘pleasure principle’ and the •reality principle’ as the starting
points for analysis. In the Freudian perspective civilisation rests
upon the repression of man’s internal drives. The •pleasure princi-
ple’ by which these drives are allowed to follow an unconstrained
search for satisfaction is seen as being subjugated in a civilised
society by the ‘reality principle’, according to which men are
prepared to postpone self-gratification in the interests of social
order. Marcuse starts from the position that tile •reality principle’
is a historically specific element. It is found of necessity only in
eras of scarcity, which presuppose the need to master nature in
order to survive. Marcuse maintains that scarcity is no longer a
characteristic of modern, technologically advanced societies,
Radical Humanism 293
since they are able to put an end to material shortages of all kinds.
The need to repress instinctive desires in such a society is thus no
longer so strong. However, it continues, and the level of repres-
sion we now find in the advanced industrial state is that of ‘surplus
repression’ – constraint over and above that which is necessary to
maintain civilisation. Surplus repression, perceived and retained
within the psyche, and supporting the system of production, is
seen by Marcuse as lying at the core of man’s psychological
domination by, and alienation within, the modern world. He sees
human emancipation from this dominating social order as being
brought about by ridding society of surplus repression, thus giving
more emphasis to the ‘pleasure principle’ expressed through libid-
inal drives. The message of Eros and Civilisation is an optimistic
one which views advanced technology as a force for liberation in
its ability to eliminate material scarcity.
In One-Dimenional Man Marcuse moves to a more Weberian
stance, though the direct links with Weberian sociology are not
specifically acknowledged or developed to any degree. 18 It is a less
optimistic book, in that the liberalising potential of Eros i$ seen as
undermined by the ‘one-dimensional’ nature of technological
societies, in which the centrifugal forces in human and social life
are dominated by technology and a one-sided commitment to
efficiency and material progress. Marcuse puts forward the thesis
that
technical progress, extended to a whole system of domination and
c~ordination, creates forms of life (and of power) which appear to
reconcile the forces opposing the system to defeat, or refute all protest
in the name of the historical prospects of freedom from toil and domina-
tion. Contemporary society seems to be capable of containing social
change – qualitative change which would establish essentially differ-
ent institutions, a new direction of the productive process, new modes
of human existence. This containment of social change is perhaps the
most singular achievement of advanced industrial society. (Marcuse,
1964, p. 10)
Marcuse argues that modern society is essentially totalitarian, in
that the technical apparatus of production and distribution
imposes itself upon the whole society. Its products and the indi-
viduals it ostensibly serves are moulded to serve its own internal
requirements. Technology is seen as a political force, a system of
domination which evolves new, increasingly effective and ·more
pleasant’ means of social control and cohesion. It produces the
‘one-dimensional’ society, in which there is a flattening out of the
294 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
difference and conflict between actuality and potentiality; in which
alternatives appear to be increasingly unrealistic; in which the
industrial system appears to have a logic of its own. Marcuse
argues that affluence and the creation of false needs impedes the
development of radical protest against the established order. Con-
sciousness is seen as being moulded and controlled through the
media. The welfare state and the ·warfare state’ are seen as
instruments for maintaining the level of consumption necessary for
sustaining a ‘happy’ workforce. All are seen as part of the ·one-
dimensional’ nature of the totality of modern technological soci-
ety, in which the logic of purposive rationality pervades modes of
thought and the organisation of the material world. For Marcuse, it
is the task of critical theory to investigate the roots of this
‘totalitarian universe of technological rationality’, and to examine
their historical alternatives, as a means of revealing unused
capacities for improving the lives of human beings.
Within the last few years the writings of Jurgen Habermas have
attracted increasing attention as his major works (Habermas,
1970a and b. 1971a and b, 1972. 1974 and 1976) have become
available in English translation. A leading exponent of contempor-
ary critical theory, his work is impressive for its range and ability
to utilise ideas and concepts drawn from a variety of perspectives
in the service of a radical humanism. In essence, his work can be
understood as a reaction against the shortcomings of interpretive
sociology and sociological positivism. Habermas believes that the
discourses of these two traditions are inadequate and that they
reflect and serve the interests of those who use them. He distin-
guishes between the empirical/analytic sciences of a positivist
orientation, which serve the interests of control; the histori-
cal/hermeneutic sciences of the phenomenological tradition,
which aim at understanding meaning without influencing it; and
the critical science perspective characteristic of the Frankfun
School, which aims both to understand the world and to change it
(Habermas, 1972). The critical theory which he favours incorp-
orates notions derived from Parsonian systems theory and its
latter-day German equivalents; hermeneutics, as reflected, for
example, in the work of Gadamer ( 1965); and various concepts
drawn from psychoanalysis. These diverse perspectives are
welded together into a critical theory which for Habermas must be
emancipatory, dialectical (in transcending the philosophical anti-
nomies of subject and object, observer and observed, fact and
value), and hermeneutic in its endeavour to understand the socio-
cultural world in which subjective meaning is located.
Radical Humanism 29.5
Habermas has attempted to shift the attention within Marxism
away from a consideration of the economic structure of capitalism
towards some of the key features of post-capitalist societies.
Whereas Marcuse has created a similar shift in attention by point-
ing towards the Weberian minotaur of purposive or technical
rationality, Habermas has stressed the structure of domination
embedded within our language and everyday discourse. For Hab-
ermas, the structure of language, its nature and use, provide a key
with which to unlock many insights into the fundamental mode of
operation of different social formations.
Recent developments in linguistics and ordinary language
philosophy demonstrate to Habermas’s satisfaction that today the
‘problem of language’ has replaced the traditional ‘problem of
consciousness’. In order to deal with these developments, he has
developed a theory of ·communicative competence’, which
borrows conceptualisations from hermeneutics in order to provide
the link between the political macro-structure and speech acts
within a context of symbolic interaction. Habermas develops the
concept of an ‘ideal speech situation’, in which ‘symbolic interac-
tion’ is possible since genuine consensus is arrived at between
parties in communication and is recognised as a consensus without
the operation of power. This ‘ideal speech situation’ is contrasted
with one characterised by ·communicative distortion’, in which a
supposed consensus is arrived at through discourse within the
context of an unequal power distribution.
Habermas illustrates the difference between these two situa-
tions through the concepts of ‘work’ and ‘interaction’. These are
seen as being fundamentally different categories of social life, with
purposive rationality dominating the former, and symbolic interac-
tion the latter. ‘Work’ is viewed by Habermas as the dominant
form of social action within capitalist industrialised society. He
sees this social form as based upon a purposive rationality which
stresses the importance of goal attainment, defined in terms of
means–ends relationships. The system develops technical rules
to guide action and modes of thinking, and places stress upon the
learning of skills and qualifications. Social life is compartmental-
ised and language is ‘context-free’. The rationalisation of the sys-
tem of action as a whole lies in the growth of productive forces and
the extension of power of technical control; ‘Work’ is seen as a
form of’communicative distortion’ characterised by asymmetrical
choice in the use of speech acts which reflects an unequal power
relationship.
‘Interaction’, on the other hand, is based on communicative
296 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
action between men in which shared norms develop and are
reflected in an intersubjectively shared ordinary language.
Implicitly, ‘interaction’ is seen as more typical of societies in the
pre-capitalist era, with their low levels of specialisation and rela-
tively undeveloped division of labour. ‘Interaction’ subsumes
‘labour’ as a cohesive and integral part of social life. Within this
social form there are reciprocal expectations about behaviour,
violations of which attract widely based social sanctions. The
norms and values which govern social affairs are acquired through
a process of role internalisation. The rationalisation of this system
of action lies in ·emancipation’, ‘individuation’ and the ·extension
of communication free of domination’ (Habermas, 1971b).
‘Interaction’ is seen as based upon ‘ideal speech’ situations in
which man is emancipated from ‘work’ and domination. Haber-
mas ‘s vision is of a post-modern world based on ‘interaction’, with
equal access to speech acts afforded to all and an equality of
opportunity within discourse. As Schroyer ( 1971) has noted, to the
extent that Habermas ‘s version of critical theory is based upon the
liberating potential of self-reflexive language, the new form of
critical science which he advocates is essentially based upon a
·pathology of communication’.
Despite the emphasis placed upon language as a focus for social
analysis, Habermas is also at pains to stress that the theory of
communicative competence must be linked to the fundamental
assumptions of historical materialism if it is to be adequate and
effective. In his more recent works, however, in which he deals
with the variety of crises which might affect modern society, the
crucial area is seen as the legitimatory superstructure of the
political system (Habermas, 1976). He argues that a permanent
economic crisis is no longer likely within advanced capitalism
because of the pervasive intervention of the State. Thus, Marx’s
analysis, with its dependence on class struggles and their relation-
ship to economic crises, is implicitly seen as outdated. For
Habermas, the key problem within advanced capitalism is the
‘legitimation crisis’. 19 Therefore, whilst recognising the analytical
importance of material production, his concern is primarily with
·superstructural’ factors, which are normally seen within orthodox
Marxism as epiphenomenal to any understanding of the economic
foundations of society. The materialist and idealist strands within
Habermas’s work are always yoked in a relationship of great
tension, and his theoretical orientation aims at their reconciliation.
Like Marcuse, Habermas has sought to update the Hegelian-
Marxist critique of contemporary society and, in so doing, has
Radical Humanism 297
drawn heavily upon developments taking place within the socio-
logy of regulation for the purpose of analysis. Their work clearly
demonstrates the way in which critical theory in the Frankfurt
tradition inverts the concerns and problematic of regulative social
theory, particularly that characteristic of the functionalist para-
digm. The functionalist tends to accept the norm of purposive
rationality, the logic of science, the positive functions of techno-
logy, and the neutrality of language, and uses them as building
blocks in the construction of supposedly value-free social theories.
The Frankfurt theorists concentrate upon demolishing this struc-
ture, indicating the essentially political and repressive nature of
the whole enterprise. They seek to demonstrate the way in which
science, ideology, technology, language and other aspects of the
superstructure of modern capitalist social formations are to be
understood in relation to the role which they play in sustaining and
developing the system of power and domination which pervades
the totality of this social form. Their function is to influence the
consciousness of the people living within it, with a view to eventual
emancipation and the pursuit of alternative forms of life.
The focus of critical theory upon the ‘superstructural’ aspects of
capitalist society is highly significant, in that it reflects the attempt
of theorists working within this tradition to move away from the
·economism· of orthodox Marxism and to elevate the Hegelian
concern for the role of the dialectic in social affairs. It is through
the dialectic that the objective and subjective aspects of social life
are thought to be reconciled. The ·superstructure’ of capitalist
society is of key interest to the critical theorists, partly because it is
the medium through which the consciousness of human beings is
controlled and moulded to fit the requirements of the social
formation as a whole. It thus lies at the interface between subjec-
tive and objective worlds. In early Hegelian-Marxist theory vari-
ous elements of the superstructure, such as religion and the State
were seen as the sources of human alienation. As Marx argued in
his early writings, these ‘intermediaries’ which exist between man
and his experience of the world ·mystify’, projecting a spurious
unity and order. He argued that they stood as seemingly indepen-
dent and alienating forces, created by man, yet reflecting back
upon him as independent presences. It was the task of the work of
the youthful Marx to ‘de-mystify’ through critique, in the true
idealist tradition.
The critical theorists reviewed in this section are all firmly
located in this intellectual tradition, and their work is to be under-
stood in similar terms. The relationship between key concepts
298 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
such as ‘totality’, ‘consciousness’, ‘alienation’ and ‘critique’
which seem to permeate Marx’s early work are not always spell
out and, indeed, do not always attract specific attention in the
writings of critical theorists. We wish to close our discussion here
by emphasising how crucial these four notions are to the per-
spective upon which critical theory is built, and we present Table
8.1 as a means of demonstrating some of the links which exist
between the work of the writers which we have considered here.
Table 8.1
Critical theory: central concepts and orientations
Totality
The notion that any understanding cl society must embrace in their entirety
the objective and subjective worlds which characterise a given epoch. Total-
ity embraces everything; it has no boundary. An understanding of this
totality must precede an understanding cl its elements, since the whole
dominates the parts in an all-embracing sense.
Consciousnrss
The force which ultimately creates and sustains the social world. Con-
sciousness is internally generated but influenced by the forms which it
assumes through the process of objectification and the dialectic between
subjective and objective worlds.
Alirnation
The state in which, in certain totalities, a cognitive wedge is driven between
man’s consciousness and the objectified social world~ so that man sees what
are essentially the creations of his own consciousness in the form of a hard,
dominating, external reality. This wedge is the wedge cl alienation, which
divorces man from his true self and hinders the fulfilment cl his poten-
tialities as a human beina.
Radical Humanism 299
Table 8.1 (continued)
Critiqu~
In their critique of contemporary society, critical theorists focus upon the
forms and sources of alienation, which they see as inhibiting the possibilities
of true human fulfilment. The various exponents of this perspective
approach it in somewhat different ways, at varying levels of generality.
Lukacs focuses upon the concept of r~iflcation. which provided the
socio-philosophical solution to the epistemological and practi-
cal problems facing Marxism in the 1920s.
Gramsci focuses upon the notion of id~oloRical h~g~mony as reflecting
a belief system among the proletariat fostered by the ruling
class. In his view, the belief system stressed the importance of
ord~r. authority and disciplin~. and was propagated throulh
institutions such as the family, school and workplau.
Marcuse through his notion of on~-dim~nsional man, focuses attention
upon the alienating characteristics which he sees as being
embedded in the growth of purposiv~ rationality within
advanced industrial societies. In particular. he emphasises the
alienating role of t~chnoiORY· sci~nc~ and logic. These sup-
plement other forces identified in his earlier work relating to
the excessive repression of libido and the maintenance of a
happy work force throulh the creation of qf}lu~nc~ andfals~
~~~~ds.
Hab~rmas focuses upon the role which lanfluag~ plays as an alienating
force in all aspects of soclal life. His theory of communicativ~
comp~unc~ seeks the common denominator in human interac-
tion, whether verbal, sexual, productive or whatever, and
seeks to show bow in contemporary Western societies there is
an element of communicativ~ distortion which lies at the heart,
and most basic level, of man’s alienation.
Anarchistic Individualism
Like so many large-scale inte11ectual movements, anarchism is not
so much a relatively unified, political and theoretical position as a
clustering of perspectives. Anarchistic individualism represents
one such perspective, advocating total individual freedom,
untrammelled by any form of external or internal regulation. 20
Anarchistic individualism is a doctrine closely associated with
Max Stimer, a German school-teacher, whose inversion of the
Hegelian system of philosophy went far beyond that of Marx in its
rejection of all social institutions and the notion of the •absolute’ in
any form. 21 His position resembles that of the existentialists in
300 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
some respects, since his notion of the ego comes close, as we shall
see, to Sartre’s concept of ‘being-for-self. Stirner emphasised the
primacy of individual existence and totally rejected any search
for universal laws governing social life. Far from sharing the
Hobbesian vision of the cataclysmic ·war of all against all’ as the
crucial problem facing man, Stirner celebrates such a ‘war’ as the
solution toman’sproblems. Only through a ‘union of egoists’- men
who pursue ruthlessly, without constraint, their own individual
interests – can true release and human freedom be attained.
Stirner studied at Berlin under Hegel and became associated
with the Left-Hegelians about the same time as Karl Marx. On
the publication of his principal work, The Ego and His Own
(1907), Stirner became branded as a fanatic and a dangerous
revolutionary, not only by those committed to maintenance of the
status quo, but also by his less violently disposed anarchist and
socialist colleagues. His book focused upon what we might now
term the forces of the id and argued that only by releasing these
from all restraints and restrictions could true human freedom be
attained. Human freedom, for Stirner, is freedom not for the
human species but for the individual ego. The Hegelian concept of
individual freedom within State control is totally overthrown in
this perspective, which emphasises emancipation through the
entire removal of the State and its trappings.
The State, in Stirner’s eyes, was the greatest enemy of human
freedom, since it represented a regulatory collectivity which, in
de-emphasising the individual’s happiness, stood for all he
rejected. Its overthrow and demolition was envisaged not through
revolution but through rebellion and insurrection. In The Ego and
His Own Stirner suggests:
Revolution and insurrection must not be looked upon as synonymous.
The former consists in an overturning of conditions, of the established
conditions or status, the State or society, and is accordingly apolitical
or .wcial act; the latter has indeed for its unavoidable consequence a
transformation d circumstances, yet does not start from it, but from
men’s discontent with themselves,is not an armed rising, but arising of
individuals, a getting up, without regard to the arrangements that
spring from it. (Woodcock, 1977, p. 167)
Stimer saw such a rebellion as being initiated by ‘the union of
egoists’, not acting in concert in any organised way, but as indi-
viduals carrying out disruption of an ostensibly similar order.
Anarchist individualism meant putting anarchist notions into prac-
tice immediately, without awaiting any societal transformations.
Radical Humanism 301
The core issue was the cognitive disposition of the individual, his
attitude of mind, rather than structural constraints or any external
ideological hegemony. Stirner·s book is in the tradition of objec-
tive idealism and focuses upon the subjective dispositions within
the individual as the starting point for any radical transformation of
society, in which, indeed, the whole notion of society is itself
threatened.
Anarchistic individualism has never made a great impact,
although it enjoyed a brief revival with the artistic resurgence of
interest in individualism of all kinds before World War I. There are
few anarchists today who accept or adhere to Stirner·s position,
although Woodcock maintains that ‘as late as the 1940s I encoun-
tered a group of anarchist working men in Glasgow for whom
[Stirner’s book} was still a belated gospel’ (Woodcock, 1975, p.
91).
However. many of Stirner’s ideas have been incorporated into
the canons of ·mainstream’ anarchism, and his emphasis upon
·cognitive liberation· and ‘freedom for the ego’ have been taken up
by writers such as Murray Bookchin (1974). Although himself
committed to the more objectivist ·anarchistic communism’,
Bookchin echoes some of Stirner’s feelings when he emphasises
the subjective aspects which link our understanding of society with
the individual psyche. As he suggests, ‘anarchists have probably
given more attention to the subjective problems of revolution than
any other revolutionary movement. Viewed from a broad his-
torical perspective, anarchism is a libidinal upsurge of the people,
a stirring of the social unconscious that reaches back, under many
different names, to the earliest struggles of humanity against
domination and authority’ (Bookchin, 1974, p. 19). 22
Stirner’s work is a political document, designed as an exhorta-
tion to individuals of all classes to rebel. The nature of the rebellion
envisaged, with its total commitment to the rejection of all exist-
ing social institutions, identities anarchistic individualism as one of
the most extreme theories of radical change that one is likely to
encounter. Since there is scarcely any room for ‘society’ in such a
conceptualisation, this brand of anarchism has come in for much
criticism, particularly from Marxists. Anarchistic individualism’s
rejection of the ·sociological’ category places it outside the Marx-
ist concern for replacing one form of society with another through
revolutionary means. For many Marxists, anarchism of this kind is
seen as essentially reactionary. From our point of view here, it
provides a good example of a philosophy of radical change
emphasising the imponance of subjectivist factors. Whilst not
302 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
claiming many sociological adherents, it serves as an illustration of
an extreme perspective within the radical humanist paradigm.
French Existentialism
French existentialism reflects a philosophical perspective firmly
located in the subjective idealist tradition deriving from the work
of Fichte and Husser!. In terms of our subjective-objective
dimension, it occupies a position between solipsism and the objec-
tive idealism characteristic of critical theory. Phenomenology and
existentialism are often seen as related schools of thought, and are
sometimes considered identical. 21 In line with our distinction be-
tween the perspectives characteristic of the sociologies of regula-
tion and radical change, we find it helpful to emphasise the distinc-
tion between them. Existential phenomenology characteristic of
the work of Schutz, as discussed in Chapter 6, is quite different
from the existentialism characteristic of the work of Sartre, to be
discussed here. Whilst from a distance they may appear to focus
upon similar areas of enquiry and to lend each other mutual sup-
port, their basic orientations are fundamentally distinct. Whilst the
work of Schutz focuses upon the social construction of everyday
life as a basis for understanding (almost as an end in itseiO, the
existentialism of Sartre is concerned with the understanding of the
pathology of such constructions, with a view to changing them.
Existentialism differs from phenomenology in its vigorous human-
ism and its political commitment to the desirability of change in the
existing social order.
However, it would be wrong to suggest that existentialist
philosophers and social theorists comprise a coherent school of
thought in the manner, for example, of the Frankfurt School.
Rather, existentialism stands for a somewhat broad and amorph-
ous movement, comprising theorists who acknowledge a common
debt to Kierkegaard. Among these theorists Jean-Paul Sartre has
emerged as by far the most important, and it is through a considera-
tion of his work that we wish to characterise the essential orienta-
tion of French existentialism as an illustration of the existentialist
movement as a whole.
It is the early writings of Jean-Paul Sartre which have established
him as a leading exponent of the French existentialist mode of
thought. Sartre’s philosophical and literary works are extremely
diverse and wide-ranging, and they testify to the direct influence of
Radical Humanism 303
a number of social theorists including Hegel, Husserl, Kier-
kegaard, Lukacs and Marx. 24 His existentialist views reflect a time
when the influence of the first three of these theorists was in the
ascendency and are expressed most forcibly in Being and
Nothingness, first published in 1943, and Existentialism and
Humanism, published just a few years later in 1948. In his later
work Sartre moved to a philosophical position consonant with a
Hegelianised form of Marxism, and the concepts emerging from
his existentialist works are harnessed in a critique of society in the
mould of a critical theory reflecting a more objective idealist view
of the world. This is mostevident,forexample,in Sartre’sCritique
of Dialectical Reason (1976).
Sartre defines existentialism in the tradition of Kierkegaard as
the conviction that ‘existence comes before essence’; this belief
implies that ·we must begin from the subjective’ – that is, the
individual located within existence is the fundamental concern of
the philosophical enterprise. It precedes any emphasis of interest
in the ‘essences’ of the ‘real’ world and in the make-up of external
reality. The individual is actively involved in the creation of his
world and not a mere observer or reflection of it. As Sartre puts it,
we do not ‘survey the world’ but rather, ‘are engaged’ by it. Sartre,
in the tradition of phenomenology, takes the consciousness of man
as a starting point for his philosophical enquiry and weds it to
humanism and a basic concern for human freedom. It is this theme
which preoccupies his early work. For Sartre, existentialism is
humanism, and he is concerned to demonstrate the way in which
·nothingness’ and ‘freedom’ are essential aspects of the ontologi-
cal relationship between subjective and objective worlds as
experienced by individual human beings.
Before one can get to grips with Sartre’s concept of ‘nothing-
ness’ and its intimate relationship with ‘freedom’, it is essential
first to understand his three concepts of ‘modes of being’, which
have their origins, more or less, in Hegel’sPhenomenoiORY. Sartre
identifies ‘being-in-itself (en-soi), the world of external reality or
the stuff of which this real world is made up; ‘being-for-self
(pour-soi) which denotes consciousness and the inner subjectivity
of men; and ‘being-for-others’. Sartre’s problem, like that of so
many idealist philosophers before him, is the nature of the rela-
tionship, if any, betweenpour-soi and en-soi • between conscious-
ness and reality. His treatment of this central issue rests upon the
idea that consciousness is always ohomethinR in the real world, so
that the relationship between pour-soi and en-soi is that between
the knower and the known. This relationship, however, depends
304 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
upon a distance or gap between the real world and the conscious-
ness of individual men, so that the separation between them is
always evident. Such a vacancy Sartre calls ‘nothingness’, for
herein lies the ability to conceptualise that which does ~•ot exist.
‘Nothingness’ allows men to think beyond the limitations of today
and this place and to imagine non-objects, new forms of social life
or any type of alternative reality in the future. ‘Nothingness’
represents freedom, therefore, in the sense that it is here that man
has total freedom to dream and to hope. The measure of a man’s
freedom, then, is the degree to which he can conceive of non-
objects and can look to potential actions rather than be constrained
by the pre-existing actuality of the en-soi. For Sartre, individuals
who retain the ability to conceive of ‘nothingness’ are free and
unconstrained, their lives bounded only by what amounts to a
voluntarist theory of action or, more precisely, interaction.
Sartre’s position is interactive not so much in a sociological
sense but in terms of man’s consciousness, in a way faintly redo-
lent of Mead’s phenomenological concepts of the ‘I’ and ·me’. To
myself, I am obviously pour-soi (a ‘being-for-self), since I am a
conscious, sentient being. Howe~er, to other men, I am but a real,
external, physically concrete object – a ‘being-in-itself (en-soi).
This paradoxical relationship between human beings in social con-
texts creates the third category of being – ‘being-for-others’,
which is the interface between different individuals’ conscious-
ness in which en-soi and pour-soi meet in day-to-day interaction.
It is from this analysis that Sartre’s notion of ‘bad faith’ emerges.
Sartre uses this concept to refer to situations in which self-imposed
constraints are placed upon human freedom; in which men come to
accept external constraints from outside their pour-soi and conse-
quently reduce the ·nothingness’ or gap in consciousness which
forms the core of their humanity. To the extent that men accept a
determining, outside interference, their internal ability to concep-
tualise ‘nothingness’ is reduced. Sartre illustrates this clearly by
indicating the way in which men often become imprisoned by their
roles. Instead of being ‘free’, we become what we are, just as an
oak tree is an oak tree. A waiter is a waiter and a father is a father,
incapable of being radically free and unable to escape at will from
the roles which they play. Sartre maintains that to live in one’s role
is a form of self-deception. We know that as conscious individuals
it is false to see ourselves from outside ourselves as objects, but
this process is part of an attempt to escape from the problem of
‘anguish •. As Sartre puts it. ‘We flee from anguish by attempting to
apprehend ourselves from without as an Other or as a thing •
Radical Humanism 305
(Sartre. 1966. p. 82). It is in the flight from ‘anguish’ that ‘bad
faith’ appears. Sartre’s most famous example of this is his con-
sideration of the waiter in Being and Nothingness:
Let us consider this waiter in the cafe. His movement is quick and
forward. a little too precise, a little too rapid. He comes towards the
patrons with a step a little too quick. He bends forward a little too
eagerly: his voice, his eyes, express an interest a little too solicitous for
the order of the customer. Finally there he returns, trying to imitate in
his walk the inflexible stiffness of some kind of automaton while
carrying his tray with the recklessness of a tightrope walker by putting
in a perpetually unstable, perpetually broken equilibrium which he
perpetually re-establishes by a light movement of the arm and hand. All
his behaviour seems to us a game. He applies himself to chaining his
movements as if they were mechanisms, the one regulating the other:
his gestures and even his voice seem to be mechanisms: he gives
himselfthe quickness and pitiless rapidity of things. He is playing, he is
amusing himself. But what is he playing? We need not watch long
before we can explain it: he is playing at heing a waiter in a cafe. There
is nothing there to surprise us. The game is a kind of marking out and
investigation. The child plays with his body in order to explore it. to
take inventory of it: the waiter in the cafe plays with his condition in
order to realiu it. This obligation is not different from that which is
imposed on all tradesmen. Their condition is wholly one of ceremony.
The public demands of them that they realise it as a ceremony: there is
the dance of the grocer, of the tailor, of the auctioneer, by which they
endeavour to persuade their clientele that they are nothing but a grocer,
an auctioneer, a tailor. A grocer who dreams is offensive to the buyer,
because such a grocer is not wholly grocer. Society demands that he
limits himself to his function as a grocer ,just as the soldier at attention
makes himself into a soldier-thing with a direct regard which does not
see at all, which is no longer meant to see. since it is the rule and not the
interest of the moment which determines the point he must fix his eyes
on (the sight ‘fixed at ten paces’). There are indeed many precautions to
imprison a man in what he is, as if he lived in perpetual fear that he
might escape from it, that he might break away and suddenly elude his
condition. (Sartre, 1966, pp. 101-2)
The waiter here is playing at a role in a way which implies a
fundamental alienation from his true being. The concept of ‘bad
faith • which it is intended to illustrate has much in common with
Marx’s concept of alienation, in which individuals meekly accept
their social situation to the detriment of their true human poten-
tialities. No doubt, for Max Stirner. Sartre’s ‘bad faith’ would
succinctly describe the constraining phenomenon his ‘union of
egoists’ would seek to overthrow.
306 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Whilst he has attracted few really committed disciples, Sartre’s
influence has been widespread. His brand of existentialism has
been important as far as certain developments in psychoanalytic
theory are concerned, particularly through the work of R. D.
Laing, and as a result of the influence of his novels and other
literary work. However, the reaction to Sartre’s work in general
has been somewhat confused. His shift in intellectual position to a
form of Hegelianised-Marxism, his writings and activities in con-
nection with the magazine Les Temps Modernes, and his political
activism, particularly since the events of 1968, have drawn criti-
cism and indeed abuse from many sides. Despite all this, however,
his contribution to the development of French existentialism is
beyond dispute and stands as a major achievement in its harness-
ing of the phenomenological approach in the service of radical
humanism.
The U nder1ying Unity of the Paradigm
The work of theorists located within the radical humanist paradigm
is underwritten by a common concern for the freedom of human
spirit. Radical humanists focus upon human consciousness within
the context of the totality which characterises a particular social
formation. There tends to be a concern with what may be
described as the ·pathology of consciousness’, by which men come
to see themselves as trapped within a mode of social organisation
which they both create and sustain in their everyday lives. Radical
humanists are concerned with understanding the manner in which
this occurs, with a view to setting human consciousness or spirit
free and thus facilitating the growth and development of human
potentialities.
Like theories characteristic of the interpretive paradigm, radical
humanist approaches to the study of social affairs are rooted in a
subjectivism which recognises the precarious ontological status of
the social world. Whilst varying in their degree of subjectivism, the
different schools of thought within the paradigm are at one in
emphasising that reality is socially created and socially sustained.
Thus their perspective stands in fundamental opposition to
approaches characteristic of the radical structuralist and
functionalist paradigms. This opposition is clearly reflected in the
ontological and epistemological divides within Marxism and the
rare, but generally hostile, exchanges between social theorists
Radical Humanism 307
adhering to the radical humanist and functionalist traditions. The
divisions between the latter two are compounded by the fact that
the ontological and epistemological distinctions are wedded to
fundamentally different conceptions of the nature of society. They
are divided in terms of both the dimensions of our basic analytical
scheme. According to the radical humanist, functionalist social
theorists create and sustain a view of social reality which
reinforces the status quo and which is to be understood as
but one aspect of the network of ideological domination which
pervades contemporary Western society. The functionalist
usually dismisses radical humanists as Utopian radicals hell-bent
upon fanning the flames of revolutionary consciousness, or as
mindless existentialists who will not or cannot adjust to the
world of everyday ‘reality’ and accept the inevitable march of
‘progress’.
Many contemporary radical humanists have developed their
critique of society with the functionalist perspective firmly in mind
and, consequently, are able to attack it on many fronts. Thus, as
we have seen, within critical theory specific attention has been
paid to demonstrating the role of science, logic, rationality,
technology, language and other aspects of the superstructure of
capitalism as vehicles of cognitive domination, which, from the
radical humanist perspective, act as alienating ‘intermediaries’
which present a barrier to the achievement of full humanness. In
the tradition of the work of the young Marx, the radical humanists
are concerned with the alienation of modern man. They start from
the premise that man lives in a world which constrains rather than
develops his full range of possibilities, and they are committed to
providing an analysis and critique of the way in which this occurs.
It is a critique which reflects a complete inversion of the functional
problematic and the view of society which it represents.
It is the emphasis which is given to consciousness in general and
alienation in particular which distinguishes the substance of the
radical humanists’ thought from that of the radical structuralists.
Theorists in both these paradigms are committed to revolutionary
changes in society but, as we shall see, the radical structuralists
tend to place much more emphasis upon deep economic and politi-
cal ‘structures’ in their analysis. As we shall see, within the con-
text of the radical structuralist paradigm, the concepts of ‘totality’.
·structure’, ·contradiction’ and ·crisis’ take over as unifying fea-
tures from those of ‘totality’, ·consciousness’, ‘alienation’ and
‘critique’, which can serve as a convenient shorthand for the
common concerns not only of critical theory, but also of the
308 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
essential orientation of the radical humanist paradigm in more
general terms.
Notes and References
I. For a general discussion of Fichte’s work, see the introduc-
tion to Fichte (1970).
2. For a discussion of the Hegelian system of thought, see Hegel
(1931) and Kaufmann (1966).
3. For a discussion of the Hegelian use of ‘dialectic’, see
Kaufmann (1966), pp. 167-75.
4. For a discussion of Marx’s views at this time, see McLellan
(1975 and 1976).
5. The influence of Feuerbach is of considerable importance
and calls for much greater attention than it is possible to give
here. For more extensive discussion, see Althusser (1969)
and McLellan ( 1976).
6. For a further discussion of Marx’s theory of alienation. see
Avineri (1968), McLellan (1976), Meszaros (1970b) and
Oilman (1971).
7. For a further discussion of critical theory, see. for example,
Jay (1973), Connerton (1976) and O’Neill (1977).
8. As will become evident from our discussion in Chapter 10,
orthodox Marxism in the 1920s was based upon an extreme
interpretation of the radical structuralism characteristic of
Marx’s later work.
9. For a discussion of Engels’ influence on the interpretation of
Marx’s work, see Chapter 10.
10. For a discussion of Lukacs’s concept of the dialectic, see the
article by Meszaros in Parkinson (1970).
11. For a discussion of Lukcic~·s use of ‘totality’, see Lukacs
(1971) and the article by Pascal in Parkinson (1970).
12. For a further discussion of this point in relation to the con-
sciousness and action of the working class, see Mann ( 1971).
13. See, for example, Gramsci’s attack on positivism in ‘Critical
Notes on an Attempt at Popular Sociology’ in Gramsci
(1971).
14. For a discussion of this important concept, see Gramsci
(1971) and Boggs (1976).
IS. Jay ( 1973) provides an excellent analysis of the role of these
key figures in the development of the Frankfurt School and
its work.
Radical Humanism 309
16. Fora good discussion, see, for example, Frisby(l972). Inter-
estingly enough, the work of both Popper and Adorno is
directed against totalitarianism; their different responses
reflect their different paradigmatic perspectives.
17. The possibility of a marriage between the ideas of Marx and
Freud has received increasing attention in recent years. For a
discussion of some of the issues involved, see Rieff (1959)
and Brown (1973).
18. See, however, Marcuse (1968) and Habermas (1971b).
19. In LeRitimation Crisis ( 1976), especially Part II, ‘Crisis
Tendencies in Advanced Capitalism’, Habermas deals with
four types of crisis, of which one is ·economic crisis’ in the
classic Marxist mould.
20. For a discussion of anarchism in general and ‘anarchistic
individualism’ in particular, see Woodcock ( 1975 and 1977).
21. Woodcock comments upon this most extraordinary man in
the following terms:
STIRNER MAX, ( 1806-1856). Kaspar Schmidt was a German
school-teacher, employed in a Berlin academy for young ladies,
when he wrote his single important book The Ef(o and His Own.
This extremely individualist anarchist was closely associated
with the Radical Young Hegelians who clustered around Arnold
Ruge and Bruno Bauer, and took the nom-de-plume of Max
Stirner because of the loftiness of his brow (stirn). The victim of
an unhappy marriage, he became in his later years a hack trans-
lator. and The ERo and His Own, which influenced Nietzsche,
remains his only work of real significance. (Woodcock, 1977, p.
379)
22. Bookchin’s paper ‘Listen Marxist’ (1974) also makes inter-
esting reading in this respect, whether or not one is being
directly addressed.
23. For a discussion of some important differences as well as
links between the two schools of thought, see Lee and
Mandelbaum (1971).
24. For a discussion of Sartre’s life and work, see Murdoch
(1967), Spiegelberg (1965), Warnock (1965) and Natanson
(1973a).
9. Anti-Organisation Theory
In the previous chapter we described the nature of the radical
humanist paradigm. tracing its broad line of development and the
way in which its basic tenets are reflected in contemporary schools
of thought. As a paradigm within the context of social theory as a
whole it must have some relevance for the study of organisations.
but as yet it is almost completely unexplored from this point of
view.• We intend toargueherethat iftheimplications of the radical
humanist paradigm are developed in relation to the study of organ-
isations. the result will be an anti-organisation theory. Since the
radical humanist perspective stands in fundamental opposition to
that of the functionalist paradigm, reflecting a complete inversion
of assumptions about the nature of science and of society. anti-
organisation theory will stand in fundamental opposition to con-
temporary organisation theory.
From any perspective characteristic of the radical humanist
paradigm, organisations as middle-range phenomena have a very
precarious ontological status. At best, they are allowed an exist-
ence as intersubjective, reified social constructs, by means of
which individuals relate to the world in which they live. The
perspectives of the various schools of thought within the paradigm
vary quite significantly on this score; consequently, they have
differential contributions to make to an anti-organisation theory.
The solipsist and existentialist perspectives reflect a form of
•subjective idealism’ which does not allow for the existence of
organisations outside the realm of individual consciousness. The
intersubjective status of the concept of organisation is extremely
problematic. Whilst Sartre’s notion of’bad faith’ has a great deal to
offer towards an understanding of the relationship between indi-
viduals and what are regarded as their occupational roles, 2 subjec-
tive idealist perspectives have a limited contribution to make to a
theory of organisations as such. Within the context of objective
idealism the scope is much greater, and we wish to argue here that
it is within the bounds of critical theory that the radical humanist
anti-organisation theory has the most scope for development.
Critical theory contributes to our anti-organisation theory in a
Anti-Organisation Theory 311
number of ways. As will be clear from our analysis presented in the
previous chapter, the critical theorist is concerned with four core
concepts: totality – the notion that the social world must be
understood in its entirety before one can comprehend its parts;
consciousness – the force which ultimately creates and sustains
the social world; alienation – the cognitive wedge between con-
sciousness and totality and which divorces man from his true
being; critique – the analysis ofthe sources and forms of alienation
which inhibit the possibilities of true human fulfilment.
These concepts emphasise the central importance of the rela-
tionship between consciousness and totality, and reduce the status
of organisations to middle-range reified social constructs which
intervene between the consciousness of individual human beings
and their appreciation of the nature of the totality in which they
live. Organisations are examples of the ‘intermediaries’ which,
from a radical humanist perspective, contribute to man’s aliena-
tion from his true being. It is through the critique of such alienating
‘intermediaries’, which reflect and sustain particular modes of
social life, that critical theory bas sought to contribute its own
particular brand of insight into our understanding of the relation-
ship between man and society. Within the context of this critique,
emphasis tends to be placed upon revealing the nature and signifi-
cance of the ·spirit’ or mode of organisation reflected in a particu-
lar totality; understanding this mode of organisation in terms of the
principles which it reflects is given greater priority than detailed
analysis of its specific empirical forms. Thus whilst organisations
as reified social constructs lend themselves as a focus for critique,
it is always within the context of the mode of organisation which
they reflect.
The critical theory perspective thus suggests an approach to
organisational analysis which is an anti-organisation theory on a
number of counts. It is anti-organisation in that it views organisa-
tions as having a precarious ontological status. It is anti-
organisation in that it stresses the importance of the mode of
organisation reflecting a particular totality, rather than the impor-
tance of organisations as discrete middle-range units of analysis
worthy of attention in their own right. It is anti-organisation in the
sense that it views the reitied social constructs labelled ·organisa-
tions’ as alienating ‘intermediaries’ which serve to mystify human
beings in their attempt to comprehend and appreciate the nature of
the totality in which they live. The perspective constitutes an
anti-organisation theory in that its presuppositions stand in fun-
damental opposition to those of functionalist organisation theory;
312 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
as we shall see, anti-organisation theory inverts the functionalist
problematic on almost every count. It is also an anti-organisation
theory in the sense that it views functionalist theory as itself
serving to mystify our understanding of the significance of organ-
isations within everyday life. Functionalist organisation theory, in
focusing upon the exclusive study of middle-range reifications, is
seen as perpetuating the divorce between human consciousness
and totality. It is seen as an alienating ‘intermediary’; as an objec-
tification of mind which hinders man’s appreciation of the totality
in which he lives. Organisation theory is viewed, from the perspec-
tive of anti-organisation theory, as an alienating force, concerned
with the wrong issues and the wrong problems, as an essentially
conservative enterprise which underpins the present system of
ideological domination within contemporary society.
In its present state of development, anti-organisation theory can
be regarded as no more than embryonic in form,.at best comprising
a few isolated and fragmentary case studies and discussions which
have approached the study of organisational activities from a
perspective consonant with critical theory. We shall return to
these in a later section of this chapter. As a means of illustrating the
general issues with which anti-organisation theory would concern
itself, we will review here a part of the burgeoning body of litera-
ture which seeks to provide a critique of contemporary culture.
Whilst approaching this endeavour in a variety of ways, and often
claiming no specific allegiance to an intellectual tradition of any
kind, much of this literature stands firmly in the radical humanist
mould. It echoes the concerns and issues which have occupied the
thoughts and attention of many idealist social philosophers who
have pondered upon the human condition. Much of this literature
has surfaced as part of the general resurgence of interest in the
subjective aspects of human existence reflected, for example, in
the developments in existentialism, phenomenology and eth-
nomethodology which took place during the 1960s and 1970s. Its
particular trademark is that it combines its interest in the subjec-
tive with a radical critique of contemporary society.
We have in mind here the work of writers such as lllich ( 1973)
and Dickson (1974) on alternative technologies; Castaneda (1970)
and Pirsig (1976) on alternative realities; Roszak (1969) and Reich
( 1972) on counter-cultures; and Meakin ( 1976) and Anthony ( 1977)
on work as ideology. In different ways these works advocate
alternative forms of culture or ‘alternative realities’ to those which
predominate within advanced capitalist societies. They range over
a variety of disciplines, assuming the form of novels or academic
Anti-Organisation Theory 313
texts, and are increasingly found on the recommended reading lists
of social science courses, as reflecting relevant and interesting
points of view which do not quite tit the orthodoxy in the particular
subject area. However, as we hope to demostrate in the next
section, they have much in common with the perspective of critical
theory, particularly as reflected in the writings of Marcuse ( 1964),
Habermas ( 197Ia and b) and Gouldner ( 1976). In the style of our
nasc\!nt anti-organisation theory, these writings seek to foster and
point the way towards alternative realities through a radical
humanist critique of the status quo. In so doing, they identify
many of the concerns and constituent elements which a more
systematically stated anti-organisation theory might seek to
embrace.
Towards Alternative Realities
Many contemporary writers have pointed to the need. for alterna-
tive technologies as a means of creating and sustaining alternative
cultural forms. David Dickson in Alternative Technology and the
Politic.t ofTeclrnical Change ( 1974), for example, seeks to demon-
strate the links between technology, politics and social control,
particularly those reflected in the nature of advanced technology
and capitalism. It is Dickson’s general thesis that the problems
associated with contemporary technology might be resolved
through the design of an ‘alterative technology’ which ·would
embrace the tools, machines and techniques necessary to reflect
and maintain non-oppressive and non-manipulative modes of
social production, and a non-exploitative relationship to the
natural environment’ (Dickson, 1974, p. II). However, in contrast
to functionalist theorists who argue in favour of alternative tech-
nologies as a means of creating alternative modes of social life,
Dickson emphasises the nece~sity of creating political change as a
basis for technological and social change. In his view, alternative
technologies on any significant scale can only be developed within
the framework of alternative societies. Alternative technologies
do not of themselves create alternative societies. This is seen as
essentially a political task. As he puts it, ‘the struggle for emanci-
pation from an apparently oppressive and manipulative technol-
ogy coincides with the struggle for emancipation from oppressive
political forces which accompany it. To argue that technological
change is per se able to bring about a more desirable form of
314 Sociological Paradigms and Organi.tatimral Analysis
society is technological determinism carried to Utopian extremes’
(Dickson, 1974, p. 13). Technology, for Dickson, operates both
materially and symbolically to reinforce a particular form of social
organisation and control. It is seen as functioning politically to
promote, within capitalism, the interests of a dominant class,
particularly through ideologies which stress technology’s role
within society as a natural, progressive, inevitable and essentially
non-political force. For Dickson, contemporary technology is
inextricably linked with the fundamental nature of the totality of
capitalism, and its significance and influence can only be under-
stood in these terms.
Ivan lllich, in his book Tools for Conviviality (1973), focuses
upon a related theme, arguing that society is in need of a ‘convivial
reconstruction’ to restore what the development of technology has
destroyed. lllich sees social and institutional development as hav-
ing passed through two watersheds. At one stage knowledge and
technique were utilised in the solution of specific problems; at
another, the success of technique was exploited to ~emonstrate
the existence of problems and needs previously unrecognised. He
presents technological progress, backed by the interests of institu-
tional elites, as fostering demands for further technological prog-
ress, through which men become en!tlaved by the tools which were
originally intended to serve their needs. Illich argues that the crisis
which has been created can only be solved
if we learn to invert the present deep structure of tools: if we give
people tools that guarantee their right to work with high, independent
efficiency, thus simultaneously eliminating the need for either slaves or
masters and enhancing each person’s range of freedon. People need
new tools to work with rather than tools that ‘work’ for them. They
need technology to make the most of the energy and imagination each
has. rather than more well-programmed energy slaves. (lllich, 1973,
p. 23)
Society, in lllich’s view, needs to be reconstructed to facilitate
‘conviviality’ – autonomous and creative intercourse among per-
sons and in their relations with their environment. The convivial
society is characterised by technologies which ·serve politically
interrelated individuals rather than managers’, and by ‘responsibly
limited tools’ (lllich, 1973, p. 12). Like Dickson, Illich points to the
political dimension of technology. and calls for a political inversion
of the ‘managerial fascism’ which characterises our present mode
of organisation.
In The Greening of America ( 1972) Charles Reich calls for a
Anti-Organisation Theory 315
change in contemporary society through a revolution in con-
sciousness based upon the values and ideals of the counter-culture
youth movement of the late 1960s. Reflecting the unbashed optim-
ism of the period, Reich boldly claims:
There is a revolution coming … It will originate with the individual and
with culture. and it will change the political structure only as its final
act. It will not require violence to succeed, and it cannot be success-
fully resisted by violence. It is now spreading with amazing rapidity,
and already our laws. institutions and social structure are changing in
consequence. It promises a higher reason. a more human community
and a new liberated individual. Its ultimate creation will be a new and
enduring wh~leness and beauty – a renewed relationship of man to
himself, to other men. to society. to nature and the land. (Reich, 1972,
p. II)
Reich’s vision is similar in many ways to those of Dickson and
lllich, in that it seeks a restoration of the non-material and spiritual
elements of man’s existence, and aims to confer on .science and
technology a background and supportive role. In contrast to their
work, however, Reich places his faith in revolution through revela-
tion, as opposed to critique and political action. His book may be
seen as reflecting the aspirations rather than the analysis of the
radical humanist perspective.
Theodore Roszak’s book of es·says, The Making of a Counter
Culture (1969) reflects similar themes, which are specifically
linked to a variety of analytical perspectives characteristic of the
radical humanist paradigm. His central focus is the struggle be-
tween •youth culture’ and the ‘technocracy’ characteristic of con-
temporary industrial, bureaucratised society. He examines the
way in which the technocracy seeks to define reality in terms of an
objective form of consciousness in ways which appropriate the
whole meaning of ‘reason·, ·reality’, ·progress’ and ‘knowledge’,
and speculates upon the ways in which this enterprise can be
ovenhrown as a means of restoring human values and poten-
tialities to a central place. His vision is of a community of love and
affection, supponed by honourable and enjoyable labour, in which
personal vision replaces objective knowledge and the scientific
expen is deposed by someone akin to the Indian village shaman.
The question of access to an alternative reality is also explored
by Carlos Castaneda in the Teachings of Don Juan ( 1970) and its
sequels, which report Castaneda’s attempt to investigate and
understand the world of don Juan, a Yaqui Indian sorcerer or ·man
of knowledge’. The book neatly counterposes alternative realities,
316 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
and illustrates the impossibility of embracing ·non-ordinary’
modes within the logic of the scientific ethos which dominates
Western culture.
In Robert Pirsig’sZen and the Art of Motor-Cycle Maintenance
( 1976) similar themes are presented, but they are explored in a
radically different way. Whereas in Castaneda’s work the focus is
upon the difference in world view of a Yaqui Indian and a Califor-
nian anthropology student trying to get his Ph. D., in Pirsig’s novel
it is upon the struggle between the competing world views which
exist within the central character’s own psyche. Pirsig describes
the way in which ·romantic’ and •cJassical’ forms of understanding
compete for dominance in the protagonist’s attempt to negotiate
and define everyday ·reality’. Whilst apparently remote in its
implications for an academic anti-organisation theory, Pirsig’s
work, like that of Castaneda, Roszak, Reich, lllich, Dickson and
many others who have addressed similar themes, provides good
illustrations of the essential concerns of the radical humanist
ethos. The struggle is between competing realities and the means
by which they can be achieved. The conflict, crudely put, is
between the commonly accepted and all too ·real’ dominant reality
of the functionalist paradigm, and the aspirations and vision of the
radical humanist paradigm. Understood in these terms. all the
works considered above counterpose functionalist and radical
humanist perspectives and. in their different ways, clearly illus-
trate the inversion of fundamental assumptions upon which the
two paradigms are built and from which they derive their distinc-
tive perspectives upon the social world. They illustrate very
clearly, too, how the two paradigms define alternative realities.
Returning to literature more consciously located in an
·academic’ frame of reference, in that its mode of presentation
adheres to a more conventional •scientific’ format, we find similar
themes expressed. Gouldner, for example, in The Dialectic of
Ideology and Technology (1976) focuses upon ideology as a •sym-
bol system’, and seeks to demonstrate the intimate relationship
between ideology and technology as modes of social domination.
His work draws heavily upon critical theory, particularly the work
of Habermas. As will be apparent from our discussion in the
previous chapter of Habermas ‘s theory of ·communicative distor-
tion’. there are many links between his distinction between work
and interaction and the ideas of the writers considered here.
Gouldner, in the tradition of critical theory, talks of present-day
‘technocratic consciousness’ and its links with science, positivism
and technology, and contrasts it with ·romanticism’. His call is for
Anti-Organisation Theory 317
an overthrow of the technocratic mode of consciousness and the
establishment of more humanly orientated forms of life.
The distinctions between work and interaction, and ·scien-
tific/technological rationality’ and ‘romanticism’, as modes of
social life are also reflected in the recent writings of two British
theorists who have investigated conceptions of work and its social
context. Though approaching the issue from the perspectives of
quite different disciplines and adopting different styles, their writ-
ings reflect strikingly similar themes. David Meakin in Man and
Work (1976) approaches the subject from a literary perspective,
focusing upon the literature and culture of industrial society. Peter
Anthony in The Ideology of Work (1977) approaches the subject
from the perspective of an industrial relations theorist, and traces
the relationship between attitudes to work and technological pro-
cess. Both writers seek to provide a radical critique of the nature of
work in contemporary society, and of the possible alternatives:
they favour the romantic ideals of writers such as John Ruskin and
William Morris, who stress the creative possibilities typical, for
example, of the craft ethic. Meakin calls for a new ideology in
which the distinction between ·art’ and ‘work’ is lost, and Anthony
calls for an end to the ‘ideology of work’ and its replacement by an
ideology in which ·pleasure’ and ‘use’ are the two guiding princi-
ples.
Table 9.1 seeks to counterpose the main concepts which the
writers reviewed here utilise to present the key dimensions of the
alternative realities with which they are concerned. Clearly, there
is a considerable convergence of interest in their work, which will
become all the more apparent from a reading of the original texts.
However, even from the necessarily abbreviated and somewhat
superficial reviews presented here, clear themes characteristic of
the radical humanist perspective are quite evident.
First, there tends to be an overriding concern with what Mar-
cuse has described as the ·one-dimensional’ nature of modern
society. These various writers tend to present society as reflecting
a form of totalitarianism based upon the all-pervasive influence
and control offactors such as work, rationality, science and tech-
nology, which shape, channel and control men’s consciousness.
Their concern is to articulate the nature of this influence and
control, and stress that this totalitarianism makes men oblivious to
alternative modes of consciousness and existence. They are con-
cerned to demonstrate that alternatives are available. Alternative
realities, alternative cultures, alternative technologies, alterna-
tives to work – these lie at the centre of their attention.
318 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Table 9.1
Autltor
Dickson
lllich
Gouldner
Roszak
Reich
Pirsig
Castaneda
Habermas
Anthony
Meakin
Key dimensio-. of alternative rea&ties
Conc~pt us~d to cltart1ct~ris~
tit~ crucial asp~ct of r~ality
witltin conumporary capitalist
social formations
‘Industrial capitalism’
‘Productivity’
‘Technocratic consciousness’
‘Objective consciousness •
‘Consciousness II’
Classical mode of thought
Ordinary reality
‘Work’
‘Work’
‘Work’
Conc~pt us~d to cltaracuris~
tit~ Cl’llcial asp«t of r~ality
within ndtHIIi~naud mod~s
ofb~ing
• Alternative technology’
‘Conviviality’
‘Romanticism’
‘Personal vision’
‘Consciousness Ill’
Romantic mode of thought
Non-ordinary reality
‘Interaction’
‘Craft’
‘Creativity’
Second, this literature tends to be characterised by a posture
which is fundamentally opposed to positivist science. Science as
viewed from the perspective of the functionalist paradigm is totally
rejected; the idea of progress through science completely inverted.
Functionalist science is seen as creating rather than solving
societal problems. Such problems are viewed as being the result of
the ideology of domination upon which positivist science is based.
The radical humanist sees the scientific ethos which has been used
to conquer man’s environment as having dominated man himself.
Man is seen as the prisoner of science and the calculative rational-
ity which it reflects. Problems characteristic of, for example, the
ecological crisis figure prominently in the analysis of the ills of
modern society, to the otherthrow of which the radical humanist is
deeply committed. In place of science-dominated Western soci-
ety, they advocate a return to a situation in which man lives in
harmony with nature, as opposed to controlling and exploiting
nature. For this purpose they often look to philosophies of the past
or to those characteristic of different cultures. Hence the interest
in the Eastern way of life, for example, and the philosophy of Zen.
The search is for a vision of a world uncontaminated by the ethos of
science and the worship of ‘progress’. In line with C. P. Snow’s
celebrated distinction between the scientific and literary modes of
thinking, (the ‘two cultures’ which exist within advanced Western
societies), the body of literature under discussion often looks to
art, drama, literature and the cinema for its references. It is to this
Anti-Organisation Theory 319
culture that they turn for the source of their problems, analysis and
solutions. Put simply, their humanism is derived from and reflects
the humanities.
A third major theme in this literature is reflected in its ·objective
idealism’ .It views man-made notions and artefacts as objectified
products of human consciousness which, within industrial society,
come to be seen as alienating forces which lie outside man’s
control. In line with the tradition of critical theory, it is the alien-
ated state of man in modern society that is ultimately the focus of
attention.
These three related themes clearly reflect the romanticism and
idealism which lie at the roots of the radical humanist philosophy.
Alternatives to the present are sought in the past: windmills not
power stations, craftsmanship not work, Zen not instrumentality.
In its idyllic view of the past, this literature has a great deal in
common with the communist vision of the young Marx, according
to which men ·do one thing today and another tomorrow ..• hunt in
the morning, fish in the afternoon, rear cattle in the evening,
criticise after dinner,just as I have a mind, without ever becoming
hunter, fisherman, shepherd or critic’ (Marx, 196S, pp. 44-5).
This idyllic and Utopian image of society is underwritten by the
assumption that scarcity is no longer a problem. Indeed, the notion
of scarcity is seen as part of the system of ideological domination
within which man lives. It is the overthrow of the concept of
scarcity that man’s salvation is, in large part, seen to lie, enabling
him to live in harmony with nature whilst avoiding the physical
deprivations commonly associated with a return to previous
modes of life. The abolition of the concept of scarcity is seen as an
avenue leading to the attainment of man’s release from the domina-
tion of existing modes of social life.
Towards an Anti-Organisation Theory
In addition to the general work discussed in the previous section, a
small number of isolated papers and case studies have been pro-
duced which can best be understood as attempts to articulate
elements of the radical humanist approach to the study of organisa-
tions. Here again, these works have found their way on to the
reading lists of many courses in organisation analysis and, again,
stand in somewhat anomalous relationship to much of contempor-
ary theory. We have in mind work such as that produced by
320 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Beynon on Working for Ford (1973), Clegg on Power, Rule and
Domination ( 1975) and a paper produced by the People and Work
team atthe Open University(Esland et al, 1975).1n addition, there
are signs towards the end of Organisational Work by Silverman
and Jones (1976) of a move towards a perspective consonant with
critical theory. All this literature is British. No doubt comparable
European and American studies also exist, though it has not
attained a level of any prominence within the British context.
All these works are characteristic of the critical theory perspec-
tive and reflect many of the ideas articulated in other contexts by
writers such as Marcuse and Habermas. The links, however, are
often far from explicit, and it is quite clear that some of the writers
have arrived at their respective positions by quite different routes.
The People and Work team express their views in general terms,
emphasising that sociology is in need of a critical perspective.
They criticise the sociology of organisations as being too little
concerned with the study of organisations within a socie-tal con-
text, and as being too coy in its treatment of alienation and depriva-
tion. They seek to replace industrial sociology, occupational
sociology and the sociology of organisations with a ‘critical sociol-
ogy of work’. Their aims in this respect are clearly illustrated in the
following quotation:
a critical sociology concerned with the question of contemporary forms
of domination and alienation has to take on increasingly the enorm-
ously self-evident legitimacy of applied positivism and technologised
control, just as workers who attempt to move from economism to
conflict over control and authority within the enterprise have to be
prepared, in their attack on managerial ·rights’, to question the whole
system of inter-connected legitimations and assumptions of which any
particular “right’ is a part. The combination of rational planning with
politically neutralised bureaucracies serving the goal of economic
progress has done much to desensitise workers and sociology itself as a
way of understanding contemporary society. It is important that the
sociology of work regains … political and social awareness … and
that work activity and experiences should be seen in the context of
more comprehensive critiques of capitalist society and mass capitalist
culture. ( Esland et al, 1975, p. 32)
These concerns are clearly related to the perspective of critical
theory. Their anti-positivism, their emphasis upon totality, aliena-
tion, domination and control, and their desire to develop a critique
of capitalist culture, are all firmly set within the context of critical
theory, with the focus upon ‘work’ as the central subject of
analysis. 1
Anti-Organisation Theory 321
The work of Beynon (1973), Clegg (1975) and Silverman and
Jones (1976) focuses upon very specific issues, and in essence
presents empirical case studies which can be interpreted as con-
sonant with a critical theory, though the links with this are, again,
undeveloped. Beynon in Working for Ford focuses upon the car
workers’ experience of factory work, and the •factory-class con-
sciousness’ which arises along with their understanding of the
work situation and the realisation that they are being exploited by
the management. Clegg’s Power, Rule and Domination presents
an analysis of power relationships on a construction site, and
argues that they can only be fully understood as part ofthe rules of
the game laid down within the context of a wider •form oflife’. The
ideas and analysis reflected here are firmly in line with the her-
meneutic critique offered by Habermas and other critical theorists
interested in the role of language in the construction of social life.
Silverman and Jones’s Organisational Work also moves in this
direction, with their analysis of the hierarchical nature of the
language of organisational life, which has much in common with
Habermas’s theory of •communicative distortion’.
The development of a systematic critical theory of organisations
calls for a clear and explicit statement of basic assumptions,
priorities and concerns. Only against such a background can the
significance of the above studies be fully appreciated and the
ground rules laid for more systematic research within this area.
Such a development calls for a movement away from the reactive
stance to functionalism reflected in much of the literature which
has been produced so far, and for an explicit statement of the
anti-organisation theory which derives logically from the underly-
ing tenets of the radical humanist paradigm. In order to facilitate
this, Table 9.2 seeks to spell out some of the characteristics which
an anti-organisation theory might assume, so that organisation
theorists can begin to appreciate the substantive implications of
critical theory and the way in which it is fundamentally opposed to
the orthodox view of organisational reality. It is a perspective
which challenges, at a most fundamental level, the very basis of the
enterprise in which most contemporary organisation theorists are
engaged. In order to illustrate the strength of this challenge, we
seek to juxtapose elements of the defining characteristics of anti-
organisation theory with those of organisation theory. Table 9.2
identifies sixteen issues on which these perspectives are funda-
mentally opposed. The list is not exhaustive, but it does go a long
way towards delineating the precise ways in which the competing
frameworks diverge, and serves to emphasise the basic coherence
322 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
and breadth of anti-organisation theory as a perspective in its own
right. Insofar as anti-organisation theory is launched in a reactive
and partial sense, it almost cenainly appears as an attack upon
functionalism and as a negative and destructive force. However, it
is clear that, viewed from a wider vantage point, it is coherent.
integrated and self-sustaining, since it draws upon a fundamentally
different intellectual tradition. Its existence is not predicated upon
the functionalist perspective per se; it does not feed upon it in any
way and can operate within an intellectual preserve which is
entirely its own. If offers an alternative view of the reality of
organisational life.
Table 9.1
Towards the definition of anti-organisation theory
Organisation Anti·orgomsorion
lhrory throry
I. Paradigmatic location Functionalism Radical humanism
2. Intellectual source of Science The humanities
problems, metaphor and
eltample
3. Conceptual focus Organisations Mode of social
(level of analysis) organisation
4. Society conceptualised as: System Totality
.s. Focus of ontology Structures Consciousness
6. Predominant socio- Widespread lack of Universal alienation
economic problem job satisfaction
7. Generic term for Industrial society; Capitalism, One
contemporary society post-industrial dimensional society;
society corporate state;
managerial fascism,
etc.
8. Man’s relationship to Exploitative/ Harmonious
nature seen as: competitive
9. Predominant means of Industrial, factory- Alternative
production based technology technology (non-
urban, small-scale,
co-operative)
Anti-Organisation Theory 323
Table 9.2 (continued)
OrRanisation Anti-orRanisation
theory theory
10. Concern for maximisation Productivity Human creativity
of
II. Technology seen as a: Positive or neutral Neptive forc:e
force
12. Current status of Universal sc:arcity Widespread
production and shortaaes economic surplus
available withia
capitalism
13. Predominant productive Work/labour Craft
mode advocated
14. Predominant mode of human Loaic Intuition
cognition
IS. Human behaviour in accord Purposive rationality Value rationality
with
16. Ethico-political stance To understand: To understand:
possibly to alter the certainly to induce a
system new totality
Stated in more specific terms, anti-organisation theory seeks to
demonstrate the sources of alienation inherent within a totality,
which converge in an organisational context. It provides a sys-
tematic critique, in the tradition of critical theory, by identifying
the factors which impinge upon and dominate human conscious-
ness in the form of seemingly objective social forces over which
man appears to have no form of direct control. Among the factors
worthy of critique, the following are usually accorded consider-
able importance:
I. The concept of purposive rationality as the dominant and
most valued mode of cognition within organisational con-
texts.
2. Rules and control systems which monitor the exercise of
rational action.
3. Roles which constrain and confine human activities within
narrowly defined limits.
4. The lanRUaRe of organisational life which reflects a situation
of ‘communicative distortion’.
324 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
S. The ideological mechanisms through which the worker is
habituated to accept the roles, rules and language of the
work place.
6. The worship of technology as a liberating force.
7. Reification, such as the concepts of work, leisure, scarcity
and profitability, which serve to mystify the relationship
between workers and the world they live in.
Anti-organisation theory, through critique, seeks to unmask the
alienations reflected in the organisational mode of life. It seeks to
stress how such alienations are intimately linked with the nature of
the totality in which they are located, and hence to point towards
the desirability of alternative modes of reality and social life.
At the present time anti-organisation theory exists in an
embryonic form. Our above analysis provides no more than the
roughest of frameworks upon which future developments might be
based. It seeks to move towards the definition of the range of
territory over which the fully-fledged anti-organisati~n theorists
might be expected to roam. The perspective as a whole can only be
developed systematically against the intellectual background of
the radical humanist paradigm. It is necessary, therefore, for the
anti-organisation theorist to~be thoroughly conversant with the
German idealist tradition and the way in which it is reflected in the
various schools of thought discussed in Chapter 8. It is not some-
thing which can be developed in isolation as a practical critique of
contemporary organisation theory. The tenets of anti-organisation
theory are set so fundamentally against the principles which
underpin the functionalist paradigm that the writer, researcher or
student who seeks to align himself with the former, must, if he is to
be consistent with his underlying assumptions, end up by rejecting
the latter. To embrace radical humanism involves the rejection of
organisation theory as a naive, misconceived and politically dis-
tasteful enterprise. It involves entering another paradigm, another
intellectual world – indeed, an alternative reality.
Notes and References
I. At first sight the literature relevant to the field of organisation
studies which advocates a radical form of humanism may
seem truly extensive. However, as will be clear from our
analysis of the functionalist paradigm, the word ‘radical’ is
Anti-Organisation Theory 325
much overused, in that many theorists who profess a radical
point of view do little more than take a mildly deviant stand-
point in relation to their immediate reference group. All the
so-called neo-human relations theorists who advocate a
humanist approach to the design of organisations, techno-
logy, etc., do so from a perspective firmly grounded in the
functionalist problematic. Their humanism represents a plea
for reform rather than a well-founded and consistent theoret-
ical perspective committed to an alternative view of society.
For the most part, their perspective is grounded in a philos-
ophy of social engineering and piecemeal reform within the
problematic which defines the status quo. Once this seem-
ingly ‘radical’ literature is placed on one side, the field is
dramatically reduced in size. Even prominent ‘radical’ works
such as those of Berger et al (1974), Ellul (1964) and Douglas
( 1970a) disappear from the sociology of radical change on this
score.
Radical humanism, as defined here, refers to a well-
grounded intellectual tradition whose basic problematic is
described and defined in some detail in the previous chapter.
2. For a discussion of ‘bad faith’ and occupational roles, see
Eldridge (1971), pp. 158-65.
3. In point offact, the papers presented in Esland et al. (1975)
range beyond the bounds of critical theory, and include
f”aper~ characteristic of the functionalist and radical struc-
turalist perspectives. The overall picture which they present
is thus somewhat inconsistent in terms of underlying meta-
theoretical perspectives.
10. Radical Structuralism
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The radical structuralist paradigm is rooted in a materialist view of
the natural and social world. It is based upon an ontology which
emphasises the hard and concrete nature of the reality which exists
outside the minds of men. The social world, like the natural world,
is seen as having an independent existence. Its facti city is taken for
granted; it is seen as being material rather than spiritual in nature.
This ·realist’ view of social reality is supplemented by an essen-
tially positivist epistemology which is geared to discovering and
understanding the patterns and regularities which characterise the
social world. Little distinction is drawn between the assumptions,
aims and methods of the natural and social sciences. The radical
structuralist tends to see himself as engaged in ·science’, and in
this endeavour shares many points of similarity with the approach
of the functionalist. However, for the radical structuralist, ·sci-
ence’ is made to serve fundamentally different ends.
Radical structuralism is aimed, first and foremost, at providing a
critique of the status quo in social affairs. It is a perspective which
is concerned not just to understand th~ world, but to change it. The
underlying focus of interest tends to be upon the structures within
society, and particularly the way in which they interrelate. Writers
within the paradigm tend to view society as composed of elements
which stand in contradiction to each other. They are interested in
the effects of these contradictions, particularly with regard to the
role which they play in creating economic and political crises.
Radical structuralism is a view which focuses upon the essentially
conflictual nature of social affairs and the fundamental process of
change which this generates. Deep-seated conflict is viewed as the
means by which man achieves emancipation from the structures of
the social world in which he lives. It is a sociology of radical change
but, in contrast to that of the radical humanist paradigm, one which
tends to place relatively little direct emphasis upon the role and
nature of man as an individual human being. However,common to
both is the underlying aim of man’s release from the various forms
Radical Structuralism 327
of domination which are seen as characterising contemporary
industrial society.
The intellectual foundations oft he radical structuralist paradigm
were laid in the second half of the nineteenth century in the work of
Karl Marx. As a theoretical perspective it has had a chequered
history, in that Marx’s work has been subjected to a wide range of
interpretations, vulgarisations and misunderstandings. Nowhere
is this better illustrated than in the term ‘Marxism’. Whilst from
within it represents a ·heterogeneous and widely differentiated
body of social theory, from outside it is often identified as a narrow
and polemical political creed. Analytically, there are many
varieties of Marxism. As we have seen the work of the young Marx
had a major impact upon certain developments within the radical
humanist paradigm. In this chapter we intend to trace the effect
which his later work has had upon the radical structuralist p&.ra-
digm. As we shall see, the contemporary structure of Marxist
thought within this paradigm is extremely complex, calling for
careful analysis in terms of the two dimensions which define our
analytical scheme. In essence, the radical structuralist paradigm
constitutes a body of social theory as complex, conceptually rich
and widely differentiated as any of the other three paradigms
considered in this work.
As we have noted in our discussion of the radical humanist
paradigm, in his early work Marx was principally involved in a
reinterpretation of the Hegelian system of philosophy, inverting its
central tenets to produce a radical critique of contemporary Ger-
man society. With the publication of The German Ideology in 1846,
however, a distinct move away from his earlier preoccupation with
and commitment to Hegelian idealism can be detected. In particu-
lar, he sought to turn from the objective idealism which character-
ised his earlier work to a position reflecting a more materialist view
of the social world. It represented the beginning of a general
movement away from philosophical concerns to those of political
economy, and an attempt to develop the outlines of a radical social
theory capable of meeting contemporary positivism on its own
ground. It signified a redirection of his overall thought which was
to receive a fuller and more explicit treatment in later work such as
the Grundrisse, and Capital, written in the late 1850s and early
1860s. 1 These works were produced after more than a decade of
active but unsuccessful political involvement which embraced the
·vear of Revolutions’ of 1848. In essence, they reflect Marx’s
attempt to obtain ·self-clarification’ on the operation of the histor-
ical process and the economic structure of the capitalist mode of
328 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
production. In terms of analysis, they place emphasis upon con-
ceptualisations derived from political economy: the idealist con-
cerns of his early work receive much less emphasis. Although
there is considerable debate about the extent to which the Hegelian
influence was to stay with Marx throughout his life, a claim is often
made that his writings in the period after 1850 reflect a major
epistemological break when compared with his earlier work. In
terms of our analytical scheme, they involve a shift in perspective
away from the radical humanist and towards the radical structural-
ist paradigm.
Given the wide range of interpretations which have been placed
upon Marx’s later work, it is extremely difficult to provide any
authoritative, clear-cut statement of his precise perspective. Our
plan in the rest of this section, therefore, will be to provide an
overview of Marx’s central concerns and then to proceed to dis-
cuss some of· the widely different interpretations placed upon
them. As we shall see, these interpretations have dictated-in large
measure the precise development of the radical structuralist para-
digm.
At the most basic level, Marx’s model of society, as expressed in
his later work, consists of two elements -the ·superstructure’ and
the ‘substructure’. The metaphor ‘substructure’ was used to refer
to the economic base of society, in which production was given the
central role. His analysis of this distinguished between (a) the
·mode of production’ (capitalism, feudalism or communism); (b)
the ‘means ofproduction’ (technology,land, capital, labour); and
(c) the ‘relations of production’ (producers and non-producers,
owners and non-owners, the class system). Marx argued that
within each mode of production there were particular associations
between the ‘means’ and the ‘relations’ of production. The term
‘superstructure’ was used to denote other, non-economic factors
within society, such as the state, religion, art,literature, etc. These
were seen, ‘in the last instance’, as being determined by the nature
of the substructure, though in turn influencing it to some degree.
Within the Grundrisse and Capital the notion of ‘contradiction’
was given a central role in Marx’s analysis of the operation of
society. As will become apparent later in the chapter, this notion
has been interpreted in many ways. 2 Common to these interpreta-
tions is the idea that society contains within it elements which
stand in antagonistic relationships one to another, and which gen-
erate conflicts which eventually lead to the breakdown of the mode
of production and its related social configurations. Marx was
primarily interested in the contradictions which exist within the
Radical Structuralism 329
substructure of society, and he placed considerable emphasis upon
his notion of ‘surplus value’ as the concept upon which the con-
tradiction between the means and relations of production was
based. 3 His interpreters have also stressed the contradictions
which exist between the substructure and superstructure, and
within the superstructure itself. The notion of contradiction is
central to Marx’s explanation of social change and the way in
which one form of society replaces another through crises pro-
duced by these contradictions. Marx saw these crises withinagiven
mode of production as getting progressively worse and eventually
leading to the cataclysmic crisis which would overthrow the soci-
ety as a whole.
As we have noted. the focus of Marx’s analysis is upon the
political economy of capitalism. ‘Structures·, ‘contradictions’ and
‘crises’ take over from the concepts of ‘consciousness’, ‘aliena-
tion’ and ‘critique’ reflected in his earlier work. Whilst this marks a
considerable change in orientation of analysis, which is consonant
with Marx’s more materialist view of the social world, a certain
continuity within the Hegelian tradition is also evident.• The
notion of contradiction is ultimately derived from the dialectic, and
the concern for alienation also remains. In Marx’s later work,
however, it tends to be imbued with the terminology of political
economy and becomes the ‘fetishism of commodities’, for within
the capitalist system alienation is seen as intimately linked with the
fact that man is treated as a commodity or resource to be bought
and sold upon the labour market. Marx’s overall change in orienta-
tion was aptly expressed by I.assalle, one of his contemporaries,
who described him as ·a Hegel turned economist, a Ricardo turned
socialist’. This description summarises succinctly the two
developments which characterise the thought of his later years, in
which he moved away from a radical idealism towards a radical
interpretation of ‘bourgeois’, ·positivist’ economics. It is this
move which laid the essential foundations of the radical structural-
ist paradigm.
As we have noted, subsequent developments within the context
of the radical structuralist paradigm have been largely based upon
different interpretations placed upon Marx’s later work. At least
three distinct lines of development can be identified. One focuses
upon Engels’ interpretation of Marx and the subsequent develop-
ment of a ‘scientific socialism· in the Russian mould. sIt is this line
of development which is most often equated with ‘Marxism’ when
evaluated from within a context outside the paradigm. A second
line of development has focused upon an interpretation of the
330 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Grundrisse and Capital as representing the essence of Marx’s
work; this has largely arisen as a response to the developments in
critical theory discussed in our chapter on the radical humanist
paradigm. The third line of development can be understood as the
result of a confrontation between the various elements of the work
of Marx and Weber. These three developments largely define the
present structure of the radical structuralist paradigm, and it will
be as well if we review them in general terms prior to more detailed
discussion later in the chapter.
As we have seen, the direction of Marx’s thought in his later
years was towards a radical reinterpretation of political economy.
Under the i ntluence of Engels. particularly after Marx· s death. this
general trend was much intensified, leading to an eventual picture
of Marxism as revealing the essential ‘laws of motion’ underlying
the capitalist system. Under Engels’ influence, the work of Marx
was increasingly seen as presenting a total science of man’s politi-
cal, economic and social life, which contained within its system the
laws of social evolution. 6 This interpretation, which sought to
stress the links between the work of Darwin and Marx. was the one
which predominated under Engels’ influence after Marx’s death.
In Engels’ hands, the dialectic between subjective and objective
worlds was left further and further behind as a materialist view of
history and of society was forged. As Engels himself notes in a
discussion of dialectical materialism,
dialectics reduced itself to the science of the general laws of motion,
both of the external world and of human thought – two sorts of laws
which are identical in substance, but differ in their expression insofar
as the human mind can apply them consciously, while in nature. and
also up to now for the most part in human history, these laws assert
themselves unconsciously, in the form of external necessity, in the
midst of an endless series of seeming accidents … (Engels in Marx and
Engels, 1951, pp. 349-50)
It was precisely this type of rendering of the dialectic within
‘dialectic materialism’ which impressed the socialists and ·social
democrats’ of the late nineteenth century. 7 Within its intellectual
sway, they became the instruments of historical necessity, hand-
maidens of fate who held in their palms the truly superior
philosophy cum science. The Russian, Plekhanov, adopted this
perspective on Marx’s work and thereafter set the ground rules for
the study, analysis and interpretation of Marxism under Bolshev-
ism. In many respects the tradition of Russian social theory over
Radical Structuralism 331
the last hundred or so years has, in large measure, been established
by this Engels-Piekhanov dialogue.
The second line of development within the radical structuralist
paradigm, somewhat paradoxically, originates from the work of
Lenin. As we have seen, Marx’s later work retained certain
Hegelian features. This fact was recognised by Lenin who, shortly
before his death, came to the conclusion that Marx, and especially
Capital, could not be understood without a knowledge of Hegel.
As Conquest (1972) reports, since Hegel had been ignored for
some fifty years. Lenin concluded that no Marxist had yet under-
stood Marx.
This line of reasoning was not developed within Russian social
theory, but it was taken up in the 1960s by a group of Marxists who
stood outside both the Hegelian and the Engelsian tradition. They
tended to see Lenin as the Marxist theorist who came closest to
tapping the essence of Marx’s work.• Their interpretation of Hegel
is a critical one, and in no sense can they be regarded as belonging
to the Left Hegelian brand of theorising discussed i~ connection
with the radical humanist paradigm. Rather they stand between the
critical theory of radical humanism and the tradition of orthodox
Russian Marxism. Marxist philosophers such as Della Volpe,
Althusser and Colletti grew up in cultures dominated by neither
German idealism nor sociological positivism and, as we shall see,
were able to distance themselves-from existing interpretations of
Marx.
The third line of development focuses upon what may be
described as ‘radical Weberianism’. As is well known, Weber
was, in certain aspects of his work, engaged in a dialogue with the
•ghost of Marx’, and certain of his key concepts have been used as
a means of exploring the interface between Marx and Weber. As
we have sought to show in earlier chapters, Max Weber’s influence
has been felt in all of the four paradigms. Whether one points to his
discussion of scientific rationality which pervades much of radical
humanism, or his development of the notion of verstehen in the
interpretive paradigm, or his work on bureaucracy which, though
often misunderstood, dominates functionalist organisation theory,
Weber cannot be ignored. Within radical structuralism, certain
strands of his work which are consistent with the orientation of a
sociology of radical change have been developed by a small group
of European social scientists. In order to distinguish their reading
of Weber from those more typical of functionalism, for example,
we wish to use the term •radical Weberianism’.
Weber’s writings contain political and sociological elements
332 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
welded together, sometimes under great strain and tension, within
the context of one overall framework. 9 For Weber, the central
political question in a unified Germany was the issue of leadership.
How was the newly created State to be governed? He accepted
unquestioningly the ‘rightness’ of its existence and sought its
continuing growth through a concern for the form of development
of industrial capitalism and its emergent bourgeoisie. Weber was a
sociologist of economic order interested in the social conse-
quences of capitalism, with regard to which his views were some-
what ambivalent. His orientation to capitalism demarcates him
quite clearly from the Marxists and the German romantic con-
servatives of his time. The former opposed the capitalist mode of
production for its deleterious effects on the newly created working
population; the latter, for its effects upon the established Junkers’
aristocracy. Between these perspectives Weber advocated a
capitalism containing a strong, intellectually refined bourgeoisie
which would remain true to the superior German culture.
What is important for radical Weberianism, however, is not that
Weber was primarily a sociologist of order and regulation, but that
his ambivalent attitude to capitalism, and particularly to the place
of bureaucracy within it, left open avenues for exploration which
lead to a sociology of radical change. Weber saw bureaucracy as a
reflection of the process of rationalisation which paralleled the
development of capitalism; a process which invaded all aspects of
social life, from politics to religion. As we have seen, Marcuse took
this notion of rationality and used it critically as a cornerstone in
his treatment of ‘one-dimensional man’. Within radical structural-
ism theorists tend to be most interested in Weber’s analysis of
bureaucracy as an instrument of social domination, most forcibly
expressed in the notion of the ‘iron cage of bureaucracy’. For
Weber, bureaucracy posed a threat to human freedom, making it
increasingly more difficult for men to exercise control over their
everyday lives. The threat of this ‘iron cage’ was seen as charac-
terising societies of both a capitalist and a socialist nature. Under
the latter Weber emphasised that the strength of bureaucracy was
increased because in the capitalist mode there was at least an area
for the free play of market forces. Under both systems, however,
the growth of bureaucracy and the mode of purposive rationality
which it reflects was viewed as a force detrimental to the interests
of those subject to its control.
Thus, in the context of radical structuralism, radical Weberian-
ism focuses upon bureaucracy, authority and power as the points
of concentration for theoretical analysis as a means of understand-
Radical Structuralism 333
ing important aspects of ~ociallife under capitalism. Rarely, how-
ever, does it produce politically radical alternatives; as may be
said of other schools of thought, it seeks to interpret critically
rather than to change. Nevertheless, Weber did joust with the
Marxian heritage and fought the battle on its ground, at least on
occasion, and it is the product of this sort of confrontation which
forms the kernel of contemporary ‘radical Weberianism’. In
essence, it seeks to emphasise the role of factors which do not
receive extensive treatment within ‘Marxism’, and which portray
man’s domination and enslavement by the social structures in
which he lives. This radical Weberianism comprises the third
strand in the intellectual development of the radical structuralist
paradigm.
The Structure of the Paradigm
The radical structuralist paradigm is thus a complex body of social
theory which is the result of the fusion of a plurality of philosophi-
cal, political and sociological traditions. Any broad categorisation
of its constituent schools of thought must do violence to this fact
but, bearing this in mind, one can recognise the three very broad
approaches discussed above. We describe them as (a) Russian
social theory; (b) contemporary Mediterranean Marxism; and (c)
conflict theory. Each of these occupies a distinctive position
within the paradigm, as illustrated in Figure 3.3.
Russian Social Theory stands within the Engelsian tradition,
having been introduced into pre-revolutionary thought by
Plekhanov. It later developed into the historical materialism of
Bukharin, and influenced, to a degree, Kropotkin’s version of
anarchistic communism. Although these approaches are politi-
cally divergent, they share a common set of meta-theoretical
assumptions which are unquestionably positivistic and naturalis-
tic. They are located in the most objectivist region of the paradigm.
Contemporary Mediterranean Marxism stands in the tradition
of Marx’s mature works, particularly Capital, and Lenin’s reading
of it. This set the tone for an approach which is of core importance
at the present time. We recognise within it Althusser’s sociology
and Colletti’s sociology which, whilst having close parallels with
each other in terms of their rejection of both Hegelianised Marxism
and orthodox Russian Marxism, again differ politically. To this
extent they occupy different positions on the regulation-radical
change dimension of our analytical scheme.
334 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Conflict theory is the sociological expression of radical
Weberianism and involves the utilisation of several Marxian con-
cepts. We distinguish between Rex’s conflict theory and Dahren-
dorfs conflict theory, although, here again, striking similarities
appear. given a sufficiently broad perspective.
We will discuss each of these schools of thought in turn.
Russian Social Theory
We use this term in order to emphasise certain commonalities
which exist between apparently distinct schools of thought in
Russian intellectual history . 10 We seek to point to connections
between the socio-philosophical approaches of the so-called
‘orthodox Marxism’ of Bukharin and the ‘anarchistic communism •
developed by Kropotkin. These bodies of thought have something
in common in terms of their intellectual backgrounds .and origins,
despite the undisguised hostility between them. The orthodox
Marxism propounded by Bukharin was virulently opposed to
anarchism in all its forms,just as tbe followers ofKropotkin stood
out against the political elitism and administrative centralisation
then nascent in Bolshevism. Indeed, anarchistic communists went
so far as to explode a bomb in a Bolshevik Party Committee
meeting, killing twelve senior members and injuring Bukharin in
the process. Such violent contempt, however, belies a similarity in
meta-theoretical terms between the perspectives of these men.
Both Kropotkin and Bukharin were familiar with the natural sci-
ences, both used ‘scientific’ conceptualisations as the cornerstone
of their systems in a thoroughly positivistic way, and both were
committed to the revolutionary overthrow of the Tsarist govern-
ment in particular and capitalism in general.
Although easy to overemphasise, their mutual ‘objectivism’
derived from Plekhanov and, dependent upon the ‘naturalistic’
assumptions of the scientific method, has remained, in some
degree, typical of contemporary Russian social theory, which has
much in common with functionalist social systems theory so far as
the subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme is
concerned.lndeed, Gouldner( 1970) has made much ofthe current
Soviet interest in functionalism, with which there are the ties of a
common positivist epistemology ,11 and there has also been inter-
est in the reverse direction. Nisbet ( 1976), for example, has sought
to portray Kropotkin as an ecologist before his time.
Radical Structuralism 33S
We begin our analysis of Russian social theory with the work fX
Bukharin.
Bukharin’ s historical materialism
In the tradition of ·scientific socialism’ developed by Engels and
Plekhanov stands the work of Nikolai Bukharin (1888-1938), a
one-time ‘lieutenant of Lenin’ who met his death at the hands of
Stalin. Bukharin sought, in perhaps his best-known work, Histori-
cal Materialism: A System of Sociology, published in 1921, to
provide a textbook in which Marxism was presented as sociology
rather than political economy. The interest at this time in the
sociological challenges to Marx from Weber and Pareto, for
example, required a Marxist response, and Bukharin saw himself
as fulfilling this role.
The son of a Moscow teacher turned bureaucrat, Bukharin
joined the Bolshevik party at the age of 17 as part of its ‘intelligent-
sia’, though deeply committed to the life of a professional
revolutionary. 12 Arrested for the second time in 1910, he was
exiled to north Russia, from whence he escaped, returning to
Moscow in 1917. Before his exile he had become one of the Party’s
leading theorists. interested in developing Marxism through
dialogue with theoretical developments in non-Marxist ‘social sci-
ence’ .In exile in Europe and briefly in New York, his intellectual
contribution was increasingly acknowledged, to the extent that,
for some Bolsheviks. he outshone Lenin, with whom his relations
were usually strained. After the Revolution, he became editor of
the Party newspapers for ten years, during which time he produced
both ·political’ and ‘theoretical’ writings. Towards the end of the
1920s his differences with Stalin grew over the way forward for the
USSR, particularly with regard to agricultural policy. Stalin’s
‘revolution from above’, in which he took over total control of the
reins of Soviet government. marked the beginning of the end for
the more cautious and gradual policies advocated by Bukharin and
his ‘Rightist’ colleagues. He was arrested in 1937 and brought
before a court in the infamous Moscow ·show trials’ by which he
was convicted and sentenced to death. His reputation in Russia
has, even to this day, never recovered from the effects of the
Stalinist Purge.
In Historical Materialism, Bukharin claims that sociology is ·a
method for history’ and, even more controversially, that bourgeois
336 SocioloRical ParadiRms and OrRanisational Analysis
sociology has something to offer Marxism. As he puts it, historical
materialism itself ‘is not political economy, nor is it history; it is the
general theory of society and the laws of its evolution. i.e. socio-
logy’ (Bukharin, 1965, p. xv). It is, in effect, ·proletaridn socio-
logy.
Bukharin did not have much time for ‘dialectics’. Lenin, just
before his death, remarked of Bukharin that ‘his theoretical views
can only with very great doubt be regarded as fully Marxist, for
there is something scholastic in them (he has never studied and I
think, never fully understood dialectics)’ (Cohen, 1974, p. 152). An
economist by training, Bukharin felt more at home with the new
physics of the twentieth century than with the German idealism in
philosophy of the century before. ‘Materialism’, for him, stood
against Hegelian metaphysics and for science and technology; as a
consequence his book is based upon the mechanical analogy
·derived specifically and in unmodified form from physics. Rather
than accept the thesis, antithesis and synthesis elements of the
dialectic, Bukharin preferred to equate these with ‘the condition of
equilibrium; in the second place, disturbance of this equilibrium; in
the third place, the re-establishment of equilibrium on anew basis’
(Bukharin, 1965, pp. 74-5). His discussion at this point goes on to
consider ‘systems theory’ from the Marxist perspective, viewing
society as being in a state of unstable equilibrium because of
imbalance with its environment. Balance with the environment is
sought through the development of technology in which the rela-
tionship between the society and nature is regulated. Social change
comes about through alterations in this balance, which leads to
periods of revolutionary disequilibrium at times of crisis and its
ultimate replacement by an equilibrium at a higher stage of
development. In this way Bukharin sought to reject the biological
analogy then prevalent in Western sociology, which saw social
change as somehow pathological, but his Russian critics were
quick to point out, as others were later to say offunctionalism, that
the notion of equilibrium, in whatever form, suggests harmony and
co-operation as the primary modes of social organisation. Indeed,
Bukharin admits such a bias when he maintains that without har-
mony ‘society will not grow but decline’.
It is important to note, however, that this disturbance of equilib-
rium implicitly takes the form of a ·catastrophe’ or ·cataclysmic
crisis’, through which social revolution is brought about. Buk-
harin’s concept of a ‘new equilibrium· implies a ‘totality shift’ of
enormous proportions and not the evolutionary or morphogenic
process envisaged by even the most change-orientated of func-
Radical Structuralism 337
tionalists. The equilibrium models are thus comparable only in
name. In essence, Bukharin’s model has more in common with the
catastrophe than the mechanical analogy for the study of social
change.
Clearly, then, Bukharin is a Marxist committed to the revolu-
tionary overthrow of capitalism through violent conflict, but is
convinced that in the end social harmony will prevail. A systems
model of a crude but early type is seen as the best theoretical
perspective through which to understand both this new socialist
society and the laws of motion of pre-socialist societies. In a sense,
then, Bukharin developed a kind offunctionalism before it became
established in the West, with a concomitant focus upon under-
standing social life in terms of long periods of relative stability. In
his case, however, it was first necessary to transform existing
Western societies through violent and sometimes bloody revolu-
tion. In this way the location of Bukharin’s sociology within our
analytical scheme parallels that of functionalism, but within the
context of a sociology of radical change. Ontologically, Bukharin
is firmly realist. In talking of idealism, Bukharin describes solips-
ism as ‘this insane philosophy’ which ‘is contradicted by human
experience at every step’. For ‘when we eat, conduct the class
struggle, put on our shoes, pluck flowers, write books, take a wife
or husband, none of us ever thinks of doubting the existence of the
external world i.e. the existence ~ let us say – ofthe food we eat,
the shoes we wear, the women we marry’ (Bukharin, 1965, p. 56).
Here the reality of the world is accepted on a common-sense level.
There is a total acceptance of the unproblematic nature of real
objects like ‘books’ and ‘class struggles’, which are seen to have
material, concrete existence outside human consciousness.
Indeed, human consciousness is seen as wholly dependent upon
economic production, for material production, and its means, the
material productive forces, are the foundation of the existence of
human society. Without it there cannot be a ·social conscious-
ness’.
Epistemologically, Bulkarin adopts the positivism of the
natural sciences as his model. Historical materialism is a ·scientific
sociology’ which explains the general laws of human evolution; it
serves as a method for history. What Bukharin seeks, then, primar-
ily through the notion of equilibrium, is to explain in a generalis-
able way the story of human development. The historical material-
ism of Marx and Engels provides a means whereby such general
laws are attainable. Furthermore, these laws provide causal
explanations. As he puts it, ‘Both in nature and in society there
338 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
exists objectively (i.e. regardless of whether we wish it or not,
whether we are conscious of it or not) a law of nature that is
causal in character’ (Bukharin, 1965, p. 30). In this way Bukharin
adopts a naturalistic positivism for his epistemological stance and
the nomothetic methodology that it implies in the attainment and
analysis of what he believes to be the constantly observable con-
nection between phenomena.
Bukharin also devotes some time to a discussion of the free
wil~determinism debate. He discusses a number of examples
drawn from everyday life, and goes on to suggest that
A consideration of these examples has shown that under all conditions,
both usual and unusual, both normal and abnormal, the will, the feel-
ing, the actions of the individual man always have a definite cause: they
are always conditioned (‘determined’), defined. The doctrine of free-
dom of the will (indeterminism) is at bottom an alternated form of a
semi-religious view which explains nothing at all, contradicts all the
facts of life, and constitutes an obstacle to scientific development. The
only correct point of view is that of determinism. (Bukharin. 1965,
p. 37)
In his own words, therefore, Bukharin clearly places himself
upon our analytical schema. He is a determinist, rejecting the
notion of a creative free will and its role in social life. Adding to this
his positivism and realism, in toto Bukharin occupies a position of
extreme objectivism within the sociology of radical change. He
delimits the objectivist wing of the radical structuralist paradigm, a
position which many in the West now describe as ‘vulgar Marx-
ism’. It is a variety of Marxism, however, which owes more to
Engels than to Marx; indeed, it takes Engels’ reformulation ofthe
work of Marx to its logical extreme. It is the variety of Marxism on
which systems theorists have seized in their attempt to equate
dialectical materialism and functionalism and pronounce that the
order-conflict debate is now dead. 13
Anarchistic communism
Anarchistic communism is most closely associated with Peter
Kropotkin (1842-1921), a Russian prince at whose funeral in
Moscow the Bolsheviks mourned.•~ After a time as a page in the
Tsar’s court, Kropotkin journeyed as a geographer and naturalist
into Siberia, where he came into contact with several nomadic
Radical Stru£”1uralism 339
groups which were to influence his later theoretical work. After
adopting the revolutionary cause and being forced into exile for
forty years, he returned to Russia in 1917, only to become disil-
lusioned with the Bolshevik Revolution before his death in 1921.
Kropotkin continually sought to put anarchistic communism on
a firm philosophical and theoretical footing, which demarcates him
from many of the more activist nihilists of the anarchist movement,
who were anti-intellectuals almost to a man. At university,
Kropotkin had studied mathematics and geography. The
methodology and epistemology of the natural sciences were to
form, throughout his life, the basis of his social philosophy. He
described his own work in these terms in an early entry in the
EncyclopiPdia Britannica:
As one of the anarchist-communist direction Peter Kropotkin for many
years endeavoured to develop the following ideas: to show the inti-
mate, logical connection which exists between the modern philosophy
of the natural sciences and anarchism; to put anarchism on a scientific
basis by the study of the tendencies that are apparent now in society
and may indicate its further evolution; and to work out the basis of
anarchist ethics. As regards the substance of anarchism itself, it was
Kropotkir.’s aim to prove that communism – at least partial – has
more chances of being established than collectivism, especially in
communes taking the lead, and that free or anarchist-communism is the
only form of communism that has any chance of being accepted in
civilised societies; communism and anarchy are therefore two terms of
evoiution which complete each other. the one rendering the other
possible and acceptable. (Quoted in Bose, 1967, p. 262)
As a naturalist, the evolutionary theories of Darwin had a profound
effect upon him, but he argued vehemently against the notions of
Herbert Spencer, whose concepts of the survival of the fittest
Kropotkin saw as implying that competition and conflict were
endemic to all animal species, including man. Rather, he pointed to
the widespread existence of ‘mutual aid’ in human societies not
characterised by the capitalist mode of production. For, as Avrich
notes,
His own observations indicated that, in the process of natural selec-
tion, spontaneous co-operation among animals was far more important
than ferocious competition, and that ‘those animals which acquire
habits of mutual aid are undoubtedly the fittest’ to survive. By no
means did Kropotkin deny the existence of struggle within the animal
kingdom, but he was confident that mutual dependence played a much
larger role – indeed, mutual aid was ‘the chief factor of progressive
evolution’. (Avrich, 1967, p. 30)
340 Sociological Paradil(ms and Or!fanisational Analysis
His belief in ·mutual aid’ had been inspired by his experiences in
Siberia, where small-scale tribal groups of nomads lived according
to ‘anarchist’ principles. Kropotkin’s experiences in these years
convinced him that the natural attitude of man was one of co-
operation and solidarity, and that the principle of hierarchy was a
recent •pathological’ development in man’s history. The centralis-
ing tendencies of the Russian State, which was undergoing a late
transition to capitalism, were the first objects of his attention, but
his forty years in exile in Western Europe convinced him that
capitalism, wherever it was found, represented an aberration in
man’s evolution. Anarchistic communism stood, for Kropotkin, in
direct opposition to the wage system of capitalism, the superces-
sion of which depended upon violent mass revolution. Once the
wage system had been overthrown. a new society would be set up,
based upon communes which would be self-governing, decentral-
ised, almost self-sufficient units. He did not see this vision as
Utopian but as the only possible solution to the problems-of capi-
talism, the State and bureaucracy. The overthrow of capitalism
brought about through economic crisis would be a bloody affair
and, although less disposed towards violence and terrorism than
many others, Kropotkin did believe in ·propaganda of the deed’
and thought it quite legitimate to engage in political assassination.
After 1917 he came to see the Bolshevik’s version of Marxism as a
new form of human enslavement, one form of centralisation having
been replaced by another, thereby preventing the return which he
sought to a form of society based upon mutual aid in which conflict
was minimised.
In Kropotkin’s publications, 15 one is able to see quite plainly the
objectivist stance which he derived from the wholesale incorpora-
tion of natural science methods and assumptions. He describes his
orientation as follows:
I gradually began to realise that anarchism represents more than a mere
mode of action and a mere conception of a free society; that it is part of
a philosophy, natural and social, which must be developed in a quite
different way from the meta-physical or dialectical methods which
have been employed in sciences dealing with men. I saw it must be
treated by the same methods as natural sciences … on the solid basis of
induction applied to human institutions. (Kropotkin, in Woodcock,
1975, P. 184)
Kropotkin is representative of that stream of Russian social theory
which sees no distinction between the natural and social sciences
and believes that the •Jaws of nature’ serve as models for the study
Radical Structuralism 341
of society. Also typical of Russian sociological thought at this
time is his firm commitment to radical change, though his vision of
this differs quite substantially from that of his contemporaries.
The social theory of the USSR before 1925, therefore, was
rooted in an equation of the social sciences with the natural sci-
ences. The influence of Darwinism, and the intimate relationship
which was seen to exist between man and nature, created variants
of an evolutionary theory in which capitalism was regarded as a
•genetic’ monstrosity, the dispatch of which would herald a new
era of social life in which harmony and understanding would
prevail: The perspective of theorists such as Bukharin and
Kropotkin differs from that of positivist social theorists located in
the functionalist paradigm, in that the analogy which they use to
characterise the· process by which this will be brought about is that
of catastrophe and revolution. It is this crucial feature of their work
which locates it within the bounds of the sociology of radical
change as opposed to the sociology of regulation.
Contemporary Mediterranean Marxism
Within this brand of theorising we recognise two separate schools,
which, although distinctive in their approaches to many substan-
tive issues, are based upon a set of common meta-theoretical
assumptions. These are the sociologies of Althusser and Colletti.
Whilst both theoreticians stand in the mainstream of contempor-
ary Western Marxist thought, they adopt perspectives consciously
distinct from the Hegelianised Marxism of Lukacs, Gramsci and
the Frankfurt School on one hand, and the orthodox Marxism of
Plekhanov and Bukharin on the other . 16 They seek to temper what
they see as the extreme objectivism of ·vulgar’ Marxism and the
subjectivism of critical theory by adopting an intermediate posi-
tion.
Althusser and Colletti, in spite of their intellectual proximity, or
perhaps because of it, have conducted a rather fierce academic
battle in which both participants have had their noses bloodied. 17
This internal conflict notwithstanding, there is a close interrela-
tionship in their work in terms of their theoretical stance, although
there are many who believe that Althusser is far and away the more
creative thinker. He has built a system; Colletti seeks to destroy
those of other people.’ 8 Whilst we do not wish to denigrate the role
of essayist and critic, we believe that Althusser’s conceptualisa-
tions have more scope for development than those of Colletti.
342 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
We have chosen the epithet ‘Mediterranean Marxism• to
emphasise not merely the origins of both men, but the fact that
their theoretical stance is located outside the north European
idealist tradition and is, at most, peripheral to the Anglo-French
positivist tradition. It is a hallmark of Althusser’s and Colletti’s
perspective that the extremes of both these broad currents of
thought are rejected in favour of an ‘intermediate’ position which,
although unmistakably objectivist, is familiar with, and not totally
unsympathetic to, German idealism. We begin our analysis with
the recognition that we cannot do justice to the quite marked
differences in detail between the perspectives of Althusser and
Colletti, but this is a task which they themselves are not slow to
address. For us, their broad similarities are of more interest at this
point, although some attention will be paid to differences between
them in terms of the regulation-radical change dimension of our
analytical scheme. We begin our analysis with a consideration of
the work of Louis Althusser.
Althusserian sociology
Louis Althusser is one of the world’s most influential contempor-
ary Marxist philosophers, and he has attracted a great deal of
attention from not only radical sociologists, but writers in many
disciplines. An Algerian by birth, Althusser fought in World
War II and was taken prisoner by the Germans in 1940. He
returned to Paris in 1945, studied under the philosopher Bachelard
and has remained there to teach ever since. He is a member of the
Communist Party and has explicit political views which are often
described as Stalinist. 19 Whilst his work is extremely complicated,
sometimes contradictory and, indeed, still in the process of being
developed, it is possible to identify certain conceptualisations
which have been the subject of much discussion and critical
assessment. Althusser uses the notion of a circle to describe parts
of his work, and in any analysis it is often very difficult to know
where to begin. However, Althusser’s work can be interpreted as a
reaction against the Hegelianised Marxism of Lukacs, Gramsci
and the Frankfurt School, and represents an attempt to develop a
more sophisticated riposte to it in the tradition of ‘orthodox’
materialism. Crucial here is Althusser’s notion of the ·epistem-
ological break’ in Marx’s work, which delimits the early ‘philo-
sophical’ work from the more mature ·scientific’ analyses of Capital
Radical Structuralism 343
and the later writings. 20 The early work is seen as completely dis-
tinct from the texts upon which Althusser wishes to focus, for he
rejects the notion of Marx as a ‘theoretical humanist’. Althusser
maintains that for the mature Marx, humanism represented nothing
more than an ideology, since it assumed both a fixed human nature
and a crucial role for subjective factors in the historical process.
Neither is a correct assumption, according to Althusser, whose
reading of Marx’s Capital supposedly demonstrates that the notion
of “dialectic’ therein, represents a ‘process without a subject’ .11
Marx was seen as transforming the Hegelian ‘dialectic • by removing
the limitations within it created by both an emphasis on man’s con-
sciousness and a dependence upon a belief in the historical neces-
sity of man’s progress through ever-developing stages. Put
crudely, for Althusser and his Marx, men do not make history; it is
made by particular configurations of structures which arise at
given points in time. Althusser, then, stands against and between
the ·subjective humanism’ of the Hegelian Marxists and the thesis
of historical inevitability proposed by Engels and Bukharin. For
him, the dialectic leads neither to subjectivism nor to historicism.
Althusser’s ·structuralism’21 depends upon an understanding of
the ‘totality’, not just as an assembly of pans to be only understood
as a whole, but as something shaping and present within each part.
The parts reflect the totality; not the totality the pans. Of these
pans, Althusser recognises four ‘practices’ – the economic, the
political, the ideological and the theoretical (scientific). Although,
in the final analysis, the economic ‘practice’ is seen as the most
important, at given historical’conjunctures’ each of the ·practices’
has relative independence, despite the possible domination of one
‘practice’ (though not neces~drily the economic) over the others.
Althusser calls such a concept a ‘structure in dominance’ .23 Any
particular historical event, therefore, represents the complex
interrelationship between ‘practices’, which are linked through the
idea of ‘overdetermination •, defined rather obscurely by
Callinicos as ‘the idea of a structure whose complexity, the mutual
distinctness and interdependence of its elements, is expressed
through the way in which the economy displaces the dominant role
within the structure to a particular instance, organising the other
instances in terms of this structure in dominance’ (Callinicos,
1976, p. 51). 24 In Althusser’s view, then, superstructural elements
can be as important as, if not more important than, those of the
economic substructure. At the most basic level this implies a
multi-causal theory of history, since economic factors are not seen
as determinate in all instances. As social development consists of a
344 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
series of historical events, the configurations of particular •over-
determinations’ create in given societies quite different social
forms. This is the famous •Jaw of uneven development’, which
rejects, of course, any concept of historical necessity or prede-
termination in the social process (Aithusser, 1969, p. 249).
Social change, for Althusser, depends upon the type and extent
of ·contradictions’ in the social formation. Some contradictions
are antagonistic and their ·explosive’ interrelationships will pro-
duce, in the long run, sweeping societal transformations at times of
great crisis. Other contradictions are non-antagonistic and play a
less important role in social change. The motor force of history,
then, is found in the interrelationship of particular contradictions
at a given point in time which surface as perceptible socio-
economic crises. 25
The logic of this position, politically, has not been obscured as
far as Althusser’s critics are concerned. If revolution is to be
achieved in this perspective, it depends upon particular conjunc-
tions of contradictions and overdetermination. The. role of the
political activist is thereby de-emphasised. 26 For what can the
revolutionary hope to do to bring about radical social change, if
this is determined ultimately by 4 deep, hidden structures?
Althusser’s philosophy, then, is open to the charge of his non-
structuralist critics of ‘quietism’ and to the accusation that it
implies a rejection of ‘praxis’. Regis Debray, a one-time student of
Althusser’s, thus commented on his mentor·s separation of
‘thought’ from ·reality’ and ‘”the operation of society” from “the
operation of knowledge”. In other words, all we had to do to
become good theoreticians was to be lazy bastards’ (Callinicos,
1976, p. 60). Althusser’s claim that philosophy is ‘the class struggle
in theory· certainly permits armchair theorising, and it is relatively
easy for cynics to point to the popularity of Althusserianism
amongst the academic Marxists of Europe as an indication of this.
Ontologically, Althusser assumes a real, concrete world exter-
nal to the individual and his consciousness of it. This real world, in
Althusser’s theory, may be thought to consist of ‘structures’ which
together, in the ‘totality’, represent given ‘social formations’.
These conceptualisations, however, according to Althusser’s epis-
temology, are not necessarily based upon any correspondence
with the real world. Indeed, as Callinicos has suggested, Althusser
argues that ‘there exists the sharpest possible separation between
the real object, that is, the reality which the theory seeks to
explain, and the thought-object, the theoretical system which
makes up a science’ (Callinicos, 1976, p. 32). The idea that a theory
Radical Structuralism 345
should mirror or fit exactly the reality it purports to explain
Althusser terms ’empiricism’, and he is fundamentally opposed to
it. The separation of the real from the theoretical which this implies
leads inexorably to the tendency of armchair theorising, which
requires no empirical work, whether ‘research’ or political activ-
ism, since theory needs no anchors in the real external world.
Althusser·s version of anti-empiricism, however, does not pre-
clude positivism in the sense of the search for universal causal
laws. It does, in fact, explicitly seek to provide a causal analysis,
but one which, in recognising the variety of overdeterminations
and the ‘law’ of uneven development, does not pursue the pro-
duction of uni-causal explanations of, say, social change. The
social reality, which we as men can only perceive as surface
bubbles upon a deep, hidden and mysterious pool, is seen as con-
tingent upon a variety of structural interrelationships and must be
analysed in terms of conjunctures – specific historical events. The
logic of Althusser’s position, in effect, calls for a case-study
method of analysing particular ‘conjunctures’, each. of which is
unique, for only in this way can our knowledge of history be
developed.
Althusser rejects the perspective of economic determinism
found, for example, in Plekhanov and Bukharin, and its more
extreme form, economic predeterminism – the unfolding of the
inexorable laws of capitalist development which inevitably leads
to its overthrow. He still maintains a determinist position, how-
ever, in that humanism, which for him emphasises subjective and
voluntarist notions, is ruled completely out of court. Man’s actions
and historical events are determined fundamentally by the social
formations in which they are located.I ndividuals, according to this
view, are not ·subjects’ but agents within the mode of production,
and are correspondingly moulded by the forces acting upon the
economic ‘practice’.
As for Althusser’s position on our subjective-objective dimen-
sion, his philosophical sophistication makes for an interesting
configuration upon the four analytical strands. Ontologically, he is
a realist, but the real world can only be understood through theory,
which need not be located or rooted in reality at all. Epistemologi-
cally, in seeking ·scientific’ knowledge outside ideology, he is a
positivist, though not of an extreme kind, since he totally rejects
empiricism. Methodologically, Althusser’s position emphasises
the case-study method of analysis for any given historical ·con-
juncture’, whilst his view of human nature is fundamentally deter-
minist. His overall position within the radical structuralist para-
346 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
digm is that of a ‘mild’ or tempered objectivist. He has sought, and
in large measure achieved, a compromise between the orthodox
Marxism of the Russian State and the Hegelianised Marxism of the
West.
Colletti’s sociology
The work of Lucio Colletti reflects a development in Italian Marx-
ism which is more notable for its wide-ranging and trenchant
criticism than its development of any socio-philosophical system.
A student of Della Volpe, 27 Colletti joined the Italian Communist
Party in 1950 and has been concerned both with the role of the
Italian working class in revolutionary activity in a ‘post-Fascist’
society, and with sketching the outlines for a ‘scientific’ Marxism.
Unlike Althusser, he became disaffected with developments in the
internal politics of Russia and her satellites. and in 1956 he left the
Party. Colletti’s work, which he calls ‘sociology’ ,21 consists
primarily of detailed attacks upon variants of Hegelianised Marx-
ism, particularly that of the Frankfurt School, and upon orthodox
Marxism represented in the main by Engels and Plekhanov (Col-
letti, 1972). On the face of it, he seeks not to reconcile these
perspectives within an overall synthesis, but to recognise that
Marx’s work reflects two faces, that of the philosopher and that of
the scientist. The unifying link between these is found in the notion
of ‘opposition’, which in Marx is seen to have two distinct mean-
ings. First, there is the meaning of the real opposition of ‘things •,
which have no synthesis and hence no dialectic relationship. As
Marx put it, ‘Real extremes cannot be mediated, precisely because
they are real extremes. Nor do they have any need for mediation,
for their natures are totally opposed. They have nothing in com-
mon with each other, they have no need for one another, they do
not complement one another’ (Colletti, 1975, p. 6). For
Colletti, this view of ·opposition’, which is found pre-
dominantly in science, must be contrasted with that of dialectical
opposition, which, of course, derives from Hegel and refers to the
opposition of abstractions, concepts or ideas which can be syn-
thesised in a ‘higher· reconciliation. This is the philosophical view
of opposition. ‘Opposition’ in the ‘science’ of Marxism is equated
with the notion of ·contradiction’. which is regarded as inade-
quately emphasised by the Hegelianised brands of thought. On the
other hand, ‘alienation’ represents ‘opposition’ in the philosophi-
Radical Structuralism 347
cal conceptualisations of Marxism, and this is underemphasised by
orthodox Marxism. So in Colletti’s words, ‘The theory of aliena-
tion and the theory of contradiction are now seen as a single
theory’, different elements of which tend to be ignored by compet-
ing versions of Marxist thought (Colletti, 1975, p. 27). Signifi-
cantly, Colletti makes no attempt at the periodisation of Marx’s
work. He specifi<:ally maintains that the notion of "alienation'
represents a theme running throughout the writings of Marx, even
in the pieces dealing with abstract political economy. Thus, for
Colletti, there are two parallel strands in Marx, not two distinct
phases of intellectual activity. His criticism ofMarcuse, for exam-
ple, and ofPiekhanov is rooted in this basic assertion. He polarises
Marxism on the basis of the relative emphasis put upon either the
philosophical strand of 'alienation' or the scientific strand of 'con-
tradiction'. His 'solution' to such polarisation is found in the
recognition of its existence, and he is content to
confine myself for the moment to registering this fact. I do not attribute
any conclusive significance to it. The social sciences ·have not yet
found a true foundation of their own. Hence I do not know whether the
existence of these two aspects is fatal or advantageous. What is not at
issue is the fact that our task now is to find out whether and how they
can be reconciled. It is one we must take seriously .It is not to be solved
by verbal subterfuge. (Colletti, 1975, p. 29)
Whilst a skilled and knowledgeable critic, Colletti has added
little to .the conceptual armoury of Marxism, but his position is one
which has attracted many followers. Without developing a 'sys-
tem' in any coherent or rigorous way, Colletti provides a refuge in
the interstices provided by, or left between, the dominant Marxist
traditions. It is a refuge characterised by the following set of
meta-theoretical assumptions. Ontologically, Colletti assumes the
real existence of the external world. As he puts it, 'Progress, then,
consists in restoring and re-establishing these 'facts', these real
processes, eluded and transcended by metaphysics and opposing
the hypostatis that conceals them. Their objective existence, is in
short, the indispensable premiss for any kind of scientific
enquiry' (Colletti, 1972, p. 5). Whilst he rejects an extreme real-
ism, and asserts that ·materialism', the philosophical position he
subscribes to, necessarily involves a consideration of man as a
'knowing subject', Colletti nevertheless sees the nature of the
social world in what is fundamentally a realist way .19 Epistemolog-
ically, Colletti is a positivist in the tradition of Della Volpe. He sees
Marxism as a ·science' which, though not overcommitted to empir-
348 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
icism, is based upon the method of hypothesis testing in the search
for underlying causal laws. When it comes to a choice of orienta-
tion over epistemology, Colletti comes down firmly on the positiv-
ist side. In talking of Husserl and Sartre (inter alia) Colletti pro-
claims, for example, that 'Against the dangers of this spiritualist
idealism, I personally would prefer to incur the opposite risks of
neo-positivism' (Colletti, 1974, p. 20). Methodologically, how-
ever, Colletti tends to be anti-historicist and does not seek a
method of providing laws valid for all societies at all points in time.
He believes that Marx was concerned primarily with capitalism,
and that Marxian theory is aimed in this direction and nowhere
else. With regard to human nature, Colletti assumes a tempered
determinism, for whilst he accepts that someone of Gramsci's
stature could contribute to change in a capitalist society ('his
research on Italian society was a real preparation for transforming
it'), Colletti nevertheless stresses the objective facti city of capital-
ism's structure and the great problems involved in its superces-
sion.
All in all, Colletti stands within the radical structuralist paradigm
in a fairly objectivist position. Faced with the self-imposed choice
of a Hegelian Marxism or an orthodox Marxism, Colletti seems to
reject the former while certainly not fully embracing the latter. For
Colletti, it seems that Lenin is the Marxist thinker who is least
incorrect.
In terms of the regulation-radical change dimension of our
analytical scheme, Colletti occupies an interesting position, and
one which is differentiated from that of Althusser. By continuing to
adhere to the 'philosophical' concept of 'alienation', Colletti
emphasises the importance of potentiality in man's development
and the way in which this is constrained by capitalism. The over-
throw of this form of social organisation is not seen as depending
solely upon violence. The Stalinist tradition, against which Colletti
particularly reacts, believed that 'it was only violence that was the
real hallmark of a revolution: everything else- the transformation
of the nature of power, the establishment of socialist democracy -
was of no importance' (Colletti, 1974, p. 22). In place of this
Colletti seeks to emphasise that revolution and violence are by no
means interchangeable concepts and that in the last resort there
could even be non-violent revolution. Nevertheless, revolutionary
activity by the working class is seen as the main solution to the
social problems posed by capitalism. For Colletti, it is not suffi-
cient for academics to develop good theory, for, as he puts it,
'Marxism is not a phenomenon comparable to existentialism,
Radical Structuralism 349
phenomenology or nco-positivism. Once it becomes so, it is
finished.' Marxism, for Colletti, involves revolutionary political
practice - a strategy for radical social change which has an
intimate connection with the 'life of the workers' movement.
There are thus clear differences between Colletti and Althusser.
Colletti has attempted to link the philosophy in Marx's work to
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason and his politics to those of
Rousseau. For Althusser, Spinoza is the intellectual antecedent of
Marx. Furthermore, as Perry Anderson has observed, 'their two
accounts of the development of Marxism since the 1920s are
incompatible, since Althusser's categories explicitly include Col-
letti in the Hegelian tradition he repudiated, while Colletti's logic
assigns Althusser to the Hegelian heritage he denounced'
(Anderson, 1976, p. 70). Nevertheless, as we have sought to show,
both writers retain elements of Hegelianism within an objectivist
framework. Colletti seeks, through the lifeline of 'alienation', to
maintain links with the Hegelianised Marxism which he wishes to
distance himself from, whilst for Althusser the association with
Hegelianism is supported by the notions of 'totality' and 'dialec-
tic'. The similarity of their intermediate stance in terms of the
subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme pro-
vides the rationale for their consideration here as distinct but
related exponents of what we have called contemporary Medit-
erranean Marxism.
Conflict Theory
As we have noted, conflict theory is a product of ·radical
Weberianism'. Weber's conceptualisations, although not
necessarily specifically intended as rejoinders to those of Marx,
have been used in precisely such a way. For whereas Marx talks of
'class', Weber speaks of 'class, status' and ·party'; Marx of 'the
means of production', Weber of 'the means of administration';
Marx of the 'dialectic', Weber of 'explanation at the level of cause
and meaning', and so on. Such distinctions, although obviously
very important, in fact delineate different approaches to the same
intellectual terrain, namely, the problems of social relations within
a capitalist society. 30 Both Marx and Weber saw that capitalism
represented a new mode of societal organisation, certainly differ-
ent from feudalism (in many ways superior to it), but nevertheless
beset by its own forms of repression, oppression and human
350 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
bondage. However, Weber did not see capitalism as the social
mode in which such tendencies reached their apogee. His concern
for the forms of domination characteristic of a whole range of
societies emphasised the role of power in social life throughout
history, not just within capitalism. The rich conceptualisations of
·status' and •party' sought to encompass the plurality offorms of
social stratification throughout historical development, and not
just the glaring inequalities of the class structure under pre-World
War I capitalism. Weber's emphasis on bureaucratisation within
capitalism was, again, rooted in history. Although he saw the
hierarchical principle, when wedded to purposive rationality. as
the basis for the workers • exploitation and alienation under capital-
ism, he found elements of the bureaucratic mode of domination in
many places and at many points in time.
The radical Weberians of today make much of Weber's concep-
tual armoury for the analysis of contemporary society. For in
Weber's notion of the •iron cage ofbureaucracy'. in his elaboration
of the complexity of modern social stratification, in his emphasis
upon power and authority, they find rich and productive insight. In
line with Marxists, they conceive of capitalism, or its latter-day
transmutations, as beset by gross economic inequalities and by
vast discrepancies in power, both of which mean that social life
must inevitably rest upon domination and conflict. For them, the
interests of the power holders are so clearly distinct from the
interests of the relatively powerless that deep-seated, irreconcil-
able conflict is viewed as the natural and the only permanent
feature of social life. Radical Weberians share Weber's pessimism;
they see no end to such inequalities. Marxism is seen as Utopian if
it expects an end to the principle of hierarchy and imbalance of
power. Social revolution, for these writers as it was for Weber, is
often more dangerous than the retention of the status quo. Thus,
the essence of the radical Weberians' position consists of a tren-
chant criticism of capitalism but without any associated commit-
ment to its transcendence by another form of social organisation.lt
is the strength and nature of their critique and arguments in the first
half of this configuration, at its interface with contemporary Marx-
ism, that identifies their work as part of the sociology of radical
change.ln the following pages we will consider the conflict theory
ofRalf Dahrendorf and John Rex as representative ofthis school of
social thought.
We have already given a certain amount of attention to Dahren-
dorf's work in Chapter 2, where we argued that his distinction
between the integration and coercion theories of society parallels
Radical Structuralism 35 I
that drawn here between the sociology of regulation and the
sociology of radical change. Dahrendorf's coercion or conflict
theory is developed in Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Soci-
ety (1959) as a part of a critique of Marx's work, 'in the light of
historical changes and sociological insights'. Dahrendorf argues
that Marx's basic analysis is faulty, in that his historical predic-
tions have not borne fruit, 31 and seeks to revamp his conceptual
schema with sociological insights drawn primarily from Weber.
Dahrendorf's conflict theory aims at explaining the relative
absence of order within industrial society and reflects one of the
central theses of his study: that 'the differential distribution of
authority' within society 'invariably becomes the determining fac-
tor of systemic social conflicts of a type that is germane to class
conflicts in the traditional (Marxian) sense' (Dahrendorf, 1959, p.
165). His analysis focuses upon the way in which conflict groups
are generated by the authority relations in what he describes as
'imperatively co-ordinated associations'. These are defined as
those forms of organisation, institution or aggregate in which
authority plays the key role in the day-to-day running.of affairs. It
is Dahrendorf's thesis that within such imperatively co-ordinated
associations there exists an authority relationship in which a clear
line, at least in theory, can be drawn between those who partici-
pate in the exercise of authority in given associations and those
who are subject to the authoritative commands of others. Dahren-
dorf thus sets up a two-'class' model of contemporary social
structures, based upon Weber's notion of hierarchical authority
but dichotomised in a manner reminiscent of Marx's thesis of
polarisation. He sees the basic conflict groups of society as rooted
in this differentiation of authority, for different positions involve,
or at least imply, the different interests of the respective role
incumbents. Such interests may be perceived, recognised and
acted upon by an aggregate of persons in a common position in the
authority structure, in which case interests become manifest and
the aggregate becomes a 'group for itself'. If these interests remain
latent, however, then one is dealing merely with a 'quasi-group'. It
is the 'group for itself', the 'interest group' which, for Dahrendorf,
is the true conflict group, having a structure, a form of organisa-
tion, a programme or goal and a personnel of members. Such
interest groups become the motive force behind societal change,
creating transformations of the social structure with varying
degrees of effect, ranging from revolution to small-scale political
reform. Violent class struggle is thus presented as but one extreme
point on a more general scale of social conflict.
3S2 Sociological Paradigm.t and Organisational Analysis
As a summary of his position, Dahrendorf presents a 'theory of
social classes and class conflict', of which the following is an
edited version.ll
I. The heuristic purpose of the approach proposed in the study is
the explanation of structure changes in terms of group conflict.
This purpose is, therefore, neither purely descriptive nor related
to problems of integration and coherence in or of society.
2. In order to do justice to this heuristic purpose. it is necessary to
visualise society in terms of the coercion theory of social
structure, i.e., change and conflict have to be assumed as
ubiquitous, all elements of social structure have to be related to
instability and change, and unity and coherence have to be
understood as resulting from coercion and constraint.
3. The formation of connict groups of the class type follows a
pattern that can be described in terms of a model involving the
following panly analytical, partly hypothetical steps:
4. In any imperatively co-ordinated association two, and only two,
aggregates of positions may be distinguished: positions of
domination and positions of subjection.
S. Each of these aggregates is characterised by common latent
interests; the collectivities of individuals corresponding to them
constitute quasi-groups.
6. Latent interests are articulated into manifest interests; and the
quasi-groups become the recruiting fields of organised interest
groups of the class type.
7. Once the formation of connict groups of the class type is com-
plete, they stand, within given associations. in a relation of group
connict (class connict).
8. Group connict of the class type effects structure changes in the
associations in which it occurs.
9. The radicalness of structure change co-varies with the intensity
of class conflict.
10. The suddenness of structure change co-varies with the violence
of class conflict.
Dahrendorf's analysis is thus firmly rooted in Weberian con-
ceptualisations. Rather than seeing class conflict as a product of
capitalism, he sees it almost as ubiquitous in any hierarchically
organised society. His focus upon power, and particularly author-
ity, borrows from Weber rather than from Marx. However, by
concentrating upon social change, radical conflict and the role of
coercion in social life, and by attacking what he sees as the basic
·one-sided' assumptions of functionalism, Dahrendorf adopts a
stance consonant with the sociology of radical change.
Radical Structuralism 353
Dahrendorf's conflict theory has many points of similarity with
that developed by John Rex in his book Key Problems in Sociolog·
ical Theory (1961), though Rex is also more committed to revamp-
ing sociological theory in terms of its assumptions in relation to the
subjective-objective dimension of our analytical scheme.
Whereas Dahrendorf is content to wed his conflict analysis to an
approach which is firmly committed to the sociological positivist
tradition, Rex starts from the assertion that both positivism and
empiricism are inadequate. In their place he advocates a model
based upon the Weberian action frame of reference which, as will
be clear from our discussion in previous chapters, stands at an
intermediate position between positivism and idealism. Rex's con-
flict theory thus follows Weber on two counts rather than just one:
in terms ofboth·conceptsand methods. Rex's action theory speci-
fically recognises that the ends which actors pursue may be
·random ends' from the point of view of the social system within
which they are located and, indeed, in conflict with it. As a result,
he argues that, •if there is an actual conflict of ends, the behaviour
of actors towards one another may not be determined by shared
norms but by the success which each has in compelling the other to
act in accordance with his interests. Power then becomes a crucial
variable in the study of social systems' (Rex, 1961, p. 112).
In Rex's scheme we have a conflict theory characteristic of the
sociology of radical change. based upon the action frame of refer-
ence. He summarises the main characteristics of his model in the
following terms:
I. Instead of being organised around a consensus of values, social
systems may be thought of as involving conflict situations at
central points. Such conflict situations may lie anywhere be-
tween the extremes of peaceful bargaining in the market place and
open violence.
2. The existence of such a situation tends to produce not a unitary
but aplurnl.wciety, in which there are two or more classes, each
of which provides a relatively self-contained social system for its
members. The activities of the members take on sociological
meaning and must be explained by reference to the group's
interests in the conflict situation. Relations between groups are
defined at first solely in terms of the conflict situation.
3. In most cases the conflict situation will be marked by an unequal
balance of power so that one of the classes emerges as the ruling
class. Such a class will continually seek to gain recognition of the
legitimacy of its position among the members of the subject class
and the leaders of the subject class will seek to deny this claim
354 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
and to organise activities which demonstrate that it is denied
(e.g. passive resistance).
4. The power situation as between the ruling and subject classes
may change as a result of changes in a number of variable factors
which increase the possibility of successful resistance or actual
revolution by the subject class. Amongst these variable factors
are leadership, the strength of the members' aspirations, their
capacity for organisation, their possession of the means of viol-
ence, their numbers and their role in the social system proposed
by the ruling class .
.S. In the case of a dramatic change in the balance of power the
subject class may suddenly find itself in a situation in which it
cannot merely impose its will on the former ruling class, but can
actually destroy the basis of that class's existence. New divi-
sions within the revolutionary class may open up, but these may
be of an entirely different kind to those which existed in the
previous conflict situation.
6. The social institutions and culture of the subject class are geared
to, and explicable in terms of, the class's interest in the conflict
situation. So far as its long-term aims are concerned, these tend
to be expressed in vague and Utopian forms. When the subject
class comes to power its ~tual practices will still have to be
worked out. But it is likely that they will be justified and even
affected by the morality of conflict and by pre-revolutionary
charters and utopias.
7. A change in the balance of power might lead not to complete
revolution, but to compromise and reform. In this case new
institutions might arise which are not related simply to the pro-
secution of the conflict, but are recognised as legitimate by both
sides. Such a truce situation might in favourable circumstances
give rise to a newunitarysocial orderoveralongperiod, in which
limited property rights and limited political power are regarded
as legitimately held by particular individuals. But such situations
are inherently unstable because any weakening of the counter-
vailing power of the formerly subject class would lead the former
ruling class to resume its old ways and the maintenance of this
power could easilyencouragethesubject class to push right on to
the revolutionary alternative. (Rex, 1961, pp. 129-30)
The conflict theories of both Dahrendorfand Rex, whilst differ-
ing in terms of the subjectivo-objective dimension of our analyti-
cal scheme, both emphasise that central attention must be devoted
to the structure of power and authority in any analysis of contem-
porary society. They both draw upon the concept of class as an
analytical tool and recognise the conflict between interest groups
as the motor force of social change. Their theories radicalise the
strains and tensions which, as will be apparent from our discussion
Radical Structuralism 355
in Chapter 4, characterise functionalist theory. In particular, they
start from the premise that society is characterised by divergent
interests rather than the functional unity presumed in the
organismic model. They adopt a model which stresses that society
is 'factional' rather than organismic in nature, and in this respect
can be seen as developing a line of enquiry which logically emerges
from Merton's concept of 'dysfunction'. As we suggested in our
discussion on conflict functionalism in Chapter 4, this notion lays
the basis for a truly radical critique of society. since, as noted by
Gouldner ( 1959), it opens the door to 'functional autonomy' and
hence 'contradiction' as a basic system characteristic. Dahrendorf
and Rex stop some way short of developing the full implications of
this possibility, which would lead them much closer to various
forms of Marxist analysis and a greater and more specific emphasis
upon the notions of 'contradiction' and ·catastrophe'.
Interestingly enough, the spirit of this critique of the conflict
theory of Dahrendorf and Rex has been captured by Loekwood,
who approaches their work from a slightly different perspective. In
his well-known article 'Social Integration and System Integration'
(1964), he takes Dahrendorf and Rex to task for focusing their
attention upon 'social integration' rather than 'system integra-
tion'. Linking this basic distinction with Marxist theory, he con-
tends that the propensity to class antagonism is a reflection of the
degree of 'social integration' and can be affected by superstruc-
tural factors which influence the degree of 'identification', 'com-
munication', etc., whereas the dynamics of class antagonisms are
fundamentally related to contradictions within the economic sys-
tem. In Marxist theory emphasis is explicitly placed upon these
·contradictions' or problems of 'system integration', whereas in
the work of the conflict theorists emphasis is placed upon the
analysis and problems of 'social integration'. Lockwood believes
that whilst these two features are interrelated they are both analyt-
ically separate and distinguishable, and that at any point in time
different combinations of 'social integration' and 'system integra-
tion' may prevail (Lockwood, 1964, pp. 249-50). In essence,
Lockwood seeks to explain the possibility of social order within a
system characterised by fundamental contradictions in its basic
structure. In this and other ways his position is quite similar to that
of Althusser.
The interface between the work of Marx and of Weber appears
as an intellectual terrain calling for a great deal more attention than
it has received up to now. It seems possible, for example, to clarify
many of the points at issue between radical Weberians or conflict
356 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
theorists and their Marxist critics by recognising that the
intellectual traditions upon which they draw approach the study ot
contemporary social formations from different perspectives. using
different analytical constructs and, as a result, they stress in the
course of their analysis the importance of different elements of the
totality which characterises a particular social formation. Let us
examine these points in a little more detail. The radical Weberians,
following Weber, approach the study of contemporary society
from a perspective concerned with explaining the degree and
nature of 'social integration'. The Marxist theorists approach the
study from a perspective concerned to explain why the social
system is in the process of change and disintegration. This is the
distinction which Lockwood (1964) has drawn between the con-
cern for 'social integration' as opposed to ·system integration', or
perhaps more appropriately, 'disintegration'. These different
perspectives favour different analytical constructs. Thus, the radi-
cal Weberians favour ·power', whereas the Marxist theorists
favour ·contradiction'. A focus upon power allows the radical
Weberian to explain how society is integrated through coercion or
the domination of particular interest groups. A focus upon contra-
diction allows the Marxist theorist to explain social change in terms
of the antagonistic relationship between system elements striving
to achieve autonomy from the dominating forces which weld them
together. As a result, the radical Weberians and Marxists tend to
stress the importance of different elements of the social formation.
The radical Weberians within the radical structuralist paradigm
tend to focus upon the 'superstructure', where the conflict of
interests between different power groups are most evident. Thus
there is often a primary concern for the role of the State and the
political, legal, administrative and ideological apparatus through
which the dominant interest groups secure their position within
society. The Marxist theorist focuses his interest, first and fore-
most, upon the forces operating within the ·substructure' or
economic base ofsociety.n Although many Marxist theorists have
concerned themselves with the nature of the relationship between
substructure and superstructure and the relative autonomy of the
latter (Aithusser and Balibar, 1970; Cutler et al. 1977), they are at
one in recognising an analysis of the economic substructure as
central to an understanding of the contradictions which act as the
generators of social change and disintegration.
Stated in this somewhat bald and oversimplified way. some of
the distinctions and similarities between the views of the radical
Weberian and the various types of Marxist thought become easier
Radical Structuralism 357
to see. For the most part their respective problematics have been
quite distinct. The radical Weberians have tended to focus upon
the relationships between social integration and power as mani-
fested in the superstructure of the social formation. Marxist theor-
ists, have tended to focus upon the relationships between system
disintegration, contradiction, and substructure /superstructure
relationships.
The increasing attention which has recently been devoted to the
nature of the relationships between substructure and superstruc-
ture could usefully be extended to embrace the interrelationships
between the other elements which distinguish radical Weberian
and Marxist thought. The relationships between the concepts of
contradiction and power, and social integration and system disin-
tegration, also seem worthy of attention. It seems clear, for exam-
ple, that the concepts of contradiction and power are connected in
some form of dialectical relationship in which the form of one
presupposes the form of the other. Power can be seen, for exam-
ple, as the manifestation of •contradictory' relationships between
elements within the social formation as a whole. Similarly, as
Lockwood has argued, there is a balance and a relationship be-
tween ·social integration' and the state of •system disintegration'.
Further developments in sociological theory within the radical
structuralist paradigm thus might welt focus upon the complex
network of relationships and concepts which characterise theories
seeking to explore the relationship between the contributions of
Marx and Weber.
This discussion perhaps serves to illustrate the similarities and
distinctions between the perspective of the radical Weberian con-
flict theorists and Marxists such as Althusser, and their respective
locations within the bounds of the radical structuralist paradigm.
As will be clear from Figure 3.3, conflict theory, in its attempt to
explore the interface between Marx and Weber (albeit in a very
limited way), can be regarded as characteristic of a sociology of
radical change located on the boundary of the radical structuralist
paradigm.
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
Theories within the radical structuralist paradigm are thus based
upon relatively objectivist assumptions with regard to the nature of
social science, and are geared to providing a radical critique of
358 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
contemporary society. They do so by focusing upon the in-built
forces which they see as creating basic and deep-seated pressures
for social change. With the possible exception of conflict theory,
they present theories of social change in which revolution, often
bloody, plays a central part. The paradigm reflects a sociology of
radical change in which the idyllic vision of non-violent revolution
through consciousness, such as that envisaged by many radical
humanists, is left far behind. From the standpoint of radical struc-
turalism, change in society almost inevitably involves a transfor-
mation of structures which, even given favourable circumstances,
do not fall or change of their own accord. Structures are seen as
being changed, first and foremost, through economic or political
crises, which generate conflicts of such intensity that the status
quo is necessarily disrupted or torn apart and replaced by radically
different social forms.
All schools of thought within the paradigm are predicated, in
varying degrees, upon four central notions. First. there is a general
acceptance of the notion of totality. All theories within the radical
structuralist paradigm, like those of the radical humanist para-
digm, address themselves to the understanding of total social
formations. Second, there is the notion of structure. The focus, in
contrast to that of the radical humanist paradigm, is upon the
configurations of social relationships which characterise different
totalities and which exist independently of men's consciousness of
them. Structures are treated as hard and concrete facticities,
which are relatively persistent and enduring. Social reality for the
radical structuralist is not necessarily created and recreated in
everyday interaction, as, for example, many interpretive theorists
would claim. Reality exists independently of any reaffirmation
which takes place in everyday life.
The third notion is that of contradiction. Structures, whilst seen
as persistent and relatively enduring, are also seen as posed in
contradictory and antagonistic relationships one to another. The
notion of contradiction, like that of alienation within the radical
humanist paradigm, has both a symbolic and a substantive aspect.
It is symbolic in the sense that it stands for the radical structural-
ists' hope and belief that capitalist social formations contain within
them the seeds of their own decay.ln substantive terms, the notion
of contradiction varies in definition and use within the context of
this overall symbolic umbrella. Some of the fundamental contra-
dictions which have been recognised are those between the rela-
tions of production and the means of production; between
exchange value and surplus value; between the increasing social-
Radical Structuralism 359
isation of the forces of production and the narrowing basis of their
ownership; between capital and labour; between the increasing
anarchy of market and centralisation of production. Different
theorists tend to select and emphasise different contradictions,
and with varying degrees of explicitness. Where Bukharin 's histor-
ical materialism is concerned, for example, the notion of contra-
diction pervades his work in implicit fashion, in terms of a basic
incompatibility between any given technology and the basis of
man's relationship to nature. In Althusser's sociology the notion of
contradiction is more explicit, and also more varied. He identifies
many forms of contradiction which, in certain configurations, act
as the motor force behind revolutionary social change. Within the
context of conflict theory, the treatment of contradiction is more
implicit and, indeed, more superficial. For example, attention is
devoted principally to the analysis of class conflict as the surface
manifestation of a more deep-seated structural imbalance
embedded in the nature of contemporary industrial society.
The fourth notion central to schools of thought belonging to the
radical structuralist paradigm is that of crisis. All theories within
the paradigm view change as a process involving structural dis-
location of an extreme form. The typical pattern is that in which
contradictions within a given totality reach a point at which they
can no longer be contained. The ensuing crisis, political,
economic, and the like, is viewed as the point of transformation
from one totality to another, in which one set of structures is
replaced by another of a fundamentally different kind.
The underlying unity and distinctive nature of the paradigm
becomes clearly evident when compared with its functionalist
neighbour. Despite sharing an approach to the study of social
reality, which emphasises how society is ontologically prior to
man and can be understood through positivist epistemology, the
orientation of radical structuralism is towards fundamentally
different ends. As we have seen, the emphasis in radical structural-
ism is upon contradiction and crisis. These factors receive no
attention within the functionalist paradigm; they are essentially
alien to this perspective, since its fundamental aim is to account
for the persistence and survival of existing social forms. Func-
tionalism is concerned with evolutionary as opposed to catas-
trophic change. Even the most change-orientated schools of
thought within the context of the functionalist paradigm are
markedly different from, and conservative in orientation when
compared with, their immediate neighbours within radical
structuralism.
360 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
Notes and References
1. In the Grundrisse, Marx provides the ·outlines' or founda-
tions of the critique of political economy which was to
occupy the remainder of his life's work. These 'outlines'
were primarily in note form and probably never intended for
publication. Though written in the late 1850s, they were not
published until1939, and they have only recently been trans-
lated from the original German and published in English for
the first time.
The three volumes of Capital - Marx's major work -
elaborate but a small part of the schema put forward in the
Grundrisse. Marx died with the vast proportion of his work
incomplete.
2. See, for example, Godelier ( 1972). He maintains that in Capi-
tal there are two central notions of 'contradiction', and a
variety of contexts in which they are used. As he puts it,
First of all there is the contradiction between workers and
capitalists. Then there are the economic 'crises' in which con-
tradictions appear between production and consumption. be-
tween the conditions of production of value and surplus value
and the conditions of their realisation, and basically between
production forces and relations of production. Finally there are
the contradictions between capitalism and small peasant or
artisan property, capitalism and socialism, etc. This simple list
. reveals differences of nature and importance among these con-
tradictions, of which some are internal to the system. and others
exist between the system and other systems. They must there-
fore be analysed theoretically. (Godelier, 1972, p. 350).
In this 'theoretical analysis' Godelierposits that Marx sees
some contradictions as 'specific' to capitalism, created by it
and reproduced continually within it. Within such a structure
these are internal contradictions 'antagonistic' to social
stability and likely therefore to be central to the violent
overthrow of the capitalist mode of production. Such an
antagonistic contradiction is evident to sociologists, etc .• in
the class struggle. More important, however, says Godelier,
there is a contradiction between structures recognised within
Capital. This is the contradiction between the increasing
socialisation of the forces of production (that is, their widen-
ing societal impact) and the narrowing basis of ownership.
Thus in the long term there are more and more producers:
Radical Structuralism 361
fewer and fewer of the bourgeoisie. However, this contradic-
tion is not originally present within capitalism; it only comes
about at a certain stage in the development of the capitalist
productive mode, when its 'positive' liberating element has
dried up and large-scale industry replaces the small-scale
production typical of early capitalism.
3. The concept of 'surplus value' and its link with the economic
structure of capitalism is by no means an easy one to grasp
and it has been the subject of much debate within economics.
Whilst surplus value is clearly defined as the extra value a
capitalist has control of after he has paid wages to the worker
- that is, the terrain upon which industrial relations and
particularly wage bargaining is fought - it is unclear how
'surplus value' relates to the tendency within capitalism for
'the rate of profits to fall'. In other words, there is an opacity
about the status of the concepts and nature of the relationship
between ·surplus value', the 'fundamental contradictions'
within capitalism and the 'economic crises' to which these
inevitably lead. Contemporary Marxist political economy is
replete with new identifications of the fundamental contra-
diction and discussions of the empirical evidence or lack of
it, for the falling rate of profit. The arguments are beyond the
scope of this exposition, but what is important is that one
recognises that, for Marx, ·surplus value' and the 'exploita-
tion' which it reflects lies at the heart of the contradictions
which blight capitalism. The central empirical reflection of
these contradictions (between the relations of production
and means of production, between exchange value and sur-
plus value, between capital and labour, between the measure
oflabour time and the use oflabour time, etc.) is the tendency
for the rate of profits to fall. As this happens, and the deeply
rooted antagonistic contradictions work to the surface, the
final, cataclysmic economic crisis occurs. Surplus value,
then, represents the economic conceptualisation central to
Marxian analysis which provides the link between deep-
seated structural contradictions and their reflection in
economic cataclysms for which revolution becomes the only
possible solution.
4. For the view that the move from an emphasis on 'alienation•
to ·surplus value' indicates a continuity within Marx in the
study of the 'dialectics of labour', see From Alienation to
Surplus Value (Walton and Gamble, 1972).
S. McLellan describes this movement succinctly as follows:
362 Sociological Paradigms and Or~:anisational Analysis
Towards the end of his life Mar" moved nearer to the positivism
then so fashionable in intellectual circles. This tendency, begun
in Anti-Duhrinl( and continued by Engels in his Ludwil( Feuer-
bach and Dialectics of Nature, reached its apogee in Soviet
te"tbooks on dialectical materialism. It was this trend which
presented Marxism as a philosophical world-view or Weltan-
schauunl( consisting of objective laws and particularly laws d
the dialectical movement of matter taken in a metaphysical sense
as the basic constituent of reality. This was obviously very
different from the ·unity of theory and practice' as exemplified
in, for instance, the Theses on Feuerbach. This preference for
the model of the natural sciences had always been with Engels,
though not with Marx, who had, for example, a much more
reserved attitude to Darwinism. (McLellan, 1976, p. 423)
6. In Anti-Diihring, a personal attack upon a German socialist
(for which, incidentally, Engels had received Marx's
approval for publication) Engels set the scene for the move-
ment towards positivistic ·scientific socialism'. He painted a
picture of Marx's ideas as representative of a totally com-
prehensive frame of reference which provided the laws of
motion for a causally determined process in which socialism
would inevitably replace capitalism. Furthermore, such a
view replaced philosophy itself.
At Marx's graveside, Engels explicitly compared the work
of Darwin in the natural sciences with that of Marx in the
social sciences.
7. It is important to emphasise that Marx himself did not use the
terms 'historical materialism' or 'dialectical materialism',
and that there has been much debate about what exactly they
mean.
8. See, for example, Colletti (1972) and Althusser (1971).
9. For a discussion of the relationship between Weber's politi-
cal and sociological views, see Giddens ( 1972b).
10. Plekhanov stands as the founding father of contemporary
Russian social theory. For a selection of his work, see
Plekhanov (1974) in which his stance within the Engelsian
tradition is described thus:
Plekhanov was an ardent defender of materialist dialectics,
which he skilfully applied to social life, correctly considering it as
an achievement of Marxist philosophic thought. He saw in it the
great and the new which, combined with the masterly discovery
of the materialist conception of history, distinguishes Marx's
materialism from the teachings of materialists before him.
Radical Structuralism 363
Plekhanov brings out the various aspects of materialist dialectics
and brilliantly expounds the theory of development, the correla-
tion between evolution and revolution,leaps, etc. In this connec-
tion he shows the opposition between Marx's dialectical method
and Hegel's, and considers the role of Hegel's idealist philoso-
phy as one of the theoretical sources of Marxism. (Piekhanov,
1974, p. 49)
The work of both Bukharin and Kropotkin discussed here
owes a great deal to Plekhanov.
11. See, for example, Gouldner (1970), 'Functionalism goes
East', in Gouldner, The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology,
op. cit., pp. 455-58.
12. For a detailed study of Bukharin's biography, see Cohen
(1974).
13. See, for example, van den Berghe (1969) and the discussion
in Chapter 2 of this book.
14. There are several very readable biographical accounts of
Kropotkin and his work. See, for example, Woodcock
(1975), pp. 171-206; Avrich (1967), pp. 26-32; Bose (1967),
pp. 257-98.
IS. For a comprehensive list of Kropotkin's publications, see
Bose (1967), pp. 261-2.
16. Perry Anderson in Considerations on Western Marxism
(1976) tends to view Althusser and Colletti in the same light
as Lukacs, Gramsci, Marcuse, etc., as part of 'Western
Marxism'. In using the term 'contemporary Mediterranean
Marxism' we seek obviously to differentiate this type of
theorising from other varieties of Marxism in Western
Europe which stand, for us, in a different paradigm. Interest-
ingly, 'Mediterranean Marxism• is relatively popular in Bri-
tain.
17. See, for example, Colletti (1974).
18. See, for example, Anderson (1976), p. 46.
19. For a further discussion of Althusser's background and
approach to Marxism, see Callinicos (1976).
20. For a discussion of the 'epistemological break', see
Althusser (1969). This notion is taken from Bachelard.
21. In addition to Althusser (1969), see also Althusser and
Balibar (1970).
22. For a comparison of Althusser's structuralism with that of
Levi-Strauss, see Glucksmann ( 1974).
23. For a useful glossary of Althusser's terminology, see
Althusser (1969), pp. 248-S7.
364 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
24. The obscurity is also present in Althusser. The concept of
·overdetermination' is taken in modified form from Freud.
25. For a further discussion of this, see Althusser (1969), pp.
88-116.
26. For a discussion, see, for example, Shaw (1975).
27. Della Volpe (1897-1968) was a Marxist philosopher who
sought to provide a much more positive interpretation of
Marxism than those of Lbkacs and Gramsci.
28. See, for example, the essay 'Marxism as a Sociology' in
Colletti (1972).
29. See, for example, Colletti (1974), p. 12.
30. For a discussion of the commonality of interest between
Marx, Weber and Durkheim, see Giddens (1971).
31. In particular, Dahrendorfargues that the crisis of capitalism,
based upon increasing immiseration of the proletariat,
increasing polarisation between proletariat and bourgeoisie
and increasing homogeneity within the two classes has been
'proved' empirically untenable at every turn (Dahrendorf,
1959, pp. 36-71).
32. This is taken from Dahrendorf( 1959), pp. 237-40. The list of
thirty-nine assumptions presented by Dahrendorf has been
reduced here, largely by removing those which are purely
definitional.
It is interesting to note that in his conceptualisation
Dahrendorf draws upon Merton's distinction between
'manifest' and 'latent' functions, developing the radical
implications which these suggest.
33. 'Marxist' is used here as a shorthand for Marxist theorists
located within the radical structuralist paradigm. The focus
of interests of 'Marxists' within the radical humanist para-
digm is, of course, quite different.
11. Radical Organisation
Theory
In recent years a number of social theorists have sought to
approach the study of organisations from a perspective charac-
teristic of the radical structuralist paradigm. For the most part they
have attempted to do this by providing a critique of the problems
inherent in the functionalist approach. As in the case of the
interpretive and radical humanist paradigms, the radical struc-
turalist approach to the study of organisations has developed in a
reactive mould. The critique which has evolved has been wide-
ranging, far from coherent and, at times, highly polemical. Func-
tionalist theorists in general. and organisation theorists in particu-
lar, have been accused of being the mere servants of the capitalist
system; of being mindlessly empiricist; of neglecting the historical
dimensions of their subject; of ignoring the whole body of social
thought reflected in the works of Marx; of underplaying the impor-
tance of class relationships in contemporary society; of ignoring
the importance of the State; and of adopting analytical models
which are generally orientated towards the preservation of the
status quo. as opposed to accounting for the phenomena of ongo-
ing social change. Not all theorists who have attempted to provide
a critique of functionalism in this way are located within the radical
structuralist paradigm. Indeed, as will be apparent from our dis-
cussion of functionalist sociology, many functionalists have criti-
cised their colleagues on some of these grounds, in order to forge a
more radical perspective within the context of the functionalist
paradigm. Again, radical structuralists have not always provided a
critique upon all the above grounds. Typically, one or more has
been given the focus of attention. The critique of functionalism has
been launched from a variety of perspectives and with a variety of
objectives in mind.
We wish to argue here that behind the radical structuralist criti-
que of functionalism lies a latent and only partially developed
approach to the study of organisations. Whilst not altogether co-
herent, it is united on certain themes. As an attempt at the articula-
366 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
tion ofsomeofthese, Table 11.1 presents a sample of twelve points
on which functionalist theory has been criticised and counterposes
these with the assumptions which implicitly underlie the radical
structuralist critique. In criticising functionalism, the radical struc-
turalists imply that they hold an alternative point of view. Whilst
this is not always systematically developed or clearly articulated,
it does underwrite their criticism, and it is as well that it be spell
out. The twelve points thus go some way towards presenting the
overall flavour of the wide-ranging nature of the radical structural-
ist critique.
Table 11.1
The unity ~the radical structuralist attack upon organisation theory
Points of criticism dir~ct~d
tlllainst orflanisation th~ory
By implication this would SU/lfl~St tit~
followinfl flUidt!lin~s for a rt~dical
orRanisation th~ory
1. Organisation theory is locked Instead of 'having their eyes turned downward
into an acceptance of and their palms upward', orpni$ation theorists
manqerially defined should 'study the structure of social
problems. oppression and bring this knowledge and the
power that it conveys to the powerless and
exploited social rruUority' •1
2. Organisation theorists Organi~ation theorists should seek to carry out
consciously or unconsciously 'action-research' which has discontinuous
play an active and concrete revolutionary change as its objective. Theory
role ifl man's degradation and practice should be unified into a seamless,
within the work place. intellectual activity of which the theorist is
well aware. 3
3. It ignores the contribution of Detailed and extensive knowledge of the work
Marx. of the mature Marx is a sin~ qua non for any
radical orpnisation theory.
4. It neglects tbe analysis of class The concept of class should form an integral
relations. part of any coherent radical orpnisation
theory.
'· It is based upon a very
narrow and misleading
interpretation of Weber.
6. It neglects tbe role of the
State.
Weber should be read in more depth and with
greater understanding. Most functionalist
organisation theorists completely misrepresent
bis views on bureaucracy, and misuse his
concept of the 'ideal type'.
Organisational analysis depends upon a theory
of tbe state which is still in need of detailed
articulation.
Radical Organisation Theory 367
Table 11.1 (continued)
Points of criticism dir~ct~d
t.rllt.rinst or~tt.rnisation th~ory
7. It is ahistorical.
8. It is 'static:', i.e., it assumes
a tendency to equilibrium, a
societal consens.us and
organic: unity.
9. It is basically empiricist. i.e.
concerned with methodology
above all.
10. It is anti-theoretical.
11. It is basically unaware of the
crucial importance of macro-
societal factors 'external' to
the organisation.
12. Its recurrent attempts to
provide a general theory
suggest the possibility and
desirability of a synthesis
when in fact, this is
unattainable.
By implication this would SUilll~St th~
followinR RUid~lin~s for a radi('a/
orRanisation th~ory
Radical organisation theory should have a
historical dimension. In order to understand
organisations today, there is a need to
comprehend them as they have been in the
past, and indeed, to understand how and why
they developed in the first place.
Organisation theory should be dynamic: - it
should conceive of society as a process which
develops throuah the interplay of contradictory
forces, which can result in m;Uor upheavals
and irregular patterns of change.
Instead of beginning with an emphasis _upon the
rigour of observation and 'experimental'
technique, radical organisation theory should
seek to assert the primacy of a coherent
theoretical perspective which is not necessarily
subject to the tyranny of data.
Suspicion of 'theory' in conventional analysis
should be inverted, so that radical organisation
theory must celebrate the development of
large-scale, politically relevant theoretical
perspectives.
Radical organisation theory must start from the
basic assumption that organisations cannot be
understood without a prior analysis of the
social processes and structures in which
organisations are thought to exist.
Conventional organisation theory and its
radical counterpart are mutually exclusive. No
synthesis is possible because their
'problematics' are incompatible. Radical
organisation theory cannot, nor should it, seek
to incorporate its functionalist adversary.
The significance of this critique, however, can only be fully
understood, developed and refined against the background of the
intellectual tradition of radical structuralism as a whole. Elements
of the critique are usually based upon elements of this perspective.
As will be apparent from our discussion in the previous chapter,
368 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
radical structuralism presents a diverse and complex body of
thought. However, there does appear to be a measure of coherence
among its constituent elements, and these provide useful
guidelines by which to chart the general direction in which the
overall thrust of radical structuralism takes us as far as the study of
organisations is concerned.
We concluded our previous chapter by suggesting that the core
concepts of 'totality', 'structure', 'contradiction' and 'crisis' were
in large measure unifying themes. Transferred to the realm of the
study of organisations, they assume significance in the following
ways. The notion of totality implies that it is crucial to study total
social formations as a means of understanding the elements of a
social system. It implies that an understanding ofthe nature of the
whole must precede any understanding of constituent parts.
'Totality' thus implies that organisations can only be understood in
terms of their place within a total context, in terms of the wider
social formation within which they exist and which they· reflect.
The significance of the nature and form of organisations only
becomes fully apparent when viewed from this all-embracing point
of view.
From the radical structuralist standpoint, the totality can be
characterised in terms of its basic structural formation. Structures
are treated as hard and concrete facticities which are relatively
persistent and enduring, and which exist independently of men's
consciousness of them. From this point of view, organisations are
structural facticities, but they represent only part of the wider
structural facti city which constitutes the totality. Organisations
are thus structural elements of a wider structure which they reflect
and from which they derive their existence and true significance.
The organisation is, in this sense, a partial reflection of totality.
The notion of contradiction is of relevance to the study of
organisations since, from the radical structuralist view, it is at the
point of production that many of the contradictions within society
come to the fore. Organisations, particularly economic organisa-
tions, are viewed as the stage upon which the deep-seated cleav-
ages within the social formation as a whole are most visible. It is in
the workshop and factory, for example, that the contradictions
between the relations and the means of production, capital and
labour, the measure of and use oflabourtime, and the fundamental
problem of overproduction, are seen as working themselves out. It
is in the empirical facets of this organisational life that contradic-
tions are seen as taking their most visible form. Not all radical
structuralists address themselves to the study of these contradic-
Radical Organisation Theory 369
lions in a direct and specific fashion. As we noted in the previous
chapter, there is a division between the so-called radical
Weberians and the Marxian structuralists on this score. The former
are most concerned with the ways in which contradictions surface
at the level of empirical reality through the interplay of power
relationships and the conflicts which ensue. Their interest in con-
tradictions is thus of an indirect as opposed to a direct nature,
and the concepts which they use and the approach which they
adopt reflect this very clearly.
The radical structuralist notion of crisis, involving the view that
macro-social change is characterised by structural contradiction
and dislocation of an extreme form, has significance for organisa-
tions, in that as structures they are necessarily involved in this
process of dislocation. If there is a change in totality, there is of
necessity a change in organisational forms. The significance of
changes in the structure of organisations can thus be seen in terms
of the changes occurring in the totality as a whole. Organisations
monitor and reflect the movement of totality from one crisis to
another. The study of organisations in crisis, therefore, is of par-
ticular interest to the radical structuralist, as reflecting the proces-
ses which contribute to and characterise totality shifts. Crises of
ownership and control, factory occupations, Wall Street crashes
and large-scale redundancies are of particular significance from
the radical structuralist point of view, not as problems to be sol-
ved, but as episodes yielding considerable insights insofar as the
understanding of the nature of the social formation is concerned.
The notions of'totality', 'structure', 'contradiction' and 'crisis'
thus provide core concepts from which a radical organisation
theory characteristic of the radical structuralist paradigm can be
forged. Taken together, these core concepts, along with the impli-
cations which underlie the radical structuralist critique of func-
tionalism, provide clear indications of the form such a radical
theory of organisations might take. Up to now it has remained
largely embryonic, its various elements scattered around a truly
diverse body ofliterature. As a means of establishing the basis for a
fuller understanding and further development of the perspective as
a whole, it seems necessary to move towards a much more sys-
tematic statement. This is our aim in this chapter. In the following
sections we intend to explore some of the relevant literature in this
area, and we will attempt to specify some of the key issues of
debate.
As will become clear, it is not possible to say that there is but one
approach to the study of organisations from a radical structuralist
370 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
perspective. As in the case ofthe functionalist paradigm, different
views can be put forward according to the nature of the assump-
tions made in relation to each of the two dimensions of our analyti-
cal scheme. In our previous chapter we demonstrated the exist-
ence of a number of distinct schools of thought within the radical
structuralist paradigm. Of these, the two described as conflict
theory and contemporary Mediterranean Marxism appear to
underwrite and be most closely connected with radical organisa-
tion theory at the present time. There may also be literature
addressed to the study of organisations from the standpoint of
what we have called Russian social theory, though of this we are
unaware.
Before discussing the radical organisation theories akin to con-
flict theory and contemporary Mediterranean Marxism, some
further remarks are in order. First, the organisation theorists who
adopt the conflict theory perspective may shun association with
the sociological school of thought which we have described under
that name. Although linked with that perspective, they have
developed their ideas somewhat independently and within the
context of different disciplines. What they have in common, how-
ever, is a commitment to the radical Weberianism which we have
described as characterising conflict theory at a sociological level.
For this reason, and in order to avoid unnecessary confusion, we
shall discuss their contribution to a radical theory of organisations
under the heading radical Weberianism. Second, the contribution
to a radical theory of organisations from the Marxist viewpoint,
whilst sharing many points in common with Althusserian structur-
alism, is not necessarily derived from it, and would not always
claim an allegiance to that perspective as a whole. The work of
Baran and Sweezy (1968) (which we shall consider later), for
example, was developed in parallel with that of Althusser. We
shall thus use the term 'Marxian structuralist' to characterise this
brand of radical organisation theory. Third, as we have argued
earlier, and as all radical theorists would accept, it is not possible
to develop a theory of organisations independent of a theory of the
totality of which they are part. The literature which is relevant to
the development of radical organisation theory is diverse and
contains many works which approach the problem of totality
rather than organisations as such. At first sight, therefore, their
relevance to the study of organisations may seem somewhat
remote.
Radical Organisation Theory 371
Radical Weberian Approaches to a Radical
Organisation Theory
The general flavour of the radical Weberian approach to the study
of organisations is perhaps best captured in the notion of •corporat-
ism', a term which has come to stand for the development of the
seamless web of bureaucratic institutions which exist in modern
society as appendages of(and subservient to) the State.3 The State
is regarded as being at the centre of an octopus-like structure,
whose bureaucratic tentacles stretch out and invade all areas of
social activity. The radical Weberians tend to be interested in the
relationship between the State and this general process of bureau-
cratisation, and they are particularly concerned to understand the
ways in which the State apparatus dominates the wider social
structure within which it exists. The radical Weberians are
interested in ·power' relationships and draw many of their ideas
and conceptualisations from the realm of political science.
The radical Weberian contribution to a radical theory of organ-
isations, therefore, can be elicited from literature which focuses
upon a theory of the totality, in which the State is accorded a
central role. Its implications for organisations as such, whether
State-related or not, have to be culled from this wider background.
Although considerable emphasis is placed upon the analysis of
bureaucracy, it only represents one part of a wider analysis geared
to obtaining an understanding of the social formation as a whole. A
radical theory of organisations from this point of view, therefore.
only has significance when developed and interpreted against this
wider background.
We will commence our review of relevant literature with Ralph
Miliband's book The State in Capitalist Society (1973). At first
sight the assertion that Miliband, a leading intellectual of the New
Left and co-editor of the Socialist Register, has an affiliation with
radical Weberianism might seem to be stretching the imagination
too far. However, it will be remembered that we maintained in the
previous <;hapter that radical Weberianism explores that
intellectual terrain in which the interests of Marx and Weber may
be thought to coincide. Just as Rex and Dahrendorf attempt to
infuse Marxian notions with a potent draught of Weberianism, so
too does Miliband in his consideration of the role of the State
within the advanced capitalist societies. Since Marx himself never
managed to complete a systematic study of the State, Miliband sets
himself the task of providing a Marxist political analysis which can
372 SocioloKica/ ParadiKms and OrJ!ani.wtional Analysis
confront democratic pluralism on its own ground. Whilst pluralism
assumes a competitive. fragmented and diffuse power structure.
Miliband seeks to demonstrate that this view 'is in all essentials
wrong' and 'constitutes a profound obfuscation' of social reality
(Miliband, 1973, p. 6).
Whilst Miliband believes that today we still live within authenti-
cally capitalist societies, there have been many changes since
Marx himself wrote of capitalism. Miliband regards advanced
capitalism as all but synonymous with the giant form of enterprise
found throughout the industrialised West. The ·economic base' of
advanced capitalism is seen as constituted in large measure by
these ubiquitous corporations, and the political arrangements of
the industrialised nations as taking on a fundamentally similar
form. Within these societies, social stratification presents a dif-
ferentiated appearance but, says Miliband, although there is a
plurality of competing elites within such social structures, taken
together these form a 'dominant economic class, possessed of a
high degree of cohesion and solidarity' (Miliband, 1973, p. 45). The
State's relationship with such a dominant class is the focus of the
book, but for Miliband the notion of the State is a complex and
problematic one. In fact, it turns out that the State consists of the
bureaucracies (the 'institutions') whose interrelationships shape
the form of the State system; these are 'the government, the
administration, the military and the police, the judicial branch.
sub-central government and parliamentary assemblies' (Miliband,
1973, p. 50). Miliband goes on to argue that the governments of the
advanced capitalist societies act positively and with good will
towards business and propertied interests (that is, the corpora-
tions) and, furthermore, that the other bureaucracies which
together form the State can normally be counted upon to support
the dominant economic interests. Of course, says Miliband. per-
turbations within this integraterl structure occur, primarily
through competition between organised interest groups, but these
are superficial and incidental to the underlying structure of domi-
nation. This domination also occurs ·at the level of meaning' and
Miliband considers the process of legitimation of the existing
power structure through, for example, political propaganda, the
media of mass communications and the universities, each acting as
a source of political socialisation. In his final chapter Miliband
considers the future, in terms of both the dangers of conservative
authoritarianism and the immense obstacles to the creation of a
truly ·socialist' society. He concludes, following Marx, that only
within the latter will the State be converted 'from an organ
Radical Organisation Theory 373
superimposed upon society into one completely subordinated to
if.
It should be clear from this brief exposition of Miliband's book
that he adopts a position much closer to radical Weberianism than
to Althusserian structuralism, a fact revealed quite clearly by
Poulantzas (1969) in his famous critique of The State in Capitalist
Society. 4 Whilst one cannot maintain that Miliband's ideas are at
one with those of Dahrendorf and Rex, there are at this level more
similarities between them than differences. For example, like
these conflict theorists, Miliband recognises the existence of a
lacuna in Marxist thought; he discusses the notion of power as his
central unifying concept; he admits a complicated form of social
stratification within capitalism; his position permits a concern for
explanation 'at the level of meaning' and, last but not least, the
notion of bureaucracy underpins much of his analysis. Of course,
Miliband's references to Weber are few and then mostly hostile,
but this does not and should not mask the essential fact .that his
underlying theoretical position is akin to that of radical Weberian-
ism.
As far as the development of a radical theory of organisation is
concerned, Miliband's analysis emphasises the importance of
obtaining an understanding ofthe theory of the State as a precursor
to a theory of organisations. From this point of view, the latter
cannot be adequately developed before the former. To understand
the operations of the police force, the judiciary and local govern-
ment, as well as industrial organisations, it is imperative to see
them as parts of the State apparatus and to attempt to understand
the processes of mutual interrelationship which link them
together. The radical Weberian perspective emphasises that
organisations cannot be understood as isolated enterprises; their
meaning and significance derive from their location within the
context of the wider social framework, and their activities only
become fully intelligible with this reference point in mind.
Other ideas with a radical Weberian flavour emerge from a close
reading of Eldridge and Crombie's book A Sociology of Organisa-
tions (1974). In essence, the book can be seen as comprising three
parts. 5 The first deals with the literature on organisation theory
and is underpinned by a concern to elucidate a range of sociologi-
cal approaches and interests. This concern follows from Eldridge
and Crombie's attack upon organisation theory for its 'ad hoc'
nature and its attempts to create a ·general theory' when there is no
hope of such a unifying conceptual framework. Thus, rather than
imply conceptual homogeneity, they draw upon organisational
374 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
analysis from both the functionalist and radical structuralist tradi-
tions in an effort to demonstrate the heterogeneity of approaches
to the sociology of organisations. In the second part of the book
Eldridge and Crombie consider the contributions of Spencer, Durk-
heim, Weber and Marx through their respective treatments of the
·organisational phenomenon'. It is important to note, however,
that the incorporation of Spencer and Marx at this point is
achieved through a conceptual leap of imagination, since the
authors make no clear-cut distinction between organisations as
empirical facticities and the ·mode of social organisation'. 6 This
allows an important link to be made between the levels of analysis
of society and organisation, but, at the cost of a certain amount of
confusion. 7 It is only in the third part of Eldridge and Crombie's
work that radical Weberianism becomes evident, as they become
involved in a discussion of the links between organisation and
society provided by the notion of power. Their analysis draws
heavily upon the literature and concepts of political science. They
discuss in some detail totalitarianism, with particular reference to
Nazi Germany; Michels's •iron law of oligarchy' is also con-
sidered, and a final section oftheir work is devoted to a ·critique of
pluralism', in which Miliband's analysis plays a central part. Their
attitude to Miliband, however, is somewhat ambivalent, for they
seem to sympathise with the analysis contained within The State in
Capitalist Society but are doubtful about the ·solutions' and
prophecies which it advocates. Eldridge and Crombie's book thus
reflects various elements of the radical Weberian perspective,
though they must be sifted from the contents of their work as a
whole.
A third example of a nascent radical Weberianism is to be found
in Nicos Mouzelis's introduction to the 1975 edition of Organisa-
tion and Bureaucracy. Whilst the original edition of this book
focuses primarily upon the tradition of functionalist organisation
theory and presents a well articulated account of the development
of organisational analysis within this paradigm, the new introduc-
tion to the 1975 edition reflects a considerable change in theoretical
orientation. Here Mouzelis seeks to point to some of the ways in
which organisation theory might fruitfully develop, and in so doing
adopts a position in many ways characteristic of radical Weberian-
ism. After discussing various aspects of the problem of reification
in social analysis, Mouzelis turns to the work of Althusser as a
means of providing a critique of what he sees as the excessive
empiricism and atheoretical nature of much contemporary organ-
isation theory. Whilst suggesting that Althusser's perspective has
Radical Organisation Theory 375
much to offer organisation theory, he does not develop its i mplica-
tions to any marked degree. Instead, he turns to emphasising the
need for a more historically based approach to the study of organ-
isations, which Althusser does not provide, and proceeds to illus-
trate what he has in mind through a discussion of the development
of State bureaucracies. This discussion draws heavily upon the
work of Weber, and elaborates upon the class relations and power
struggles which have characterised the emergence and develop-
ment of the process of bureau~ratisation in Western Europe.
Mouzelis demonstrates very clearly the way in which bureau-
cracies have developed their power base and have achieved a high
degree of autonomy within society, to the extent that they now
stand not so much as ·a neutral tool at the service of the people and
its legitimate leaders', but as 'the real master' (Mouzelis, 1975,
p. xxxiv). His analysis reflects many of the concerns of radical
Weberianism. The concern for the power structure within society,
the place of the State bureaucracy within it, and the possibility of
bureaucracy's domination of its intended masters, are central to
his perspective. Mouzelis thus points the way towards a radical
organisation theory based upon an historical analysis which pays
central attention to the nature of organisations within the context
of the power structure of society as a whole. Within this
framework, the nature and role of the State apparatus would
qualify for special attention.
In their paper 'Organisation and Protection' ( 1977) McCullough
and Shannon address a number of the issues referred to above, and
place particular emphasis upon relationships between organisa-
tions and the State. They maintain that within organisation theory
the predominant conceptualisation of the relationship between
organisations and the State is one of dissociation, in which organ-
isations and the State are viewed as ·separable, rational, self-
conscious and self-determining entities' (McCullough and Shan-
non, 1977, p. 72). In practice, they argue, the relationship is quite
different from this, with the State extending 'protection' to organ-
isations which lie within the scope ofintluence -and that, histori-
cally, this is the role which the State has always performed. In line
with this argument, they see the multi-national corporations of
today not so much as phenomena which stand in opposition to the
sovereignty of nation states, but as phenomena which are to be
understood as part and parcel of the development which has led to
the nation state in its present form; as components of the same
repressive system of world division of labour based upon exploita-
tion. McCullough and Shannon adopt a historical perspective for
376 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
much of their analysis, and they present evidence concerning the
role of the State in the growth of the East India Company. for
example, and other State--organisation relationships, as a means
of illustrating the 'hegemonic' nature (as against the liberal,
pluralistic or countervailing nature) of governmental and indus-
trial organisations. In their view the State and organisations have,
internationally and historically, formed an integrated bureaucratic
framework which represents a structure of domination in which
power rests with a small fraction of the population. However, the
integration of this institutional framework is not immutable, nor
does it carry a life-long guarantee, and they point to the contem-
porary situation in Northern Ireland as an illustration. The inabil-
ity of the State there to offer protection to organisations and its
lack of a monopoly of force have, it is argued, entirely disrupted
the normal pattern of organisational life, since the present adminis-
trative, military and legal apparatuses are in a ~ondition of disin-
tegration (McCullough and Shannon, 1977, p. 83). Such.a crisis
offers an opportunity, they suggest, to examine the relationships
between organisations and the State which protects them, in a way
unknown to contemporary organisation theory.
The essence of the radical Weberian perspective which emerges
from this brief review of relevant literature is that organisations
must be studied as elements within the political structure of society
as a whole. This necessarily involves an analysis of power rela-
tionships, particularly in relation to the role of the State, which
stands as the dominant institutional structure offering itself for
analysis. Organisations cannot be understood in isolation. Their
significance arises from their location within the network of power
relations which influence societal processes. From the radical
Weberian standpoint it is this issue of power which stands at the
centre of the analytical stage. The theory of power which under-
writes this perspective is in stark contrast to the pluralist theory
discussed in earlier chapters. It is a theory of power which stresses
the integral as opposed to the intercursive nature of this
phenomenon. The central role accorded to power as a variable of
analysis redirects the organisation theorist's attention towards
issues such as the process of bureaucratisation itself, the increas-
ing concentration of the means of administration in the hands of
bureaucrats, and the rapid development of State intervention in
almost every area of social activity. The macro-orientation of
radical Weberianism points the way towards the development of
macro-theories of organisational process which stand in stark con-
trast to the middle-range theorising reflected in the work of the
Radical OrRanisation Theory 377
majority of organisation theorists located within the functionalist
paradigm. We shall return to some of these issues later in the
chapter. ·
Marxian Structuralist Approaches to a
Radical Organisation Theory
Those theorists who approach the study of organisations from this
perspective tend to place the problems inherent in monopoly capi-
talism at their centre of analysis. Whereas the radical Weberians
are most concerned with the role of the State within an essentially
political network of bureaucratic power relationships. the Marxian
structuralists focus upon the economic structure of society, which
they see as the key determinant ofthe powerrelationships to which
the radical Weberians address their attention. For the Marxian
structuralists, therefore, political economy provides the most use-
ful intellectual reference point and source of conceptualisations.
They are primarily concerned with the analysis of the economic
structures of capitalist society, and they draw upon Marx's Capital
and the notion of 'contradiction' as central elements in their per-
spective. The modern corporation is of interest as an empirical
reflection of the underlying structure of monopoly capitalism; it is
studied as a means of throwing light upon the nature of this under-
lying structure rather than as an entity in its own right. As in the
case of the radical Weberian perspective, organisations only have
significance in relation to the totality in which they are located.
This concern for totality is clearly apparent in the first work
which we consider in our review of literature in this area: Baran
and Sweezy's Monopoly Capital. They begin by quoting Hegel's
dictum 'the truth is the whole', and stress the need to understand
the social order as a totality rather than ·as a collection of small
truths about various parts and aspects of society' (Baran and
Sweezy, 1968, p. 16). Although Marxism is seen to provide the
starting point, Capital itself is seen as a limited document because
of its failure to appreciate the contemporary importance of mono-
poly rather than competition within the capitalist market place.
The authors give Lenin full recognition for his understanding of the
importance of monopolies to the growth of capitalistic imperial-
ism, and it is to the analysis of the large-scale monopoly corpora-
tion that Baran and Sweezy direct their attention. They suggest that
'the typical economic unit in the capitalist world is not the small
378 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
firm producing a negligible fraction of a homogenous output for an
anonymous market but a large-scale enterprise producing a signif-
icant share of the output of an industry, or even several industries,
and able to control its prices, the volume of its production and the
types and amounts of its investments' (Baran and Sweezy, 1968, p.
19). They argue that any model of the economy within advanced
capitalist societies cannot afford to ignore this central point. The
book is seen as a •scientific' sketch on the American economic and
political order, in which 'the generation and absorption of the
surplus • produced under monopoly capitalism is given primary
consideration, since it is seen as the link between the economic
substructure and the political, cultural and ideological superstruc-
ture of society. The economic base is regarded as consisting
largely of giant corporations which act as engines for the accumu-
lation of capital and the maximisation of profits. Such is their
monopoly position that corporations, by controlling price and cost
policies, creat a tendency for the amount of surplus to rise. This
surplus is seen as being consumed, wasted or invested in an effort
to ensure that it is absorbed by the capitalist system without being
distributed among the populace. Thus imperialism, militarism,
the sales effort, government spending and research and develop-
ment are all seen as ways of consuming the surplus and postponing
the inevitable crisis of overproduction. Baran and Sweezy then go
on to ask how this consumption of surplus has affected the quality
of life within a monopoly capitalist society. Using measures of
divorce rates, housing conditions,juvenile delinquency and so on,
they conclude that it represents an 'irrational system'. Monopoly
capitalism is seen as irrational, because it has at its heart a funda-
mental contradiction; whilst the actual processes of production are
becoming more thoroughly rationalised, more controlled and bet-
ter understood, the system as a whole retains an undiminished
elementality - that is, men may seek to understand it but, like the
wind or tides, it remains beyond their control. Baran and Sweezy,
in essence, argue that the deep structures of monopoly capitalism
are not amenable to empirical knowledge if one uses an 'ideology'
of bourgeois economics. They argue that only with a 'scientific'
recognition that it is these economic structures and their interrela-
tionships which are the key to social injustice, and that no altera-
tions to their superstructural manifestation can fundamentally
affect them, will social revolution be possible in America. • Baran
and Sweezy argue that the crisis produced by the profound
economic contradictions inherent in monopoly capital have
already produced, and will continue to produce, revolutionary
Radical Organisation Theory 379
wars which have as their goal decolonisation from 'this intolerable
social order'.
We have here an analysis which draws upon the tradition of
Marxist political economy in order to arrive at an understanding of
the essential structure of capitalist society. The monopolist
corporation is given central attention, and the authors demonstrate
that in terms of wealth and control of economic resources, it is
often more powerful than the state within which it is located. Baran
and Sweezy have stimulated much interest in the analysis of
multi-national corporations, and it is at this level that their work is
perhaps of most relevance to the development of a radical organ-
isation theory. Their use of the concept of economic surplus as a
basic analytical tool presents organisations in a light which is quite
different from that which arises from the notion of the purposive,
goal-orientated rationality which dominates functionalist organ-
isation theory. From Baran and Sweezy's standpoint the signifi-
cance of the monopolistic corporation is ultimately related to the
position which it occupies within the fundamental economic base
of society; its activities - research and development, production,
marketing, etc. - are to be understood in terms of the role which
they play in the generation and use of the economic surplus
necessary to sustain the structure of the capitalist system. Baran
and Sweezy demonstrate the relevance of the concept of surplus to
an analysis of organisations. It provides an important concept
linking organisations to the totality and offers the radical organisa-
tion theorist a powerful tool with which to forge a view of organisa-
tions in fundamental opposition to that evident in the functionalist
perspective.
The relevance of Baran and Sweezy's perspective for the study
of organisations has been taken up by Harry Braverman in a book
entitled Labor and Monopoly Capital (1974). In essence Brav-
erman attempts to 'fill in the gaps' left by Monopoly Capital by
applying Baran and Sweezy's approach to a study of the labour
process, and, in particular, he is concerned with the de-skilling of
work, which he sees as an integral part of organisational reality in
the Western world. The book presents a study of the development
of the capitalist mode of production during the past hundred years
or so, and uses as its starting point the first volume of Marx's
Capital, the obvious core of any Marxist analysis of the labour
process. Braverman rejects any assertion that Marx was a
'technological determinist' and points out that, for Marx, it was
technology itself which was determined by the social form in which
it was placed. Thus Braverman focuses upon the labour process as
380 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
it reflects the relations of production in terms of the class system;
he is interested not so much in 'consciousness' or working-class
activities as in how the labour process is dominated and shaped by
the accumulation of capital. Following an historical analysis of the
development of both labour and management, Braverman turns to
a consideration of various schools of management theory and their
role as reflected in the development of the capitalist mode of
production.
First, he turns his attention to 'scientific management'. Taylor-
ism for him is not a 'science of work', nor is it the 'best way' to do
work 'in general'; it is, on the contrary, ·a science of the manage-
ment of others' work' and represents an answer to the problem of
how best to control 'alienated' labour. The followers of Mayo, in a
continuation of this line of argument, are presented as the 'main-
tenance crew' for the human machinery created by Taylor's
·scientific management'. Today Taylor's successors inhabit work
design and work study departments, while the Mayoites are to be
found upstairs in the personnel office. These tendencies, initiated
by Taylor, have ensured that ·as craft declined, the worker would
sink to the level of general and undifferentiated labour power,
adaptable to a large range of simple tasks, while as science grew, it
would be concentrated in the hands of management' (Braverman,
1974, p. 121). Braverman elaborates on these processes in some
detail, giving historical examples drawn from throughout the
capitalist world. He attaches particular importance to the
scientific-technical revolution and the development of machinery
which otTers to management the opportunity to do by wholly
mechanical means that which it had previously attempted to do by
organisational and disciplinary means. Machinery, then, can only
be seen as part ofthe control system of the organisation and hence
as a reflection of the capitalist mode of production. Under capital-
ism the socio-technical system, of whatever kind, represents for
Braverman a 'modern', 'scientific', 'dehumanised prison of labour'.
Having looked at what stands as contemporary management
theory in this highly critical way, Braverman addresses himself to
the question of the form which monopoly capitalism takes. Follow-
ing Baran and Sweezy, he maintains that monopoly capitalism
consists primarily of monopolistic organisations. However, for
him, these are more consumers of surplus labour than producers of
surplus value. The existence of the modern giant corporation is
seen as having three consequences of key importance for the
occupational structure of the advanced capitalist societies: 'the
first is to do with marketing, the second with the structure of
Radical Organisation Theory 381
management and the third with the function of social co-ordination
now exercised by the Corporation' (Braverman, 1974, p. 26.5). All
of these are seen as ser\ling to consume surplus labour. Since the
market is the prime area of organisational uncertainty, marketing
is necessary in order to control this threat to profitability. Simi-
larly, the growth of an army of clerical workers aids the control and
administration of the corporation, while reducing the level of
surplus labour. Finally, and most important, the development of
the internal co-ordination of the organisation is seen as necessary
because of the lack of overall social co-ordination. The complexity
of the division of labour under capitalism is regarded as requiring
an immense amount of social control, which lies beyond the
capabilities of the public functions of the total society. The internal
planning of such corporations becomes, in effect, social planning
to fill in the existing large gaps in social control left by the State.
Despite these three primary ways of consuming surplus labour,
Braverman argues that all surplus labour cannot be absorbed by
capitalism, so that one inevitably finds, as Marx described, a
reserve army of the working class. It is among this reserve army
that poverty and degradation are at their highest levels. In addi-
tion, Braverman argues, even among the ranks of the employed,
poverty and degradation are essential features of labour under
monopoly capitalism.
Braverman's work can be regarded primarily as a critique of the
ways in which labour develops under monopoly capitalism. His
analysis, in effect, attempts to fill in the interstices of Baran and
Sweezy's work, and he accepts their basic theoretical position
almost without cavil. What is interesting for our present purposes
is the form taken by Braverman's attack upon many of the con-
temporary schools within management theory, an attack which is
predicated upon an analysis of advanced capitalism in terms of its
basic economic structure, using conceptualisations derived from
Marx's Capital. With the aid of detailed examples, Braverman
carefully links the developments of these schools with changes in
the societal means and relations of production. In essence, he
portrays management theory as a superstructural manifestation of
the workings of the economic base of capitalist societies. He
implies that ·as a branch of management science', it 'views all
things through the eyes of the bourgeoisie'. To Braverman, how-
ever, scientific management, human relations, the socio-technical
approach, the quality of working life debate and so on, all r~flect,
in their own ways, the development of the labour process within
monopoly capitalism. Moreover, they become an important
382 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
motive force in this process in their own right. 9 Thus, not only do
theories of organisation and management describe and legitimate
the labour process within advanced capitalism; through their
intervention, they actively and in a concrete way ensure its survi-
val and continued good health.
This is a view with a pedigree which has been. further described
and elaborated by V. L. Allen in his book Social Analysis: A
Marxist Critique and Alternative (197S). Allen begins by giving a
biographical account of his own intellectual development up to the
point where he could see nQ alternative to the complete rejection of
conventional sociological theory. This rejection is seen as the only
possible reaction to a sociology which assumes that social reality is
basically a 'static' phenomenon characterised by consensus, a
tendency to equilibrium and an organic unity. Allen argues that it is
in the attempts of sociological theorists to analyse organisations
that this •static' sociology is most readily visible. His first attack is
upon the "dogma of empiricism' which characterises much of
organisational analysis. The organisational empiricists are seen as
being anti-theory, in that they rely almost exclusively upon a
number of seemingly disparate, data-packed, problem-centred
studies, which seek description rather than causal analysis. If this
trend continues, Allen maintains, the studies of the empiricists will
end up as wholly irrelevant exercises in mathematical methods.
Allen's second target is the theoreticians who have addressed
themselves to the study of organisations. His criticism here is that
they employ static models which view organisations primarily as
self-equilibrating mechanisms. Theories of classical management,
human relations, Weber, March and Simon (1958), and Etzioni
(1961), are all found wanting in this respect, though Allen recog-
nises that some attempt has been made by the latter to modify
equilibrium analysis by introducing some consideration of 'move-
ment' and conflict.
In opposition to these views, Allen offers a 'dynamic' sociology
which is directly concerned with ·movement' and underpinned by
the assumptions and methodology of dialectical materialism. Such
a sociology, he suggests, would concern itself with the ongoing
dynamic processes which affect social situations and would em-
ploy dialectical materialism in the analysis of their causes. A socio-
logy of movement implies that organisations are causally related to
their past states as well as to the hidden and observable features of
their environments, with which there is a perpetual process of
interaction and absorption. In line with such a view, Allen suggests
that we should be concerned with the following questions:
Radical Organisation Theory 383
First, what properties do organisations have in common with their
environments? Second, in what way are organisations distinguished
from both their environments in general and other arrangements of
social relationships in particular? Third, what is the meaning of organ-
isational autonomy in this context? And, lastly, what is the source of
movement in organisations and the mechanism through which it
passes? (Allen, 1975, p. 184)
Allen suggests that the answers to these questions present a
theoretical perspective and approach to the study of organisations
which is both distinct from, and preferable to, that presented by
more statically orientated systems analysis.
Allen maintains that his perspective does not seek to provide a
middle-range theory of organisations, but rather a dynamic gen-
eral theory capable of analysing middle-range situations. In this
task he uses as a building block the concept of structure. He asserts
that economic factors are the 'primary' determinants of social
behaviour but non-economic factors have a degree of ank>nomy.
After giving some consideration to recent writings on structural-
ism, particularly those of Piaget, Boudon and the Marxist struc-
turalists, he concludes that ·every situation possesses a structure
and superstructure’, the former ultimately determining the latter in
an historical context. Allen then proceeds to equate the notions of
structure and superstructure with the respective notions of
·environmental variables’ and organisation, in a way which is
arguably the source of much confusion. 10
In considering the components of the superstructure, Allen
posits that analytically it consists of three elements: skills, power
and ideology (Allen, 1975, pp. 213-47). Organisational environ-
ments are seen as consisting of these same elements, which are
entangled empirically but occupy distinct ‘causal positions’. He
later examines trade unions as organisations in terms of their
interface and interrelationships with these three elements, particu-
larly the dominant ideology of capitalist society.
In his final chapter Allen moves towards a form of dialectical
materialism, treating the concept of dialectic as representative of a
‘process between variables in real social situations’, in which the
totality is crucial. For Allen, the totality of capitalism is shot
through with contradictions, some of which are ‘primary’, some
‘internal’ and some ‘secondary’. Business organisations, for
example, ar~ seen as subject to crises of overproduction, which are
a superstructural manifestation of the prime contradiction within
the capitalist mode of production – the fact that production capac-
ity often exceeds the proletariat’s capacity for consumption
384 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
because of its condition of poverty. The effect of the surfacing of a
primary contradiction within the superstructure, says Allen, is
akin to that of a pebble dropped into a pond. Waves of movement
spread out from the source, producing a variety of effects within
the totality. For Allen, the extent of a totality can be gauged by the
spread of the repercussions (Allen, 1975, pp. 268-71). It is this
form of analysis which Allen views as offering the potential for his
·dynamic’ approach to social analysis. It is a perspective which
emphasises the importance of looking at actual empirical situa-
tions, identifying structures and superstructures, and identifying
the contradictions and their repercussions. Allen sees it as an
approach which throws light on the process of change, ‘but with-
out ever allowing the process to be timed, the climax to be antici-
pated, and its parts named’ (Allen, 1975, p. 292).
In this way Allen seeks to develop the rudiments of a radical
organisation theory based upon a Marxian structuralist analysis.
However, much of Allen’s discussion is cast in a reactive mould,
and great emphasis is placed upon providing a critique of func-
tionalist theory. In certain respects Allen can be regarded as hav-
ing been trapped by this preoccupation with functionalism, to the
extent that he seeks to incorporate the-distinction between organ-
isation and environment in a way which is arguably counter-
productive with respect to the development of a fully developed
and self-sustaining Marxist theory of organisations. Despite these
limitations, however, Allen’s work stands as one of the most
significant and systematic attempts at the construction of a radical
organisation theory.
Allen’s concerns have a relatively well developed pedigree as
far as the literature on industrial relations is concerned. Allen has
long been an advocate of a ·radical’ or Marxist view of industrial
relations in opposition to the functionalist perspective which
dominates this area of study. Other writers, such as Goldthorpe
(1974), Hyman (1975), Hyman and Fryer (1975), Hyman and
Brough (1975) and Wood (1976), have also been concerned to
provide a Marxist critique of functionalist industrial relations
theory, in terms which stress the importance of developing a
theory of the totality of capitalism before one can begin to under-
stand contemporary industrial relations. In varying degrees these
writers address themselves to the political economy of capitalism,
directing attention to inequalities inside and outside the work
place,the problems of trade union organisation within such a mode
of production and the possibilities for sweeping social change. As
yet, however, these authors, collectively and individually, have
Radical rJrganisation Theory 385
not yet produced a well developed radical industrial relations
theory which stands on its own. For the most part they have
contented themselves with providing a critique of the functionalist
orthodoxy and consequently have been locked into a reactive
stance.
Towards the Further Development of Radical
Organisation Theory
Our review ofliterature in the two previous sections of this chapter
has suggested that it is possible at the present time to identify two
relatively distinct approaches to the study of organisations from
within the radical structuralist paradigm. The radical Weberian
and Marxian structuralist perspectives tend to draw upon rela-
tively distinct intellectual traditions and focus upon different areas
of interest. In defining the relationship between. these two
approaches it is convenient to recognise at least five points of
difference, as illustrated in Table 11.2.1n the rest of the chapter we
seek to discuss the significance of these differences, as a means of
clarifying the foundations upon which further developments in
radical organisation theory might be based.
Table 11.2
Some differences in emphasis between Marxian structuralist and
radical Weberian approaches to radical organisation theory
The Marxian structuralist approaches
to a radical organisation theory tend
to stress:
I. Political economy
2. Economic structures
3. Monopoly capitalism
4. Contradiction
S. The catastrophe analogy
The radical Weberian approaches
to a radical organisation theory tend
to stress:
I. Political science
2. Political administrative structures
3. Corporatism
4. Power
S. The factional analogy
The Marxian structuralist approaches to a radical organisation
theory, in looking to the work of the mature Marx as a source of
inspiration, found their analytical framework upon the tenets of
Marxian political economy. They focus upon the economic sub-
386 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
structure of society as the centrepiece of analysis, particularly as it
is reflected in the structure of monopoly capitalism. The notion of
contradiction is emphasised as providing the principal means of
explaining the process of ongoing structural change, generating
periodic crises which will eventually lead to the complete trans-
formation of the totality of capitalism. Insofar as an emphasis is
placed upon crisis and social change upon a macro-scale, these
theorists implicitly draw upon the catastrophe analogy as a means
of modelling the socio-economic system, though the use of the
factional analogy is often consistent with this point of view.
The radical Weberian approaches to a radical organisation
theory, in looking to Weber as the primary source of inspiration,
base their analytical framework upon conceptualisations drawn
from political science. They tend to focus upon political and
administrative structures rather than the economic substructures
of society, and are principally concerned with ·corporatism’ as
opposed to monopoly capitalism. They address themselves par-
ticularly to the structure and development of the State apparatus
within the power structure of society as a whole, and to the way in
which the ‘means of administration’ come to fall under the control
of fewer and fewer hands. Specific attention is devoted not so
much to the direct analysis of contradictions as to the analysis of
power relationships within the superstructure of society. Conse-
quently, the factional as opposed to the catastrophic analogy is
favoured as a basis for analysing basic social processes. Society is
generally seen as dichotomised in terms ofthe factional interests of
a relatively cohesive dominant class which controls the basic
operation of society on the one hand, and the groups which tend to
be subject to that control on the other; society is characterised by
conflicts of interest and power struggles, which provide the motor
force for major social change.
The Marxian structuralist and radical Weberian approaches to a
radical organisation theory stand at the present time as relatively
distinct approaches sharing a commitment to the meta-theoretical
assumptions which characterise the radical structuralist paradigm.
Whether they will follow separate lines of development in the
future remains to be seen. They doubtless contribute their own
special brand of insight to an understanding of organisations within
contemporary society, though, as we argue below, it also seems
that some measure of synthesis is possible. Insofar as they develop
along separate lines, they may be expected to adopt the key con-
ceptualisations and modes of analysis characteristic of the respec-
tive schools of thought from which they derive. as discussed in
Radical Organisation Theory 387
Chapter 10. A great number of issues relevant to the development
of Marxian structuralist and radical Weberian approaches to a
radical organisation theory have already been thoroughly
explored, and there is scope for adapting and welding them to a
specific concern for the study of organisations.
As far as Marxian radical organisation theory is concerned, the
field is wide open. since Marx himself did not specifically address
the problem of organisations. and Marxist theorists up to now have
largely disregarded this middle-range level of analysis.’ 1 Yet it
would seem that a theory of organisations built around the notion
of contradiction and specifically modelled upon some variation of
the factional or catastrophic systems models would have a great
deal to contribute to an understanding of the processes of organis-
ational change, and to its significance within the context of the
totality which characterises the contemporary social formation of
advanced capitalism. Such a perspective would carry Gouldner’s
( 1959) analysis of the notion of •functional autonomy’ to illi logical
conclusion, with a focus upon the contradictory relationships
which exist within organisational contexts. It could also usefully
draw upon work outside the Marxist tradition which has interested
itself in the catastrophic or schismatic tendencies of various types
of system. Rene Thorn’s recent work on catastrophe theory in the
context of mathematical modelling, for example, may have much
to contribute in terms of insight, if not formal technique (Thorn,
1975). 12 Within the field of anthropology the outstanding work of
Gregory Bateson (1973) and Marshall Sahlins (1974) constitute
other sources of inspiration and analytical method. Bateson’s
notion of ‘schismogenesis’. and the analyses of both these theorists
of the factional tendencies which exist within primitive societies,
open the way to similar forms of analysis of the social formations
within the considerably more complex structure of contemporary
society.
As far as a radical Weberian organisation theory is concerned, it
would seem that there is much scope for the development of
models based upon the factional analogy. with a key focus upon
the nature of power relationships within the structure of society as
a whole. As will be evident from our discussion of the work of
theorists already located in this tradition, the view of power which
emerges stands in stark contrast to the unitary and pluralist per-
spectives characteristic of the functionalist paradigm. Indeed, the
radical Weberian approach to the study of societies diverges from
the unitary and pluralist views in terms of its assumptions with
regard to interests, conflict and power, and the key features of this
388 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
essentially “radical’ view can usefully be counterposed with those
presented in Table S.l in the following terms:
Table 11.3
The radical Weberian view of interests, conflict and power
lru,e:st:s
Conflict
Power
The radical view:
Places emphasis upon the dichotomous nature and
mutual opposition of interests in terms of broad socio-
economic divisions of the ‘class’ type within social
formations as a whole. which are also reflected in
organisations in the middle range of analysis.
Regards conflict as an ubiquitous and disruptive motor
force propelling changes in society in general and
organisations in particular. It is recognised that conflict
may be a suppressed feature of a social systein, not
always evident at the level of empirical ‘reality’.
Regards power as an integral. unequally distributed.
zero-sum phenomenon, associated with a general pro-
cess of social control. Society in general and organisa-
tions in particular are seen as being under the control of
ruling interest groups which uercise their power
through various forms of ideological manipulation. as
well as the more visible forms of authority relations.
The radical Weberian approach to a radical organisation theory
thus otTers a mode of analysis which, in focusing upon the totality
of contemporary social formations, allows one to transcend the
insights which emerge from an exclusive pre-occupation with the
middle-range level ofanalysis characteristic of functionalist organ-
isation theory. It is a perspective which emphasises the integral
rather than the intercursive nature of power, interests and conflict
within the context of society as a whole. Whether the radical
Weberian view of power which, as suggested in the previous
chapter, is largely confined to the superstructural aspects of cap-
italism, is adequate as an all-embracing perspective is open to
question. It begs many questions in relation to the role and relative
importance of the economic substructure and superstructure of
society. It is important to emphasise the deep structural elements
in the analysis of social power(what Lukes (1974) has described as
Radical Organisation Theory 389
the •third dimension’). in addition to the view of power which
emerges from the analysis of superstructural factors on their own
account. The radical Weberian view clearly has a special contribu-
tion to make towards a radical organisation theory which attempts
to locate and evaluate the significance of organisations, both
public and private. within the context of the power structure of
contemporary society as a whole.
The question of the relationship between substructural and
superstructural factors within contemporary society conveniently
leads to the issue of whether or not radical organisation theory
might also develop through a further synthesis of the Marxian
structuralist and radieal Weberian perspectives. As we concluded
in our discussion of conflict theory in Chapter 10, such a develop-
ment seems quite a logical and attractive one, since the radical
Weberians and Marxian structuralists tend to approach the study
of social formations from different perspectives, which lead to the
use of different analytical constructs with emphasis upon differ-
ent elements of the total social formation. As we have suggested,
each ofthese three factors can be regarded as being in a dialectical
relationship both internally and in relation to one another. The
respective concerns for social integration and system disintegra-
tion, power and contradiction, superstructure and substructure,
presuppose an attitude to, and a definition of, the others. Radical
organisation theorists might thus usefully focus upon organisa-
tions as elements within a totality which express a certain relation-
ship between power and contradiction, and between substructural
and superstructural factors, and which throw light upon the bal-
ance between social integration and system disintegration within
the totality as a whole.
A systematically developed radical organisation theory charac-
teristic of the radical structuralist paradigm, which follows any of
the three lines presented above, is likely to offer many new insights
with regard to our understanding of organisations in society. It is
likely that it will offer new perspectives on processes of organisa-
tional control; the dynamics of organisational change; the relation-
ship between substructural and superstructural elements of organ-
isation; new typologies for understanding the role and significance
of different organisations within the wider social formation; and
other insights which emerge from the radical structuralist perspec-
tive as a whole. All three lines of development will seek to build
upon the core concepts of totality, structure, contradiction, power
and crisis, and will recognise that a theory of organisations con-
sonant with radical structuralism would involve not so much the
390 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
development of a radical theory of organisations as such, as a
radical theory of society in which organisations are accorded a
central role.
Notes and References
1. These quotes from M. Nicholaus are quoted in Horowitz
( 1971). They appear in a paper advocating a radical sociology
but would also seem germane to a radical organisation
theory.
2. For a discussion of this, see Willener (1971).
3. For a discussion of corporatism, see Pahl and Winkler( 1974),
Winkler (1975 and 1976).
4. The substance of Poulantzas’ criticism is that (I) Miliband
accepts the ‘bourgeois problematic’ and confrolfts their
analysis at the level of concrete empirical reality (that is, he
adopts an empiricist approach, according to Althusser’s
definition of that term); (2) his analysis is couched in inter-
personal ‘subjective’ terms and not in terms of structures
(that is, Miliband seeks explanation at the level of meaning as
well as that of cause); (3) Miliband does not provide a politi-
cal alternative; he is ‘too discrete’. This form of criticism is
precisely what one would expect, given the different assump-
tions and paradigmatic location of Althusserian sociology
and conflict theory, as discussed in the previous chapter.
See, however, Miliband’s reply to this critique; both are
reprinted in Urry and Wakeford (1973), pp. 291-314.
5. The book is published in a series of textbooks which stress
exposition rather than the advocacy of a particular tradition.
The radical Weberianism within the book is thus buried
beneath the exposition of a variety of different perspectives.
The three parts which we identify here are not specifically
recognised in the text. The first part consists of pp. 1-124;
the second, pp. 125-49, the third, pp. 150-204.
6. This conflation of two distinct meanings of ‘organisation’
follows from their definition of the term derived from Weber.
They expand on this point as follows:
We note in anticipation that the concept of organisation is cer-
tainly not a synonym for bureaucracy. Whereas we have seen
that Caplow, Parsons and Etzioni define organisation as a kind of
Radical Organisation Theory 391
social system and Maciver and Page as a kind of social group, for
Weber it is treated as a kind of social relationship. This is the
term employed to denote the existence of a probability that
between two or more persons there is a meaningful course of
social action. By pointing to the significance of an individual’s
social behaviour, Weber is wanting to avoid the reification of a
collective concept like organisation, state, church and so on.
(Eldridge and Crombie, 1974, p. 27)
7. Eldridge and Crombie’s notion of the ‘organisational
phenomenon’ only serves to mask two distinctive problema-
tics. The first focuses upon organisations as middle-range,
empirical facticities, which are seen as networks of social
relationships forming, through their interdependencies, con-
crete structures. The second problematic lies not with organ-
isations but with principles of organisation. Thus Sper,cer
asked what rules or types of organising principle under-
pinned a whole range of social formations from the mi_litary to
the industrial. Marx, on the other hand, was concerned to ask
what forms of organising principle the proletariat should
adopt in its revolutionary struggle.
Clearly, these two problematics may have in common the
term ‘organisation’ but little else. Whilst it would be myopic
to assert that these two aspects were completely independent
(particularly when one looks at bureaucracy both as a mode
of organisation and as a concrete structural form), they are
not the same by any means. Any theoretical perspective
which takes ‘organisation’ to mean only a principle of interre-
latedness and ignores organisations in their empirical concre-
teness cannot claim, with any justification, to be an organisa-
tion theory true to the traditional concerns for ‘real’
structures which are at the core of radical structuralism.
Looking further afield, John Eldridge’s radical Weberianism
is more evident in some of his other work. See, for example,
his ‘Industrial Relations and Industrial Capitalism’ in Esland
eta/. (1975) pp. 306-24, ‘Industrial Conflict: Some Problems
of Theory and Method’ in Child (1973) and ‘Sociological
Imagination and Industrial Life’ in Warner (1973). In all of
these, the last few pages are particularly important for their
radical Weberian flavour.
8. Baran and Sweezy elaborate on their notion of ‘scientific
understanding’ in the following terms:
Scientific understanding proceeds by way of constructing and
analysing ·models’ of the segments or aspects of reality under
392 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
study. The purpose of these models is not to give a mirror image
of reality, nor to include all its elements in their exact sizes and
proportions, but rather to single out and make available for
intensive investigation those elements which are decisive. We
abstract from non-essentials, we blot out the unimportant, we
magnify in order to improve the range and accuracy of our
observation. A model is, and must be, unrealistic in the sense in
which the word is most commonly used. Nevertheless, and in a
sense paradoxically, if it is a good model it provides the key to
understanding reality. (Baran and Sweezy, 1968, p. 27)
This approach has much in common with the perspective
advocated by Althusser. However, their approach has been
subjected to criticism. Gamble and Walton ( 1976), for exam-
ple, have suggested that in focusing primarily upon the change
in markets of monopoly capitalism, ‘Baran and Sweezy focus
attention on the level of appearances only’, and therefore,
by implication, ignore ‘the real laws of motion of capitalism’
rooted in production (1976, p. 108). Gamble and Walton also
debate Baran and Sweezy’s analysis of the rise in ‘surplus’
(1976, pp. 108-10). On a separate point, it is interesting to
note that Baran and Sweezy spend some time discussing the
role of the State, but in classic Marxist fashion they see it as
but a superstructural feature of monopoly capitalism.
9. For example, it seems that, for Braverman, Taylorism
represents the ‘bringing to life’, the concretisation of Marx’s
concept of abstract labour. Taylorism, in this way, becomes
simultaneously an inevitable part of capitalism’s develop-
ment and a stimulus to it (Braverman, 1974, pp. 181, 315).
10. For example, it is possible to consider certain types of organ-
isation as being located within the substructure as opposed to
the superstructure of society. Allen appears to wish to retain
the distinction between organisation and environment within
the context of a Marxist analysis, though at the cost of a
significant degree of theoretical clarity and consistency, as
far as Marxist analysis is concerned.
II. Marx did not address himself to the study of organisations
because, apart from the State, large-scale organisations
comprised but a small element of the social formation of his
day. Marxist analysts since then have expressed more inter-
est in modes of organisation than in organisations as middle-
range phenomena.
12. For a very useful and readable discussion of catastrophe
theory, see Zeeman (1976).
Part III
Conclusions
http://taylorandfrancis.com
12. Future Directions: Theory
and Research
In the previous chapters we have sought to provide an overview of
our four paradigms in relation to the literature on social theory and
the study of organisations. Each of the paradigms draws upon a
long, complex and conceptually rich intellectual tradition, which
generates its own particular brand of insight. Each of the para-
digms has been treated on its own terms. We have sought to
explore from within and to draw out the full implications of each
for the study of organisations. Using our analytical scheme, de-
structive critique would have been a simple task. By assuming a
posture in a rival paradigm, it would have been possible to demol-
ish the contribution of any individual text or theoretical perspec-
tive, by providing a comprehensive critique in terms ofits underly-
ing assumptions. Using the dimensions of our analytical scheme,
we could have attacked work located il\ any given paradigm from
each of the three other paradigms simply by locating ourselves in
turn within their respective problematics. We could then have
moved inside the given paradigm and provided a critique from
within, evaluating it in terms of the consistency of its assumptions
from the point of view of its own problematic. Many ofthe critical
treatises in our general area of study attempt to do precisely these
things. They evaluate in detail from within, or in terms of funda-
mentals from a given point outside which reflects their own para-
digmatic location. Whilst there may be much to recommend the
all-embracing style of critique which our analytical scheme
suggests, particularly where the intention is to investigate a single
work in depth, or in student essay writing, seminar sessions, and
academic papers, it has little to offer here. The task of academic
demolition is simply all too easy. We have consciously sought to
adopt a constructive stance, to build rather than to demolish. We
have sought to show what each of the paradigms has to offer, given
an opportunity to speak for itself.
Treatment of the paradigms in these terms emphasises both their
coherence and their distinctive natures. Viewing social theory and
396 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
the literature on organisational analysis from the perspective of the
functionalist paradigm, one has the impression that there is a
dominant orthodoxy which is surrounded by critical perspectives,
each of which seeks to adopt some form of ‘radical’ stance. Such a
view is unduly narrow; it assumes that the perspectives are
satellites which take their principal point of reference from the
orthodoxy itself. It assumes that their aim and function is critique
and the exposure of the limitations reflected in the orthodoxy.
They tend to be regarded as ·points of view’, which need to be
considered and, if possible, rebuffed or incorporated within the
context of the dominant orthodoxy. Such a view favours fusion
and incorporation as the natural line of intellectual development.
We have illustrated, in relation to the historical development ofthe
functionalist paradigm, how various elements of idealism and
Marxist theory have been incorporated in this way. Whilst
strengthening the functionalist perspective, the fusion has not by
any means done full justice to the respective problematics from
which these elements derive. Indeed, it has been at the cost of their
complete emasculation and a misunderstanding of their very
nature.
Stepping outside the functionalist paradigm, we have had an
opportunity to become more aware of the nature of the broad
intellectual traditions at work. We have seen how at the level of
social theory each of the paradigms, drawing upon a separate
intellectual source, is in essence distinct, internally coherent and
self-sustaining. At the level of organisation studies this distinc-
tiveness tends to be less clear-cut, partly because theorists operat-
ing here have adopted a reactive stance with regard to the func-
tionalist orthodoxy. Whilst deriving inspiration from alternative
problematics, they have often been drawn into critique on the
functionalists’ ground, thus giving an impression of their satellite-
like status. Our analysis of these approaches to the study of organ-
isations has indicated that, in essence, they are linked with a
completely different intellectual tradition. As we have argued,
they seek to move towards alternative theories of organisations.
Consequently, they should be seen as embryonic rather than
fully-fledged theoretical perspectives. They represent partial and
sometimes confused attempts to grasp an alternative point of view.
Their reactive stance has often prevented them from realising the
full potential which their paradigmatic location offers.
In our analysis of these theories of organisation outside the
functionalist paradigm we have consciously and systematically
attempted to relate them to their wider problematic. In so doing it
Future Directions: Theory and Research 397
has been possible to anticipate certain lines of development. The
paradigm in which they are located defines the nature of the issues
in which they are interested and the lines of enquiry which they
may fruitfully pursue. We have been able to suggest, for example,
that the radical humanist paradigm offers a nascent anti-
organisation theory and to sketch out the form it might be expected
to take. We have shown that the radical structuralist paradigm
generates at least two strains of a radical organisation theory and,
again, have attempted to identify some of the key issues relevant to
future developments in this area. Our analysis of the interpretive
paradigm has confronted the basic ontological problems which
organisations as phenomena present. We have sought to show that
from certain perspectives within this paradigm organisations are
not permitted an existence on their own account, and that no
theory of organisations as such is possible. From another stand-
point within the interpretive paradigm we have sought to show that
there is room for theorising and research in relation to the concept
of organisation and the part it plays in the accounting practices
within the context of everyday life.
Looking to the future from locations outside the functionalist
paradigm, therefore, at least three broad lines of development
offer themselves for exploration. The radical humanist, the radical
structuralist and the interpretive paradigms all offer themselves
virtually as virgin territory insofar as studies of organisations are
concerned. Whilst each already contains an element of creative
and insightful work in this area, the work is very fragmentary and
not altogether coherent. Accordingly, it does not provide the ideal
starting point nor offer an altogether firm foundation for subsequent
work. Theorists who wish to develop ideas in these areas cannot
afford to take a short cut. There is a real need for them to ground
their perspective in the philosophical traditions from which it
derives; to start from first principles; to have the philosophical and
sociological concerns by which the paradigm is defined at the
forefront of their analysis; to develop a systematic and coherent
perspective within the guidelines which each paradigm offers,
rather than taking the tenets of a competing paradigm as critical
points of reference. Each paradigm needs to be developed in its
own terms.
In essence, what we are advocating in relation to developments
within these paradigms amounts to a form of isolationism. We
firmly believe that each of the paradigms can only establish itself at
the level of organisational analysis if it is true to itself. Contrary to
the widely held belief that synthesis and mediation between para-
398 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
digms is what is required, we argue that the real need is for
paradigmatic closure. In order to avoid emasculation and incorpo-
ration within the functionalist problematic, the paradigms need to
provide a basis for their self-preservation by developing on their
own account. Insofar as they take functionalism as their reference
point, it is unlikely that they will develop far beyond their present
embryonic state – they will not develop coherent alternatives to
the functionalist point of view. This conclusion is firmly in line
with the perspective we have adopted throughout this work in sug-
gesting that the paradigms reflect four alternative realities. They
stand as four mutually exclusive ways of seeing the world. One of
the major conclusions prompted by our journey through the realms
of social theory, therefore, is that organisation theorists face a wide
range of choices with regard to the nature of the assumptions which
underwrite their point of view. For those who wish to leave the
functionalist onhodoxy behind, many avenues offer themselves
for exploration.
For those who feel inclined to remain within the functionalist
paradigm, our analysis raises a number of imponant issues. The
first of these relates to the ontological status of their subject of
investigation, and the second, to the nature of the models which
are used as bases of analysis. These two issues derive directly from
the nature of the two dimensions which we have used to define our
analytical scheme.
The ontological status of organisations is a question wonhy of
investigation. Organisation theorists frequently treat the existence
of organisations in a hard, concrete sense as taken for granted.
They assume there are real phenomena which can be measured
through the nomothetic methods which dominate empirical
research in this area. From their point of view, our journey into
phenomenology and solipsism may seen;t a journey into the absurd
and extreme. However, having made that journey, the position
adopted by highly objectivist social scientists appears equally
absurd and extreme. The notion that one can measure an organisa-
tion as an empirical facticity is as extreme as the notion that
organisations do not exist. It is awareness of these extremes that
underwrites the imponance of examining the ontological status of
our subject of study. Many intermediate perspectives offer them-
selves for consideration. As our discussion of the action frame of
reference has demonstrated, there is room for a questioning of
assumptions with regard to ontology within the bounds of the
functionalist paradigm.
The implications of this issue can perhaps be most forcefully
Future Directions: Theory and Research 399
expressed by suggesting that there is a need for organisation theor-
ists to adopt methods of study which are true to the nature of the
phenomena which they are attempting to investigate. Our review
of the dominant orthodoxy within organisation theory has shown
that a large proportion of empirical research is based upon highly
objectivist assumptions. The tendency in much empirical research
has been for methodologies to dominate other assumptions in
relation to the ontological, epistemological and human nature
strands of our analytical scheme. The wholesale incorporation of
methods and techniques taken directly from the natural sciences
needs to be severely questioned. The problem of developing
methods appropriate to the nature of the phenomena to be studied
remains one of the most pressing issues within the whole realm of
social science research.
Putting aside the problems of ontology. methodology and other
issues related to social science debate, what model of society
should organisation theorists use to underwrite their analysis? As
we have argued, this is the second crucial issue facing theorists
who wish to understand the nature of the social world. In the past
organisation theorists have almost automatically based their work
upon analogies which treat organisations either as mechanical or
as organismic systems. Since the emergence of open systems
theory as the dominant framework for organisational analysis, the
choice of an organismic analogy has been almost automatic. As we
have sought to show, the choice of this model is often implicit
rather than explicit, since organisation theorists. like many other
social scientists, have mistakenly equated open systems theory
with the use of the organismic analogy. Whilst the organismic
analogy provides an illustration of an open system, the two are by
no means synonymous. Our discussion in Chapter 4, for example,
identified three other types of open systems models – the
morphogenic, the factional and the catastrophic. These three
models reflect quite different assumptions about the nature of the
social world. The morphogenic model emphasises •structure elab-
oration’ as a basic feature of social process. The factional model
emphasises that system parts strive for autonomy rather than
functional unity, and that the system has a tendency to split up and
divide. The catastrophic model emphasises the possibility of small
incremental changes in system inputs, leading to dramatic changes
in the state of the system as a whole. In extreme cases the change
produced replaces one state of affairs with a completely new one.
The choice facing the organisation theorist and other social sci-
entists lies essentially in the question of which of these models
400 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
seem to present the most ‘accurate’ view of the social reality which
he is attempting to study. Do groups and organisations have a set of
needs and a functional unity binding constituent parts together in
the interests of survival, as the organismic analogy would have us
believe? Do groups and organisations have an inherent tendency to
split up and divide as constituent parties attempt to preserve their
autonomy, as the factional analogy would have us believe? The
former places emphasis upon system integration as a key group
and organisational attribute. The latter places emphasis upon
system division as a key characteristic; it emphasises decentralisa-
tion and dispersion as opposed to centralisation and unity. Clearly,
the simple polarisation of just these two models underlies the range
and importance of the choices open to the social scientist in his
decision concerning the analytical tools which he is to employ in
his studies. The upshot of our argument is that social scientists
need to be more conscious of the problem ofbeing ‘true’- even in
their own terms – to the very nature of the phenomena under
investigation.
The question relating to choice of analogy brings us back to the
issue of paradigms. As we have argued in earlier chapters, the
factional and catastrophic models emphasise and reflect an under-
lying view of society characteristic of the radical structuralist as
opposed to the functionalist paradigm. Whilst functionalists may
be able to incorporate and use these models within the framework
of their analysis, taken to their logical conclusion the two models
belong to a quite different reality. They stress how social forma-
tions have inbuilt tendencies towards radical change rather than
the maintenance of a regulated order. Social analyses which
attempt to be true to this perspective as a guiding principle find
themselves confronted by the analysis of totalities in these terms.
They are thus deflected from the problematic of organisations and
groups towards an understanding of the organising principles
which underlie the totality within which these organisations and
groups may be located. The analysis of particular elements of
society, in terms of their particular factional or catastrophic tenden-
cies, is replaced by a concern for the study of these tendencies
within the whole social formation, the basic characteristics of
which elements such as organisations and groups merely reflect.ln
the hands of the radical structuralist, the use of factional and
catastrophic analogies is located within quite a different analytical
enterprise.
Our attempt to explore social theory in terms offour paradigms
and their constituent schools of thought raises at least one further
Future Directions: Theory and Research 401
issue of some importance which we wish to address here. This
concerns the question of the level ofanalysis adopted for the study
of organisations. For the most part this is a concern of relevance to
the functionalist paradigm, where the work of psychologists,
organisation theorists, sociologists and industrial relations theor-
ists are all offered as different ways of studying the same organisa-
tional reality. The differences between their respective
approaches produces an impression of a wide range and diversity
of point of view. It is our contention that this diversity is more
apparent than real, since the different theorists often adopt identi-
cal postures in relation to their view of the social world. Not only
are they usually located within the same paradigm, but they
occupy similar perspectives within it. The emphasis upon the
differences between theories relating to the individual, the group,
the organisation and society has tended to mask much more impor-
tant points of commonality. Multi-disciplinary teams, therefore,
do not always give an all-round view, as is sometimes thought.
Theories which seek to incorporate different levels of analysis do
not always give the all-round view which is sometimes sought.
They may merely serve to strengthen and reinforce an approach
which is, in essence, very narrowly founded. This is an issue which
has considerable relevance for the organisation of research
activities within social science as a whole. Multi-disciplinary
research teams, panels of advisers, grant-awarding bodies and
university departments are growing in both numbers and impor-
tance, a development which is helping to broaden what are seen as
the limited perspectives which have characterised the past. The
nature of our four paradigms, however, clearly illustrates that the
problem of obtaining an all-round perspective is much more far-
reaching than this.
The path to the future is wide open. It is clear that the choices
available to organisational analysts are extremely wide. Our jour-
ney through social theory has given a glimpse of its complexity and
diversity, and has revealed the relatively narrow piece of ground
which organisation theorists, along with many other groups of
social scientists, have thus far tilled. It has become clear that the
foundations of the subject are extremely narrow, and that for the
most part organisation theorists are not always entirely aware of
the traditions to which they belong. The subject is frequently
viewed as having a short history. This appears to be a mistaken
view. The ideas which it has utilised can be traced back to the
broader intellectual traditions which have underwritten social sci-
ence in the widest of terms. It is time that organisation theory
402 Stldologit:lll Pt~..l’tfdigms •nd CHg•nisa.tiomll Analy•is
became fully aware of its pedigree. It is time for it to lhi;nk more
consciously about the social phil·osophy upon which it is based. In
short, it is time that it became more fuUy aware ofits relation.ship to
the ‘big issues’. Onl.y by grounding itself firmly in. a knowlalae of
its p.ast and of the alternative avenues for development can it
realise its fuD pot.ential in the years ahead.
Bibliography
ALLEN, V.L. (1975), Social Analysis: A Marxist Critique and
Alternative. Londo_n and New York: Longman.
ALTHUSSER, L. (1969), For Marx. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
ALTHUSSER, L. (1971), Lenin and Philosophy and Other
Essays. London: New Left Books.
ALTHUSSER, L. and BALIBAR, E. (1970), Reading Capital.
London: New Left Books.
ANDERSON, P. (1976), Considerations on Western Marxism.
London: New Left Books.
ANGELL, J.R. (1902), The Relations of Structural and Func-
tional Psychology to Philosophy. Chicago: The Decennial Publica-
tions Ill, University of Chicago.
ANGYAL, A. (1941), Foundations/or a Science of Personality.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
ANTHONY, P.D. (1977), The Ideology of Work. London: Tavis-
tock.
ARGYRIS, C. (1952), The Impact of Budgets upon People. New
York: Controllership Foundation.
ARGYRIS, C. (1951),Personality and Organisation. New York:
Harper and Row.
ARGYRIS, C. (l964),Integrating the Individual and the Organ-
isation. New York: Wiley.
ARON, R. (1965), Main Currents in Sociological Thought – I.
London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.
ARON, R. (1968), Main Currents in Sociological Thought – 2.
London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
AVINERI, S. (1968), The Social and Political Thought of Karl
Marx. London: Cambridge University Press.
AVRICH, P. (1967), The Russian Anarchists. Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press.
BARAN, P. and SWEEZY, P. (1968), Monopoly Capital. Har-
mondsworth: Penguin.
BARNARD, C. (1938), The Functions of the Executive. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
BATESON, G. ( 1973), Steps To An Ecology of Mind. St. Albans:
Paladin.
BAUMAN, Z. (1977), Towards a Critical Sociology. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
404 BibUography
BEAUVOIR. SIMONE DE, (1963), The Prime of Life. London:
Deutsch.
BELL, D. (1962), The End of Ideology. New York, London:
Collier MacMillan.
BELL, G.D., ed. (1967), Organisations and Human Behaviour.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
BENNIS, W. (1966), Changing Organisations. New York:
McGraw Hill.
BENTON, T. (1977), Philosophical Foundations of the Three
Sociologies. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
BERGER, P.L., ed. (1974), The Human Shape of Work. London
and New York: Macmillan.
BERGER, P.L., BERGER, B. and KELLNER, H. (1974), The
Homeless Mind. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
BERGER, P.L. and LUCKMANN, T. (1966), The Social Con-
struction of Reality. New York: Doubleday.
BERGER, P.L. and PULLBERG, S. (1966), ‘Reification and the
Sociological Critique of Consciousness’ ,New Left Review, 35, pp.
56-71.
BERKELEY. G. (1962), The Principles of Human Knowledge and
Three Dialogues Between Hvlas and Philonous. London: Collins.
BEYNON, H. (1973), Working for Ford. Harmondsworth: Pen-
guin/ Allen Lane.
BIITNER, E. (1965), ‘The Concept of Organisation’, in R.
Turner, Ethnomethodology. op. cit.
BIITNER, E. (1967), ‘The Police on Skid Row- a Study of Peace
Keeping’, American Sociological Review, 32 (5), pp. 699-715.
BLACK, M., ed. (1961), The Social Theories of Talcott Parsons.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
BLACKBURN, R., ed. (1972), Ideology in Social Science. Lon-
don: Fontana/Collins.
BLAKE, R.R. and MOUTON, J.S. ( 1964), The Managerial Grid.
Houston, Texas: Gulf Publishing Company.
BLAU, P.M. (1955), The Dynamics of Bureaucracy. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
BLAU, P.M. (1964), Exchange and Power in Social Life. New
York: John Wiley.
BLAU, P.M. (1974), On the Nature of Organisations. New York:
John Wiley.
BLAU, P.M. and SCHOENHERR, R.A. (1971), The Structure of
Organisations. New York: Basic Books.
BLUM, M.L. and NAYLOR, J.C. ( 1968), Industrial Psychology.
New York: Harper and Row.
Bibliography 405
BLUMER, H. (1962), ·society as Symbolic Interaction’, in A.
Rose, Human Behaviour and Social Processes, op. cit.
BLUMER, H. ( 1966), ·sociological Implications of the Thought of
George Herben Mead’ ,American Journal of Sociology, 71 (5), pp.
535-48.
BLUMER, H. (1969), Symbolic lnteractionism: Perspective and
Method. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
BOGGS, C. (1976), Gramsci’s Marxism. London: Pluto.
BOOKCHIN, M. (1974), •Listen Marxist’, in Post-Scarcity
Anarchism. London: Wildwood House, pp. 171-220.
BOOKCHIN, M. (1974), Post-Scarcity Anarchism. London:
Wildwood House.
BOSE, A. (1967), A History of Anarchism. Calcutta: The World
Press Private.
BOSWELL, J. ( 1953),Lifeof Johnson. London: Oxford University
Press.
BOTIOMORE, T. (1975), Marxist Sociology. London: Macmil-
lan.
BOTIOMORE, T. and RUBEL, M. (1963), Karl Marx: Selected
Writings in Sociology and Social Philosophy. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
BOWEY, A. (1976), The Sociology of Organisations. London:
Hodder and Stoughton.
BRAMSON, L. (1961), The Political Content of Sociology.
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
BRAV~RMAN, H. (1974), Labor and Monopoly Capital. New
York and London: Monthly Review Press.
BROWN, B. (1973), Marx, Freud and the Critique of Everyday
Life. New York: Monthly Review Press.
BUCKLEY, W. (1967), Sociology and Modern Systems Theory.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
BUKHARIN, N. (1965), Historical Materialism: A System of
Sociology. New York: Russell and Russell. (First published 1925.)
BURNS, T. and BURNS, E., eds. (1976), The Sociology of Drama
and Literature. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
BURNS, T. and STALKER, G.M. (1961), The Management of
Innovation. London: Tavistock Publications.
CALLINICOS, A. (1976), Althusser’s Marxism. London: Pluto
Press.
CAREY. A. ( 1967), ·The Hawthorne Studies: A Radical Critic-
ism”, American Sociological Review, 32 (3), pp. 403-16.
CARTWRIGHT, D. and ZANDER, A. (1968), Group Dynamics:
Research and Theory (3rd edn). New York: Harper and Row.
406 Bibliography
CASTANEDA, C. ( 1970), The Teachings of Don Juan: A Yacqui
Way of Knowledge. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
CHADWICK-JONES, J.K. (1976), Social Exchange Theory.
London: Academic Press.
CHILD, J. (1972), ‘Organisational Structure, Environment and
Performance: The Role of Strategic Choice’, Sociology, 6 (I), pp.
1-22.
CHILD, J., ed. (1973), Man and Organisation. London: George
Allen and Unwin.
CHOMSKY, N. (1959), ‘Review of Skinner’s “Verbal
Behaviour'”, Language, 35, (1), pp. 26-58.
CICOUREL, A.V. (1964), Method and Measurement in
Sociology. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
CICOUREL, A.V. (1972), Cognitive Sociology: Language and
Meaning in Social Interaction. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
CLEGG, S. (1975), Power, Rule and Domination. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
CLEGG, S. and DUNKERLEY, D. (1977), Critical Issues in
Organisations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.·
CLINARD, M.B. (1964), Anomie and Deviant Behaviour.
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
COHEN, P.S. (1968), Modern Social Theory. London:
Heinemann.
COHEN, S.F. (1974), Bulcharin ·and the Bolshevik Revolution.
London: Wildwood House.
COLFAX, J.D. and ROACH, J.L., eds. (1971), Radical
Sociology. New York: Basic Books.
COLLETII, L. (1972), From Rousseau to Lenin. London: New
Left Books.
COLLETTI, L. (1974), “A Political and Philosophical Interview’,
New Left Review, 86, pp. 3-28.
COLLETTI, L. (1975), ‘Marxism and the Dialectic’, New Left
Review, 93, pp. 3-29.
COMTE, AUGUSTE (1853), The Positivist Philosophy, Vol. I
(freely trans. by H. Martineau). London: Chapman.
CONNERTON, P., ed. (1976), Critical Sociology. Harmonds-
worth: Penguin.
CONQUEST, R. (1972), Lenin. London: Fontana/Collins.
COOPER, R. (1976), ‘The Open Field’ ,Human Relations, 29(11),
pp. 999-1017.
COOPER, W.W., LEAVITT, H.J. and SHELLEY, M.W., eds.
(1964), New Perspectives in Organisation Research. New York:
Jobn Wiley.
Bibliography 401
COOPER, W.W., LEAVITT, H.J.andSHELLEY, M.W. (1964),
‘Administrative Rationality, Social Setting, and Organisational
Development’, in Cooper et al, New Perspectives in Organisation
Research, op. cit.
CORNFORTH, M. (1955), Science Versus Idealism. London:
Lawrence and Wishart.
COSER, L.A. (1956), The Functions of Social Conflict. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
COSER, L.A. (1965), Georg Simmel. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall.
COSER, L.A. (1967), Continuities in the Study of Social Conflict.
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
COSER, L.A. and ROSENBERG, B., eds (1969), Sociological
Theory (3rd edri). New York and London: Macmillan.
CROZIER, M. (1964), The Bureaucratic Phenomenon. London:
Tavistock Publications.
CUTLER, J., HINDESS, B., HIRST, P. and HUSSAIN, A.
(1977), Marx’s Capital and Capitalism Today, Vol.. I. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
CYERT, R.M. and MARCH, J.G. (1963), A Behavioural Theory
of the Firm. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
DAHL, R. (1957), •The Concept of Power’ ,Behavioural Science,
2, pp. 201-15.
DAHRENDORF, R. (1959),CiassandCiass Conflict in Industrial
Society. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
DALTON,M.(1959),Men Who Manage. New York: John Wiley.
DAVIS, F. (1967), •The Cab-Driver and His Fare: Relationship’,
in G.D. Bell, Organisations and Human Behaviour, op. cit.
DAVIS, K. (1959), ·The Myth of Functional Analysis as a Special
Method in Sociology and Anthropology•, American Sociological
Review, 24 (6), pp. 757-73.
DAVIS, L.E. and CHERNS, A.B., eds. (1975), The Quality of
Working Life, Vols I and II. New York: Free Press.
DAVIS, L.E. and Taylor, J.C., eds (1972), Design of Jobs. Har-
mondsworth: Penguin.
DA WE, A. (1970), •The Two Sociologies•, British Journal of
Sociology, 21, pp. 207-:-18.
DECHERT, C.R. (1965), •The Development of Cybernetics’, The
American Behavioural Scientist, 8, pp. 15-20.
DEMERATH, N.J. (1966), ·synecdoche and Structural Function-
alism’, Social Forces, 44 (3), pp. 390-401.
DENZIN, N.K. (1970), •symbolic lnteractionism and Eth-
nomethodology•, in J.D. Douglas, Understanding Everydtly Life,
op. cit.
408 Bibliography
DICKSON. D. (1974), Alterlllltive Technology and the Politics of
Technical Change. London: Fontana.
DILL, W.R. (1958), •Environment as an Influence on Managerial
Autonomy’, in Administrative Science Quarterly, 2, pp. 409-43.
DILTHEY, W. (1976), Selected Writings (ed. H.P. Rickman).
London: Cambridge University Press.
DOUGLAS, J.D. (1967), The Social Meanings of Suicide. Prince-
ton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
DOUGLAS, J.D., ed. (1970a), Freedom and Tyranny in a Tech-
nological Society. New York: Alfred Knopf.
DOUGLAS, J.D., ed. (1970b), Understanding Everyday Ufe.
Chicago: Aldine Publishing; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
DREITZEL, H.P., ed. (1970), Recent Sociology, No. 2. New
York: Macmillan.
DUBIN, R. (1956), ·Industrial Workers’ Worlds: A Study of Cen-
tral Life Interests of Industrial Workers’ ,Social Problems, 3, pp.
131-42.
DUNLOP, J.T. (1958), Industrial Relations Systems. New York:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
DUNNETTE, M.D. ( 1976), Handbook of industrial and Organ:.
izational Psychology. Chicago: Rand McNally.
DURKHEIM, E. ( 1938), The Rules of Sociological Method. Glen-
coe, Ill.: Free Press.
DURKHEIM, E. (1947), The Division of Labour in Society (trans.
G. Simpson). Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
DURKJIEIM, E. (1951), Suicide (trans. J.A. Spalding and G.
Simpson). Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
EASTON, D. (1953), The Political System. New York: Alfred
Knopf.
ELDRIDGE, J.E.T. (1971), Sociology and Industrial Ufe.
London: Nelson.
ELDRIOOE,J.E.T. and CROMBIE, A.D. (1974),A Sociology of
Organisations. London: George Allen and Unwin.
ELLUL, J. (1964), The Technological Society. New York:
Vintage Books.
EMERSON, J. (1970), •Behaviour in Private Places’, in H.P.
Dreitzel, Recent Sociology, No. 2, op. cit.
EMERSON, R.M. (1962), •power-Dependence Relations’,
American Sociological Review, 27 (1). pp. 31-40.
EMERY, F.E. and TRIST, E.L. (196S), ·n.e Causal Texture m
Organisational Environments’, Human Relations, 18 {1), pp.
21-32.
Bibliography 409
EMERY, F.E. and TRIST, E.L. (1972), Towards a Social
Ecology, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
ESLAND, G., SALAMAN, G. and SPEAKMAN, M.A., eds.
(1975), People and Work. Edinburgh: Holmes MCDougall (in
association with the Open University Press).
ETZIONI, A. (1961), A Comparative Analysis of Complex Organ-
isations. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
EVANS-PITCHARD, E.E. (1954), Social Anthropology.
London: Oxford University Press.
FARIS, R.E.L., ed. (1964), Handbook of Modern Sociology.
Chicago: Rand McNally.
FARIS, R.E.L. (1967), Chicago Sociology. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
FAYOL, H. (1949), General and Industrial Management (trans.
C. Storr). London: Pitman.
FEYERABEND, P. ( 1972), Against Method. London: New Left
Books.
FICHTE, J .F. ( 1910),Science of Knowledge (with first and second
introductions; eds. P. Heath and J. Lachs). New York: Century
Philosophy Sourcebooks.
FIEDLER, F.E. (1967), A Theory of Leadership Effectiveness.
London and New York: McGraw Hill.
FILMER, P., PHILLIPSON, M., SILVERMAN, D. and
WALSH, D. (1972), New Directions in Sociological Theory.
London and New York: Collier Macmillan.
FINCH. H.A. (1949), Max Weber on the Methodology of Social
Sciences. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
FOX, A. ( 1966), ‘Industrial Sociology and Industrial Relations’,
Research Paper 3, Royal Commission on Trade Unions and
Employers’ Associations, London: HMSO.
FOX, A. (1973), ‘Industrial Relations: A Social Critique of Plural-
ist Ideology’, in J. Child, Man and Organisation, op. cit.
FOX, A. ( 1974a), Beyond Contract: Work, Power and Trust Rela-
tions. London: Faber and Faber.
FOX, A. (1974b), Man Mismanagement. London: Hutchinson.
FRASER. R., ed. (1968), Work, Vols I and II. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
FRENCH, J.R.P. and RAVEN, B. (1968), ‘The Bases of Social
Power’, in D. Cartwright and A. Zander, Group Dynamics, op. cit.
FRIEDRICHS, R.W. (1970), A Sociology of Sociology. New
York: Free Press.
FRISBY, D. (1972), ‘The Popper-Adorno Controversy: The
Methodological Dispute in German Sociology’ ,Philosophy of The
Social Sciences. 2, pp. 105-19.
410 Bibliography
FRISBY, D. (1974), ‘The Frankfurt School: Critical Theory and
Positivism’, in J. Rex, ed., Approaches to Sociology, op. cit.
GADAMER, H.G. (1965), Wahrheit und Method, Tubingen:
J.C.B. Mohr, (English copyright: Sheed and Ward, London,
1975).
GAMBLE, A. and WALTON, P. (1976), Capitalism in Crisis.
London: Macmillan.
GARFINKEL, H. (1967), Studies in Ethnomethodology.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
GARFINKEL, H. (1968), ‘The Origins of the Term Eth-
nomethodology’, Proceedings of the Purdue Symposium on Eth-
nomethodology, Institute monograph No. 1, Institute for the
Study of Social Change, Purdue University; reproduced in R.
Turner, ed., Etlrnomethodology, op. cit.
GAUS, J.M. (1936), The Frontiers of Public Administration.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
GAUS, J.M. (1936), ‘A Theory of Organisation in Public
Administration’, The Frontiers of Public Administration, op. cit.
GERTH, H.H. and MILLS, C. WRIGHT, eds. (1948),From Max
Weber. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
GIDDENS, A. (1971), Capitalism and Modern Social Theory.
London: Cambridge University Press.
GIDDENS, A. (1972a), ‘Elites in The British Oass Structure’,
Sociological Review, 20 (3), pp. 345-72.
GIDDENS, A. (1972b), Politics and Sociology in the Thought of
Max W~ber. London: Macmillan.
GIDDENS, A. (1974), Positivism and Sociology. London:
Heinemann.
GIDDENS, A. (1976), New Rules of Sociological Method. Lon-
don: Hutchinson.
GLUCKSMANN, M. (1974), Structuralist Analysis in Contem-
porary Social Thought. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
GODELIER, M. (1972), ‘Structure and Contradiction in Capital,’
in R. Blackburn, ed.,ldeology in Social Science, op. cit.
GOFF MAN, E. ( 1959), The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life.
New York: Doubleday.
GOFFMAN, E. (1961), Asylums. New York; Doubleday.
GOFFMAN, E. (l963),Behaviourin Public Places. Glencoe, Ill.:
Free Press.
GOFFMAN, E. (1967), Interaction Ritual. New York: Double-
day.
GOLD, R.L. (1964), ‘In the Basement- The Apartment Building
Janitor’, in P.L. Berger, ed., The Human Shape of Work, op. cit.
Bibliography 411
GOLDMANN, L. (1969), The Human Sciences and Philosophy.
London: Cape.
GOLDTHORPE, J.H., LOCKWOOD, D., BECHHOFER, F.
and PLATT, J. (1968), The Affluent Worker: Industrial Attitudes
and Behaviour. London: Cambridge University Press.
GOLDTHORPE, J.H. (1974), •Industrial Relations in Great
Britain: A Critique of Reformism’, Politics and Society, 4 (3), pp.
419-52.
GOLDTHORPE, J.H. (1974), ·social Inequality and Social Inte-
gration in Modern Britain’, in D. Wedderburn. ed., Poverty,
Inequality and Class Structure, op. cit.
GOULDNER, A. W. ( 1954a), Patterns of Industrial Bureaucracy.
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
GOULDNER, A. W. (1954b), Wildcat Strike. New York: Antioch
Press.
GOULDNER, A. W. ( 1959), •Reciprocity and Autonomy in Func-
tional Theory’, in A.W. Gouldner, For Sociology, op. cit.
GOULDNER, A. W. (1969), •The Unemployed Self’, in R. Fraser,
ed., Work, op. cit.
GOULDNER, A.W. (1970), The Coming Crisis of Western
Sociology. London: Heinemann.
GOULDNER, A. W. (1973), For Sociology. Harmondsworth:
Allen Lane.
GOULDNER, A.W. (1973), •Anti-Minotaur: The Myth of a Value
Free Sociology’, in A.W. Gouldner, For Sociology, op. cit.
GOULPNER, A. W. (1976), The Dialectic of Ideology and Tech-
nology. London and New York: Macmillan.
GRAMSCI, A. (1971), Selections From the Prison Notebooks of
Antonio Gramsci (eds. Quinton Hoare and Geoffrey Noweii-
Smith). London: Lawrence and Wishart.
GROSS, N.M., WARD, S. and McEACHERN, W.A. (1958),
Explorations in Role Analysi$: Studies of the School Super-
intendent Role. New York: John Wiley.
HABERMAS, J. (1970a), ·on Systematically Distorted Com-
munications’, Inquiry, 13, pp. 205-18.
HABERMAS, J. (1970b), •Towards a Theory of Communicative
Competence’ ,Inquiry, 13, pp. 360-75.
HABERMAS, J. (1971a), Towards a Rational Society. London:
Heinemann.
HABERMAS, J. (1971b), •Technology and Science as Ideology’,
in J. Habermas, Towards a Rational Society, op. cit.
HABERMAS, J. ( 1972), Knowledge and Human Interests.
London: Heinemann.
412 BibHography
HABERMAS. J. (1974), Theory and Practice. London:
Heinemann.
HABERMAS, J. (1976), Legitimation Crisis. London:
Heinemann.
HAGE, J. and AIKEN, M. (1967), ‘Relationship of Centralisation
to Other Structural Properties’, Administrative Science Quarterly,
12, pp. 72-92.
HALL. R.H., (1972), Organisations: Structure and Process.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
HARVEY, D. (1973), Social Justice and the City. London:
Edward Arnold.
HEGEL, G. (1931), The Phenomenology of Mind. London:
George Allen and Unwin.
HERZBERG, F., MAUSNER, B. and SNYDERMAN, B. (1959),
The Motivation to Work. New York: John Wiley.
HICKSON, D.J., PUGH, D.S. and PHEYSEY, D.C. (1969),
‘Operations Technology and Organisation Structure: An Empiri-
cal Reappraisal’, Administrative Science Quarterly, 14, pp.
378-97.
HICKSON, D.J .• HININGS, C.R., LEE, C.A., SCHNECK.
R.E. and PENNINGS, J.M. (1971). ‘A Strategic Contingencies
Theory of Intra-Organisational Power’, Administrative Science
Quarterly, 16, pp. 216-29.
HINDESS, B. (1975), The Use of Official Statistics in Sociology:
A Critique of Positivism and Ethnomethodology. London:
Macmillan.
HODGES, H.A. (1952), The Philosophy of Wilhelm Dilthey.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
HOMANS, G.C. (1950), The Human Group. New York:
Harcourt. Brace and World.
HOMANS, G.C. ( 1958), ‘Human Behaviour as Exchange’.
American Journal of Sociology, 63 (6), pp. 597-606.
HOMANS, G.C. (1961), Social Behaviour: Its Elementary Forms.
New York: Harcourt Brace and World.
HOMANS, G.C. ( 1964a), ‘Contemporary Theory in Sociology’, in
R.E.L. Faris, ed., Handbook of Modern Sociology, op. cit.
HOMANS, G.C. (1964b), ‘Bringing Men Back In’. American
Sociological Review, 29 (5), pp. 309-18.
HOMANS, G.C. and CURTIS, C.P. (1934), An Introduction to
Pareto, His Sociology. New York: Alfred Knopf.
HOPPOCK, R. (1935), Job Satisfaction. New York: Harper.
HORKHEIMER, M. (1972), Critical Theory: Selected Essays.
New York: Herder.
Bibliography 413
HOROWITZ, D., ed. (1971), Radical Sociology: An Introduction.
New York: Harper and Row.
HORTON, J. (1964), ‘The Dehumanisationof Anomie and Aliena-
tion’, British Journal of Sociology, 1.5 (4), pp. 283-300.
HUGHES, E. (19.58), Men and Their Work. Glencoe, Ill.: Free
Press.
HUGHES, H. STUART (19.58), Consciousness and Society. New
York: Alfred Knopf.
HUSSERL, E. (1929), Entry on ‘Phenomenology’, in Ency-
cloptzdia Brittannica, 14th edn.
HYMAN, H.H. and SINGER, E. (1968), Readings in Reference
Group Theory and Research. New York: Free Press.
HYMAN, R. ( 197.5),Industrial Relations: A Marxist Introduction.
London: Macmillan.
HYMAN, R. and BROUGH, I. (197.5), Social Values and
Industrial Relations. Oxford: Blackwell.
HYMAN, R. and FRYER, R. (197.5), ‘Trade Unions: Sociology
and Political Economy’, in J. McKinlay, ed., Processing People:
Cases in Organisational Behaviour, op. cit.
ILLICH, I. (1973), Tools/or Conviviality. London: Fontana/Col-
lins.
JAQUES, E. (1951), The Changing Culture of a Factory.
London:Tavistock.
JAQUES, E. (1962), Measurement of Responsibility. London:
Tavistock Publications.
JAMES, W. (1890), Principles of Psychology, London:
Macmillan.
JARVIE, I.E. (1964), The Revolution in Anthropology. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
JAY, M. (1973), The Dialectical Imagination. London:
Heinemann.
KAHN, R.L. and BOULDING, E., eds. (1964),PowerandCon-
jlir.t in Organisations. London: Tavistock Publications.
KAST, F.E. and ROSENWEIG, J.E. (1973), Contingency Views
of Organisation and Management. Chicago: Science Research
Associates.
KATZ, D. and KAHN, R.L. (1966), The Social Psychology of
Organisations. New York: John Wiley.
KAUFMANN, W. (1966), Hegel. London: Weidenfeld and
Nicolson.
KEAT, R. and URRY, J. (197.5), Social Theory as Science.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
414 Bibliography
KELLEY, H.H. (1968), ‘Two Functions of Reference Groups’, in
H.H. Hyman and E. Singer,ReadingsinRe[erenceGroup Theory,
op. cit.
KERR, C., DUNLOP, J.T., HARBISON, F.H. and MYERS,
C.A. (1964),/ndustrialismand Industrial Man (2nd edn). London:
Oxford University Press.
KOLAKOWSKI, L. (1972), Positivist Philosophy. Harmonds-
worth: Penguin.
KUHN, T.S. (1970), The Structure of Scientflic Revolution (2nd
edn). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
LAING, R.D. (1967), The Politics of Experience. New York:
Ballantine.
LANDSBERGER, H.A. (1958), Hawthorne Revisited. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
LANDY, F .J. and TRUMBO, D.A. (1976), Pyschology of Worlc
Behaviour. New York: Dorsey Press.
LAWRENCE, P.R. and LORSCH, J. W. (1961),0rganization and
Environment. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Graduate School~
Business Administration. ·
LEE, E. and MANDELBAUM, M., eds. (l911),Phenomenology
and Existentialism. New York: John Hopkins.
LEVI, A. W. (1967), ‘Existentialism and the Alienation of Man’, in
E. Lee and M. Mandelbaum, eds., Phenomenology and Existen-
tialism, op. cit.
LEWIN, K., LIPPITI, R. and WHITE, R.K. (1939), ‘Patterns~
Aggressive Behaviour in Experimentally Created Social Oi-
mates’, Journal of Social Psychology, 10, pp. 271-99.
LICHTHEIM. G. (1967), Marxism: An Historical and Critical
Study. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
LICHTHEIM, G. (1970). Luktlcs. London: Fontana/Collins.
LIKERT, R. (1961), New Patterns of Management. New York:
McGraw Hill.
LIKERT, R. (1967), The Human Organisation. New York:
McGraw Hill.
LOCKE, E.A. (1975), ‘Personnel Attitudes and Motivation’,
Annual Review of Psychology. pp. 457-79.
LOCKWOOD, D. (1956), ·some Remarks on .. The Social
System'”, British Journal of Sociology, 1, pp. 134-43.
LOCKWOOD, D. (1964), ‘Social Integration and System Integra-
tion·, in O.K. Zollschan and W. Hirsch, eds., Explorations in
Social Change, op cit.
LORSCH, J.W. and LA WRENCE.P.R.(1970).Studiesin Organ-
isation Design. Homewood, Ill.: Irwin.
Bibliography 4lS
LORSCH, J.W. and MORSE, J.J. (l914),0rganisations and Their
Members: A Contingency Approach. New York: Harper and Row.
LUKACS, G. ( 197 1), History and Class Consciousness. London:
Merlin. (First published 1923).
LUKES, S. (1973), Emile Durkheim: His Life and Work.
Harmondsworth: Allen Lane.
LUKES, S. (1914),Power: A Radical View. London: Macmillan.
LUPTON, T.(l963),0ntheShopFioor. Oxford: Pergamon Press.
LUPTON, T. (1971), Management and the Social Sciences (2nd
edn). Harmondsworth: Penguin.
McCULLOUGH, A. and SHANNON, M. (1977), •organisation
and Protection’, in S. Clegg and D. Dunkerley, eds., Critical
Issues in Organisations, op. cit.
McGREGOR, D. (1960), The Human Side of Enterprise. New
York: McGraw Hill.
McHUGH, P. (1968), Defining the Situation. Indianapolis:
Dobbs-Merrill.
MaciNTYRE, A. (1970), Marcuse. London: Fontana/Collins.
McKINLAY, J.B., ed., (1975), Processing People: Cases in
Organisational Behaviour. London an4New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston.
McLELLAN, D., ed. (1973), Marx’s Grundrisse. St. Albans:
Paladin.
McLELLAN, D. (1975), Marx. London: Fontana/Collins.
McLELLAN, D. (1976), Karl Marx: His Life and Thought. St.
Albans: Paladin.
McNALL, S.G. and JOHNSON, J.C.M. (1975), •The New Con-
servatives: Ethnomethodologists, Phenomenologists, and
Symbolic Interactionists’, The Insurgent Sociologist, 5 (4), pp.
49-65.
MAKKREEL, R.A. (1975), Dilthey- Philosopher of the Human
Studies. Princeton. N.J.: Princeton University Press.
MANN, M. (1971), Class Consciousness and Action Among the
Western Working Class. London: Macmillan.
MANIS, J.G. and MELTZER, B.N. (1961),Symbolic Interaction.
Boston: Allyn and Bacon.
MARCH, J.G. (1965), Handbook of Organizations. Chicago:
Rand McNally.
MARCH, J.G. and SIMON, H.A. (1958), Organisations. New
York: John Wiley.
MARCUSE, H. (1954), Reason and Revolution (rev. edn 1964).
New York: Humanities Press.
416 Bibliography
MARCUSE, H. (1964), One-Dimensional Man. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
MARCUSE, H. (1966), Eros and Civilisation. Boston: Beacon.
MARCUSE, H. (1968), Negations: Essays in Critical Theory.
London: Heinemann.
MARCUSE, H. (1968), ‘Industrialisation and Capitalism in the
Work of Max Weber’. Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, op.
cit.
MARX, K. and ENGELS, F. (1968), Selected Works, London:
Lawrence and Wishart Ltd.
MARX, K. and ENGELS, F. (1965), The German Ideology. Lon-
don: Lawrence and Wishart. (First published 1846.)
MARX, K. (1973), Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of
Political Economy (trans. M. Nicolaus). Harmondsworth: Pen-
guin. (First published Moscow, 1939-41.)
MARX, K. (1975), Early Writings (trans. R. Livingstone and G.
Benton). Harmondsworth: Penguin. (This contains Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts, 1844.)
MARX, K. ( 1976), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vols
1-111. (trans. B. Fowkes). Harmondsworth: Penguin. (Vol. I first
published 1867. Vol. II. 1885, Vol. Ill. 18~.)
MARTINS. H. (1974), ‘Time and Theory in Sociology’. in J. Rex,
ed., Approaches to Sociology, op. cit.
MASLOW, A. (1943). “A Theory of Human Motivation’.
Psychological Reivew, 50, pp. 370-96.
MASSIE. J.L. (1965), “Management Theory’, in J.G. March, ed.,
Handbook of Organizations, op. cit.
MAUSS, M. (1954), The Gift. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
MAYO. E. ( 1933), The Human Problems of an Industrial Civilisa-
tion. New York: Macmillan.
MAYO, E. (1949), The Social Problems of an Industrial Civilisa-
tion. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
MAYS, W. ( 1975), ‘Phenomenology and Marxism’, in E. Pivc!eci~.
ed .• Phenomenological and Philosophical Understanding, op. cit.
MEAD, G.H. ( I932a), Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth
Century (ed. M.N. Moore). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
MEAD, G.H. (1932b), The Philosophy of the Present (ed. A. E.
Murphy). Chicago: Open Court Publishing.
MEAD, G.H. (1934),Mind, Self and Society (ed. Charles Morris).
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
MEAD, G.H. (1938), The Philosophy of the Act (ed. Charles
Morris). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
BibUography 411
MEAD, G.H. (1956), The Social Psychology of George Herbert
Mead (ed. Anselm M. Strauss). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press (Phoenix Books).
MEAKIN, D. (1976), Man and Work: Uterature and Culture in
Industrial Society. London: Methuen.
MELTZER, B. and PETRAS, J. ( 1973), ‘Theoretical and Ideolog-
ical Variations in Contemporary lnteractionism’. Catalyst. 1, pp.
1-8.
MELTZER, B.M., PETRAS, J. and REYNOLDS, L. (197S),
Symbolic lnteractionism: Genesis, Varieties and Criticism.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
MENNELL, S. (1974), Sociological Theory: Uses and Unities.
London: Nelson.
MERTON, R.K. (1948), ‘Manifest and Latent Functions’, in R.K.
Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, op. cit.
MERTON, R.K. (l968),Social Theory and Social Structure. New
York: Free Press (enlarged edn).
MESZAROS, I. (1970a), ‘Lukacs’ Concept of Dialectic’, in
G.H.R. Parkinson, ed., George Lulctics: The Man, His Work and
His Ideas. op. cit.
MESZAROS, I. (1970b), Marx’s Theory of Alienation, London:
Merlin.
MESZAROS, I. ( 1971), Aspects of History and Class Conscious-
ness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
MICHELS, R. (1949),Political Parties. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
MILIBAND, R. (1973), The State in CapitaUst Society. London:
Quartet.
MILLER, D.L. ( 1973), George Herbert Mead: Self, Language
and the World. Houston, Texas: University of Texas Press.
MILLER, E.J. and RICE, A.K. (1967), Systems of Organisation.
London: Tavistock Publications.
MILLS, C. WRIGHT (1959), The Sociological Imagination.
London: Oxford University Press.
MINER, J.B. and DACHLER, H.P. (1973), ‘Personnel Attitudes
and Motivation’ ,Annual Review of Psychology, 24, pp. 379-402.
MOUZELIS, N. ( 191S),Organisation and Bureaucracy (2nd edn).
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
MURDOCH, I. (1967), Sartre. London: Fontana.
MYERS, C.S. (1924), Industrial Psychology in Great Britain.
London: Cape.
NAT ANSON. M. ( 1966), Essays in Phenome’fology. The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff’.
418 Bib6ography
NATANSON, M. (1973a), A Critique of Jean-Paul Sartre”s
Ontology. The Hague: Martinus NijhotT. (First published 19Sl.)
NAT ANSON, M. ( 1973b), Edmund Husser/: Philosopher of Infi-
nite Tasks. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
NAT ANSON, M. (1973c), The Social Dynamics of George H.
Mead. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. (First published 19S6.)
NELL, E. (1972), ‘Economics: The Revival of Political
Economy’, in R. Blackburn, ed.,ldeology in Social Science. op.
cit.
NEWCOMB, T.M.(19SO),Socia/Psychology. New York: Dryden
Press.
NEWCOMB, T.M. (19S3), “An Approach to the Study of Com-
municative Acts’, Psychological Review, 60, pp. 393-404.
NISBET, R.A. (1967), The Sociological Tradition. London:
Heinemann.
NISBET, R.A. (1969), Social Change and History. London:
Oxford University Press.
NISBET, R. ( 1976), The Social Philosophers, St. Albans: Paladin.
OLLMAN, B. (1971), Alienation: Marx’s Critique of Man in
Capitalist Society. London: Cambridge University Press.
OLSEN, M., ed. (1970), Power in Society. London: Macmillan.
O’NEILL, J., ed. (1977), On Critical Theory. London:
Heinemann.
OSBORN, R.N. (1974), ‘Environment and Organisational Effec-
tiveness’, Administative Science Quarterly, 19, pp. 231-46.
PAHL. R.E. and WINKLER, J. (1974), ‘The Coming Corporat-
ism’, New Society, 30 (627), pp. 72-6.
PALMER, R.E. (1969), Hermeneutics. Evanston: Northwestern
University Press.
PARETO, V. (1934), An Introduction to Pareto, His Sociology
(eds. G.C. Homans and C.P. Curtis). New York: Alfred Knopf.
PARETO, V. (193S), The Mind and Society, (trans. Andrew
Bongiorno and Arthur Livingstone), 4 vols. New York: Harcourt,
Brace, Jovanovich.
PARK, R.E., and BURGESS, E.W. (1921),/ntroduction to the
Science of Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
PARKIN, F. (1973), Class, Inequality and Political Order. St.
Albans: Paladin.
PARKINSON, G.H.R., ed. (1970), Georg Lukacs: The Man, His
Work, His Ideas. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
PARSONS, T. (1949), The Structure of Social Action. Glencoe,
Ill.: Free Press.
Bib6ography 419
PARSONS, T. and SHILS, E.A., eds. (19SI), Towards a General
Theory of Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
PARSONS, T. (19SI), The Social System. London: Tavistock;
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
PARSONS, T. ( 19S9), Economy and Society. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
PARSONS, T. (1963), ‘On the Concept of Political Power’, Pro-
ceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 107, pp. 232-62.
PASSMORE, J.A. (1966), A Hundred Years of Philosophy (2nd
edn). London: Duckworth.
PERR 0 W, C. ( 1967), ‘A Framework for the Comparative Analysis
of Organisations’, American Sociological Review, 32 (2), pp.
194-208.
PERROW, C. (1972), Complex Organisations: A Critical Essay.
New York: Scott, Foresman and Co.
PETTIGREW, A.M. (1973), The Politics o/Organisational Deci-
sion Malcing. London: Tavistock Publications.
PIRSIG, R.M. (1976), Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Main-
tenance. London: Corgi.
PIVl:ECIC, E., ed. (197S), Phenomenological and Philosophical
Understanding. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
PIZZORNO, A., ed. (191l),Po6tical Sociology. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
PLEKHANOV, G. (1974), Selected Philosophical Works: Vol. I.
Moscow: Progress.
POPPER, K. ( 1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of
Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
POULANTZAS, N. ( 1969), ‘The Problem of the Capitalist State’,
New Left Review, S8, pp. 67-78.
PUGH, D.S. ( 1966), ‘Modern Organisation Theory: A Psychologi-
cal and Sociological Study’, Psychological Bulletin, 66 (21), pp.
23S-Sl.
PUGH, D.S. and HICKSON, D.J. (1976), Organisational
Structure in Its Context. Farnborough: Saxon House and
Lexington Books.
PUGH, D.S. and HININGS, C.R., eds. (1976), Organisational
Structure, Extensions and Rep6cations: The Aston Programme II.
Farnborough: Saxon House.
QUINN, R. E. ( 1977), ‘Coping with Cupid: The Formation,lmpact
and Management of Romantic Relationship in Organisations’,
Administrative Science Quarterly, 22, pp. 30-45.
RADCLIFFE-BROWN, A. (1952), Structure and Function in
Primitive Society. London: Cohen and West.
420 Bibliography
RAVETZ, J.R. (1972), Scientific Knowledge and Its Social
Problems. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
REICH, C.A. ( 1972), The Greening of America. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Report of the Royal Commission on Trade Unions and Employers’
Associations. London: HMSO, Cmnd. 3623. ·
REYNOLDS, L.T. and MELTZER, B. (1973), ‘Origins of
Divergent Methodological Stances in Symbolic Interaction’,
Sociological Quarterly, 14 spring, pp. 189-99.
REX, J. (1961). Key Problems in Sociological Theory. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
REX. J. ( 1974), Approaches to Sociology. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
RICE, A.K. ( 1958), Productivity and Social Organisation: The
Ahmedebad Experiment. London: Tavistock Publications.
RICE, A.K. (1963), The Enterprise and its Environment. London:
Tavistock Publications.
RICKMAN, H.P. (1976), Dilthey: Selected Writings. London:
Cambridge University Press.
RIEFF, P. (1959), Freud: The Mind Of the Moralist. London:
Gollancz.
ROBERTSON, R. ( 1974), ‘Towards the Identification of the Major
Axes of Sociological Analysis’, in J. Rex, ed., Approaches to
Sociology. op. cit.
ROCHER, G. (1974), Talcott Parsons and American Sociology
(trans. B. and S. Mennell). London: Nelson.
ROETHLISBERGER, F.J. and DICKSON, W.J. (1939), Man-
agement and the Worker. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
ROSE. A. (1962), Human Behaviour and Social Processes.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
ROSE, M. (1975),lndustrial Behaviour: Theoretical Development
Since Taylor. Harmondsworth: Allen Lane.
ROSZAK, T. (1969), The Making of a Counter Culture. New
York: Doubleday and Co.
ROY, D. (1960), ‘Banana Time: Job Satisfaction and Informal
Interactions’, Human Organisation, 18 (2), pp. 156-68.
RUNCIMAN, W.G. (1972),A Critique of Max Weber’s Philosophy
of Social Science. London: Cambridge University Press.
RUSSETT, C. E. (1966), The Concept of Equilibrium in American
Sociological Thought. New Haven: Yale University Press.
SAHLINS, M. (1914),Stone Age Economics. London: Tavistock
Publications.
Bibliography 421
SALAMAN, G. and THOMPSON, K., eds. (1973), People and
Organisations. London: Longman.
SARTRE, J.-P. (1948), Existentialism and Humanism (trans. P.
Mairet). London: Methuen.
SARTRE, J.-P. (1966), Being and Nothingness. New York:
Washington Square Press.
SARTRE, J.-P. (1974), Between Existentialism and Marxism.
London: Pantheon.
SARTRE, J.-P. (1976), Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. I.
London: New Left Books.
SAYLES, L.R. (1958), Behaviour of Industrial Work Groups:
Prediction and Control. New York: John Wiley.
SCHEGLOFF, E.A. and SACKS, H. (1973), ‘Opening Up Oos-
ings’, Semiotica, 8 (4), pp. 289-327.
SCHEIN, E. (1970), Organisational Psychology (2nd edn).
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
SCHROYER, TRENT. (1971), ‘ARe-Conceptualisation of Criti-
cal Theory’, in J.D. Colfax and J.L. Roach, e4s., Radical
Sociology, op. cit.
SCHUTZ, A. (1967), Collected Papers 1: The Problem of Social
Reality. (2nd edn). The Hague: Martinus Nijhotf.
SCHUTZ, A. (1964), Collected Papers II: Studies in Social
Theory. The Hague: Martinus Nijhotf.
SCHUTZ, A. (1966), Collec-ted Papers Ill: Studies in
Phenomenological Philosophy. The Hague: Martinus Nijhotf.
SCHUTZ, A. (1967), The Phenomenology of the Social World
(trans. G. Walsh and F. Lehnert). Evanston: Northwestern Uni-
versity Press.
SCHUTZ, A. and LUCKMANN, T. (1974), The Structures ofthe
Life World. London: Heinemann.
SCOTT, J.F. (1963), ‘The Changing Foundations of the Parsonian
Action Scheme’, American Sociological Review, 28 (5), pp.
116-35.
SELZNICK, P. (1943), ‘An Approach to a Theory of
Bureaucracy’, American Sociological Review, 8 (1), pp. 47-54.
SELZNICK, P. (1948), ‘Foundations of the Theory of Organisa-
tions’, American Sociological Review. 13 (1), pp. 25-35.
SELZNICK, P. (1949, 1966), T.V.A. and The Grass Roots. 1949
edn, Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press; 1966 edn,
New York: Harper and Row.
SELZNICK, P. (1957), Leadership in Administration. New York:
Harper and Row.
422 Bibliography
SHAW, M. (1974), ‘TheTheoryoftheStateandPolitics: A Central
Paradox of Marxism’, Economy and Society, 3 (4), pp. 429-50.
SHAW, M. (1975), Marxism and Social Science. London: Pluto.
SILVERMAN, D. (1970), The Theory of Organisations. London:
Heinemann.
SILVERMAN, D. (1975a), ‘Accounts of Organisations- Organ-
isational Structures and the Accounting Process’, in J.B.
McKinlay, Processing People: Cases In Organisational
Behaviour, op. cit.
SILVERMAN, D. (1975b), Reading Castaneda. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
SILVERMAN, D. and JONES, J. (1973), ‘Getting In: The Man-
aged Accomplishments of .. Correct” Selection Outcomes’, in J.
Child, ed., Mali and Organisation, op. cit.
SILVERMAN, D. and JONES, J. (1976), Organisational Work:
The Language of Grading /The Grading of Language. London and
New York: Collier/Macmillan.
SIMMEL, G. (1919), Nachgelassenes Tagebuch, Logos VII.
SIMMEL, G. ( 1936), The Metropolis and Mental Life. Chicago:
University of Chicago.
SIMMEL, G. (1950), ‘The Sociology of Georg Simmel’, in K.H.
Wolff, The Sociology of Georg Simmel, op. cit.
SIMMEL, G. (1955), Conflict and the Web of Group Affiliations
(trans. K.H. Wolff and R. Bendi·x). Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
SIMON, H.A. (1951),Administrative Behaviour: A Study of Deci-
sion Making Processes in Administrative Organisation (2nd edn).
New York: Collier/Macmillan.
SIMON, H. (1964), ‘On the Concept of Organisational Goal’,
Administrative Science Quarterly, 9 (1), pp. 1-22.
SKINNER, B.F. (1953), Science and Human Behaviour. New
York and London: Macmillan.
SKINNER, B.F. (1957), Verbal Behaviour. New York:
Appleton-Century-Crofts.
SKINNER, B.F. (1972), Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New
York: Alfred Knopf.
SNOW. C.P. (1959), The Two Cultures and the Sdentific Re,•olu-
tion. London: Cambridge University Press.
SPENCER, H. (1873), The Study of Sociology. London: Kegan
Paul and Tench.
SPIEGELBERG, H. (1965), The Phenomenological Movement,
vols. I and II. The Hague: Martinus NijhotT.
STIRNER, M. (1907), The Ego and His Own. New York: Lib-
ertarian Book Club.
Bibliography 423
STRYKER, S. (1957). ‘Role-taking Accuracy and Adjustment’,
Sociometry, 20, pp. 286-96.
STOUFFER, S.A. (1949), The American Soldier. Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press.
STRASSER, H. ( 1976), The Normative Structure of Sociology.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
STRAUSS, A.L. (1964), G.H. Mead: On Social Psychology.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
SUDNOW, D. (1965), ‘Normal Crimes: Sociological Features of
the Penal Code in a Public Defender Office’, Social Problems, 12
(3), pp. 255-76.
SUDNOW, D. (1972), Studies in Social Interaction. New York:
Free Press.
TANNENBAUM, A.S. (1968), Control in Organisations. New
York: McGraw Hill.
TAYLOR, F. W. (1947), Scientific Management. London and
New York: Harper.
TERREBERRY, S. (1968), ‘The Evolution of Or:ganisational
Environments’, Administrative Science Quarterly, 12 (4), pp.
590-613.
THEVENAZ, P. (1962), What is Phenomenology? New York:
Quadrangle.
THOM, R. (1975), Structural Stability and Morphogenesis. New
York: Benjamin.
THOMAS, W.l. (1971), ‘The Definition of The Situation’, in L.A.
Coser and B. Rosenberg, Sociological Theory, op. cit.
THOMPSON, J.D. (1967), Organisations in Action. New York:
McGraw Hill.
THORNS, D. (1976), New Directions in Sociology. Toronto:
Rowmann and Littlefield.
TODD, W. ( 1968), Analytical Solipsism. The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff.
TRIST, E.L. and BAMFORTH, K.W. (1951), ‘Some Social and
Psychological Consequences of the Longwall Method of Coal-
Getting’, Human Relations, 4 (I), pp. 3-38.
TRIST, E.L., HIGGIN, G.W., MURRAY, H. and POLLOCK,
A.B. (1963), Organisational Choice. London: Tavistock Publica-
tions.
TURNER, A.N. and LAWRENCE, P.R. (1965), Industrial Jobs
and the Worker. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
TURNER, B.A. ( 1971), Exploring the Industrial Subculture. Lon-
don: Macmillan.
424 BibUography
TURNER, R., ed. (1974), Ethnomethodology. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
TUTILE, H.N. (1969), Wilheim Dilthey’s Philosophy of Histori-
cal Understanding. Leiden: E.J. Brill.
UDY, S. ( 1959), Organisation of Work: A Comparative Analysis of
Production Among Non-Industrial Peoples. New Haven:
H.R.A.F. Press.
URRY, J. and WAKEFORD, J., eds. (1973), Power In Britain.
London: Heinemann.
VAN DEN BERG HE, P.L. ( 1969), ‘Dialectic and Functionalism:
Towards a Theoretic Synthesis’, in W.L. Wallace, ed., Sociologi-
cal Theory, op. cit.
VICKERS, G. (1966), The Art of Judgement. London: Chapman
and Hall.
VON BERTALANFFY, L. (1950), ‘The Theory of Open Systems
in Physics and Biology’, Science, 3.
VON BERTALANFFY, L. (1956), ‘General System Theory’,
General Systems, I, pp. 1-10.
VROOM, V.H. (1964), Work and Motivation. New York: John
Wiley.
VROOM, V.H. and DECI, E.L. (1910),Managementand Motiva-
tion. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
VROOM, V.H. (1976), ‘Leadership’, in M.D. Dunnette, ed.,
Handbook of Industrial and Organizational Psychology, op. cit.
WALKER, J. and GUEST, R.H. (1952), The Man on the Assem-
bly Line. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
WALLACE, W.L. (1969), Sociological Theory. London:
Heinemann.
WALTON,P.andGAMBLE,A.(l972),FromAiienationtoSurp-
lus Value. London: Sheed and Ward.
WALSH, D. (1972), ‘Varieties of Positivism’, in Filmer et al., New
Directions in Sociological Theory, op. cit.
WARNER, M., ed. (1973), The Sociology of the Work Place.
London: George Allen and Unwin.
WARNER, W .L. and LOW, J .0. ( 1947), The Social System of the
Modern Factory. New Haven: Yale University Press.
WARNOCK, M. (196S), The Philosophy of Sartre. London:
Hutchinson.
WARR, P.B., ed. (1971), Psychology at Work. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
WEBER, M. (1947), The Theory of Social and Economic Orgall-
isation (trans. A. Henderson and T. Parsons). Glencoe, Ill.: Free
Press.
Bibliography 425
WEBER, M. (1949), The Methodology of the Social Sciences.
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
WEDDERBURN, D. ed. (1974), Poverty, Inequality and Class
Structure. London: Cambridge University Press.
WEIR, M., ed. (1976), Job Satisfaction. London: Fontana.
WHEELER, S., ed. (1970), On Record. New York: Russell Sage.
WHITEHEAD, A.N. (192S), Science and the Modern World.
London: Macmillan.
WHITEHEAD, T.N. (1938), The Industrial Worker. London:
Oxford University Press.
WHYTE, W.F. (1948),Human Reldtions in the Restaurant Indus-
try. New York: McGraw Hill.
WHYTE, W.F. (1955), Money and Motivation. New York:
Harper and Row.
WHYTE, W.F. (1969), Organisational Behaviour: Theory and
Application. Homewood, Ill.: Irwin-Dorsey.
WILLENER, A. (1971), The Action Image of Society. London:
Tavistock Publications.
WILLIAMS, R. (1976), ‘Symbolic Interaction: The Fusion of
Theory and Research·, in D. Thoms, ed., New Directions in
Sociology, op. cit.
WINCH, P. (1958), The Idea of a Social Science. London: Rout-
ledge and Kegan Paul.
WINKLER. J.T. (197S), ‘Law, State and Economy: The Industry
Act 1975 in Context’, British Journal of Law and Society Vol. II,
pp. 103-28.
WINKLER, J.T. (1976), ‘Corporatism’, European Journal of
Sociology, Vol. 17, No. I, pp. 100-36.
WISDOM, J.O. (1956), ‘The Hypothesis of Cybernetics’, General
Systems, I, pp. 111-22. ·
WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1963), Philosophical Investigations.
Oxford: Blackwell.
WOLFF, K. H. ( 1950), The Sociology of Georg Simmel. Glencoe,
Ill.: Free Press.
WOOD, S. (1976), ‘The Radicalisation of Industrial Relations
Theory’, Personnel Review, 5 (3), pp. 52-7.
WOOD, S. and ELLIOT, R. (1977), ‘A Critical Evaluation of
Fox’s ”Radicalisation” of Industrial Relations Theory’, Sociol-
ogy, 11 (1), pp. 105-25.
WOOD, S. and KELLY, J. ‘Towards a Critical Management
Science’, Journal of Management Studies (forthcoming).
WOODCOCK, G. (191S),Anarchism. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
426 BibHography
WOODCOCK, G. (1977), The Anarchist Reader. London: Fon-
tana/Collins.
WOODWARD,J.(I9S8),ManagementandTechnology. London:
HMSO.
WOODWARD, J. (1965), Industrial Organisation, Theory and
Practice. London: Oxford University Press.
WOODWARD, J. (1~2),lndustrial Organisation: Behaviour and
Control. London: Oxford University Press.
WRONG, D.H. (1968), ‘Some Problems in Defining Social
Power’, American Journal of Sociology, 3 (4), pp. 673-81.
ZALD, M.N., ed. (1~0), Power in Organisations. Vanderbilt:
Vanderbilt University Press.
ZEEMAN, E.C. (1~6), ‘Catastrophe Theory’, Scientific Ameri-
can, 234 (4), pp. 65-83.
ZIMMERMAN, D.H. (l~Oa), ‘The Practicalities of Rule Us.’, in
J.D. Douglas, ed., Understanding Everyday Ufe, op. cit.
ZIMMERMAN, D.H. (1970b), ‘Record Keeping and the Intake
Process in a Public Welfare Organisation’, inS. Wheeler, ed., On
Record, op. cit.
ZIMMERMAN, D.H. and POLLNER, M. (1~0), ‘The Everyday
World as a Phenomenon’, in J.D. Douglas, ed., Understanding
Everyday Ufe, op. cit.
ZIMMERMAN, D.H. and WIEDER, D.L. (1~0), ‘Eth-
nomethodology and the Problem -of Order’, in J.D. Douglas, ed.,
Understanding Everyday Life, op. cit.
ZOLLSCHAN, O.K. and HIRSCH, W., eds. (1964), Explor-
ations in Social Change. London: ·Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Subject Index
KCGUntina practices, 247-8, 250, 260,
269
action frame « reference, 8, 11, 122,
137. 195-202, 209-10, 218, 353
Adnrillistrariv~ Sci~nc~ Qututerly, 162,
163
atienation,32,270,282,286,298,307,
311,312,323,324,329,~7.348,
349
in Simmel, 72
as bad faith, 304-5
as fetishism « commodities, 329
as one-dimensionality, 292, 293-4,
317, 332
transc::ended by identic:al subject-ob-
ject, 286, 287
alternative realities, 312-9
anarchism, 301, 339
anarchistic communism, 301, 333,
334,338-41
anarchistic individualism, 283,
299-302
anonde,45,91,92, 139
anti-orpnisation theory, 33, 31G-25
anti-positivism, 5, 28, 32, 200,228, 253,
291, 318, 320
Aston studies, 162-3, 166
behaviourism, 49, 73-4, 76, 80, 84,
102-4, lSI
behavioural symbolic interac:tionism,
77,79,81,189-93,251
biolqpc:al anaiOIY (organismic anai-
QIY),42,43,44,49-S0,52-3,S6,
61,63,64,65,68,73,81, 100,140,
153, 154, 159, 164, 167. 184, 187.
220,355,399,400
llureaucrac:y, 92-3, 162, 175, 315, 332.
~tltism,286,287,327,330,332,337,
340, 341, 349-SO, 372, 373, 377,
378, 380, 383, 386
crises fA, 326,337,344,359,368,369,
378,383
carastrophic analoay, 66, 336-7. 387,
399
causal analysis, 44, 231, 337-8
Chic:ap socioiOI)’, 77-8,82, 100, 190,
194-S
classical management theory, 123,
126-30, 142, 165, 166
communicative distonion, 269, 295,
296, 321, 323
conflict, 13, 72, 95, 203, 204, 205, D,
280,326
conflict theory, 34, 334, 349-57, 370,
389
conflict functionalism, 93-9,202,213
conaruency between strands on objec-
tive-subjcctivt dimension, 8, 103,
246
between orpnisational subsystems,
176-9
consciousness, 279-81;285, 286, 291,
292, 294, 291,307, 310, 311, 337,
358
class, 284, 286, 288
false, 32
patholoty fA, 306
continaency theory, 126, 164-81, 182
. contradictions, 34, 98, 307, 328-9, 344,
346, 347, 3SS, 356, 357, 358, 368,
377. 383, 386
conviviality, 314, 318
critic:al theory, 282, 283-99, 310, 312,
316,320
Frankfurt School, 284, 290-99, 302,
341,346
m organisations. 321-2
culture, SO, 100,101,193,315,318,320
cybernetics, 100, 101
determinism,6, 25, 34, 103,289,338,345
dialectic,280, 287,336,343,346,349,
357,383
dialcctic:al materialism, 94, 285, 330,
383-4
dysfunctions, 98-9, 184, 186, 355
empiricism, 76, 90, 218, 345, 353, 365,
374
abstracted,49,S7,82,92,104-6,180,
190
empiric:al studies fA orpnisational
characteristics, 126, 160-64
environment, 156-60, 164-6, 168, 171,
181, 336, 384
cpistemoloay. llii, I, 5, 57, 71, 75, BS,
428 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
130, 164, 192, 227. 228, 231, 232,
2SO, 21S, 276, 278, 291, 306, 337,
34S, 348, 399
epistemological break, 22, 25,34, 282,
284, 328. 342-3
cpodb~.233,242,244-S
equilibrium, 47, S9, 60-62, 101. 136,
139-40, 142, 147, 336
theories or organisation, 12S, 148-S2
elhnomethodology, 8, II, 21, 86, 201,
23S, 247-S3, 254, 2SS, 261, 312
linguistic, 248, 249, 2S2
situational. 248, 249, 2S3
ethnomethodological approaches to
organisational activities, 261-70,
271,272
exchange, 88-90
existcntialism,33, 282.299,302-6,310,
312,348
factional analogy, 66,3SS,l81 ,399,400
functional analysis, 44, 50-S3, 91-2,
94, 188
functional co-ordination. 14-IS. 107
functional imperatives, S4-S, 6S, 94,
IS4, 158-9, 168, 182-3
functionalist sociology, 41-117
structural functionalism, 43, 48,
49-57,64,81, 12S, IS2-4
functions,42,S0,97
manifest and latent, 93-4, 9S
or social conflict, 10, 49, 72, 96
Gristeswrsseucllqft'”· 228, 229, 236,
28S
German idealism, 7-8, 27, 31, 46, 69,
74, 107. 197′ 227. 230, 279, 282,
324, 331,336
neoidcalism,69, 73,83,282
objective idealism, 236, 279, 280-81,
28S, 290, 319, 327
subjec:tive idealism, 238, 279, 281,
282,302
Harvard School, 46, 61-2, 138, 148
Hawthorne Studies, 123, 130-43, 20S
Hqclianism, 280, 282, 28S, 288, 291,
296-7,300,303,327,329,331,336,
341, 342, 346, 348
hermeneutic circle, 237-8
hermcncutics,232,23S-8,2S4,210,294
bOIDCOstasis, S9,61,62, 101,140
bumannarurc,2,6, 71, 7S,I64,27S,276
human relations, Ill, 119, Ill, 143-6,
16S-6, 381
ideal type, 231, 2S2, 266
or burcauaac:y, 86, 163,366
idcopapbic approach, 6, 28, 32, 2S3
ideological hegemony, 289
industrial psychology, 123. 128-30,
Ill, 13S, 142, 143, 14S-6
industrial relations, x, 28, S1, 212,
384-S, 401
industrial sociology, x. 28, 131.401
sociology of Of’8anisations, 118, 192
integration hypothesis, 179-80
integrative theory, 48, 87-102
intentionality, 241-2
interactionism, 48, 68-87, 101, 191
symbolic interactionism, 78-82, 8S,
189, 190, 193, 209
intermediaries, 297, 307
interpretive paradigm, 22, 23, 28-32,
227-78, 306, 397
job satisfaction, 134-8, 143-6
language, so. 198, 238, 267, 269-70,
295-6, 297. 323
life-world, 243, 249
Marxism, xiii, 22, 27, 33, 99, 108,
283-99,301,306,327-33
contemporary Mediterranean, 333,
341-9,370
Russian, 333, 334-8, 340, 341
structuralist approaches to organisa-
tion theory, 377-8S
mechanical analogy, 47, 61, 68, 100,
130, 132, 140, IS3, 220, 336, 399
methodology, 2, 6, S7, 71, 1S, lOS, 164,
190,2S0,27S,276,278,288,399
mode or organisation, 311, 374
murual aid, 339-40
nominalism, 4, 28, 32, 199, 2S3
Nomothetic approach, 6, 2S, 34, 82,
103, lOS, 277, 338
nothinancss, 303-4
objectivism, 49, 102-6, 121-2, 160-84
objectivist approaches, 8, 21-3, 76,
103, 106, 130, 144, 160-64, 334,
338,341, 342,348
ontology, xii, I, 4, S7, 71, 1S, 130, 164,
190, 191, 199, 227, 232, 239, 2SO,
2S3, 266, 272, 273, 274, 21S, 276,
287, 306, 310, 326, 337, 34S, 347,
398,399
ontological oscillation, 266, 270
order-conflict debate, xii-xiii, IG-16,
28
organisational psychology, x, 28, 401
organisations, 127-8, ISO, 152-4, 219,
260, 273, 310, 311, 365, 368, 369,
373, 376, 379, 380, 384, 317, 319,
395,391
as open systems, 154-60. 167-71
as structures, 161-1, 166, 186, 189,
265. 267. 269, 274
organisation theory, x, 28, 118, 261,
273-5. 321. 324, 373, 3W, 401-2
functionalist, 118-26,275,331,374,
375, 388
critique of, 311-13,321-1,365-7
paradigm, x-xi, xiii, 23, 24-5
phenomenology, 8, II. 21, 76. 201.
232-1, 240-17. 254, 255, 267.
273-8,279,285,292,349,391
existential, 200, 235, 243-7, 254, 302
transcendental, 234, 235, 240-13, 246
phenomenological reduction, 242
phenomenological sociology, 193, 235,
247-53, 266, 272, 275-8
phenomenological · symbolic interac-
tionism, 77, 79, 81, 86, 235, 247,
249,250-53,261,270-73
pluralist theory, 122, 141, 187, 188,
202-17
positivism
epistemological, 5, 25, 34, 82, 197,
277,288,326,333,334,337,347
sociological, 7-8,26-7,41-8,69,73,
83, 107,227,228,294,331,353
post-industrialism. 126, 157. 182-1
power, 89, 105, 203-1, 208, 209,
212-17. 351-2. 353, 354, 356-7,
372, 376, 388
quality of working life movement, 126,
181-1, 381
radical change, sociology of, 16-19,
21-3,32,33,326,338.351,358
radical organisation theory, 35, 365-92
radical Weberianism, 331-3, 349-57,
369, 371-7, 385, 387
rationality, 151, IS4, 206, 231-2, 294,
295, 323, 332
realism, 4, 25, 34, 103, 191, 337, 345
reference groups, 91-2
reflexivity, 193-1, 244, 248
regulation, sociology of, 16-9, 21-3,
25,28,45,76, 103,231-2.254,278,
3Sl
Subject Index 429
reificalion, S3, 160, 196, 201, 218, 287,
312, 324, 374
science, 41, 44, 69, 103, 107,230,315,
326,347
scientific management, 126-7, 132,
13S, 380, 381
social action theory, 68-9, 82-7, 218
social facts, 44, 138, IW
social system theory,48,49-68,121-2,
123-60, 205-7, 218-20
morphogenic systems theory,
99-102
socio-technical systems theory, 125,
136, 146-8, ISS, 183, 381
systems theory, 48, 57-68, 125
solipsism, 23S, 238-10, 282-3, 302,
310,337
reef of, 239, 240, 242, 283
state,300,340,366,371-7
structure, 42, Sl, 54, S7, 6S, 206, 260,
263,264,265,276,307,328,343-S,
356, 3S7. 358, 368, 369, 377. 383,
388,389
subjectivist approaches. 8, II, 21-3,
80, 189, 191, 233, 239
surplus labour, 381-2
Tavistock Institute, 146-8, ISS, 159
technology, 119-20, 146-7, 161, 173,
180, 293, 313-1, 316. 336
theories of bureaucratic dysfunctions,
122, 184-9, 207-9
total institutions, 191-2, 209, 210
totality, 286-7, 288, 291, 306, 307, 320,
323, 343, 344, 349, 358, 368, 369,
370, 3n. 384, 400
typifications,24S,2S2,266,273
union of egoists, 300
v,strhrn. 82-3, 197, 201, 229-30,
232, 23S, 236, 238. 244, 2S3, 331
voluntarism. 6, 28. 32, as. 218, 2S3, 276,
288,289
work, 29S-6, 317,318,320,324
Name Index
Adorno, T. W., 291-2
Aiken, M., 163
Allen, V. L., 383-4
Aldlusser, L., 22, 34, 331, 341-9,
3SS-9, 374-S
Anual, A., S7-8
Anthony, P. D., 312. 316
Af’IYI’is, C., 147-8, 174, 206
Aron, R., 41
Avridl, P., 339
Bamforth, K. W.,6S,I46,JSS,I61,206
~.P.,310,377-81
Barnard, C., 61-2, 12S, 148-SS, 20S
Bateson, G., 387
Bennis, W., 183
Berpr, P. L., 21, 193, 199
Berason. G., 76, 244
Bedeley, G., 239, 279
Beynon, H., 320-21
Bittner, E., 261-7, 274
Blake, R. R., 176
Blau,P. M.,49,88-90,120,162,184-S,
188-9, 207, 21G-ll
Blauner, R., 120
Blumer, H., 78-82, 100, 190
Bookchin, M., 301
Braverman, H., 379-81
Buckley, W., 43. S6-7, 60-1. 6S
Bukharin, N., 34,99-101,333-8, 341,
343, 34S, 3S9
Buraess, E. W., 100
Bums, T., 161, 166, 171, 172, 17S
Callinicos, A., 343-4
Carey, A., 130
Castaneda, C., 33, 312, 315-16
Cherns, A. B., 182-3
Child, J .• 171
Cicourel, A. V ., 249
Oeg, S., 320-21
Cohen, P. S., 10-11, 16, 84, 336
Colletti, L., 34,331,341-2,346-9
Comte, A., 26, 41-3, 49, SS, 108
Cooper, R •• 180
Coser, L. A., 10, 13, 69, 10-72, 93,
95-9
Crombie, A. D., 119, 192, 202, 209,
373-4
Dahl, R., 214
Dahrendorf, R., 10-19, 34,87, 3SO-SS,
371-3
Dalton, M., 206
Davis, L. E., 182-3
Dawe, A., 10
Della Volpe, 347
Dcnzin, N. K., 2SI-2
Dickson, D., 312-16
Dickson, W.J.,61,131-6,138-9,142,
144
Dill, W. R., 171
Dildley, W., 31, 197,228-38, 27S, 28S
Douglas, J. D., 248, 2SJ-2
Dubin, R., 17S, 206
Dunlop, D. T., S7
Durkheim, E., 17,26-7, 44-S, 47. 49,
SS, 84-S, 90, 108, 138-9, 141, 191
EldridJe, J. E. T., 87, 119, 192, 19S,
202,209,373-4
Emerson, J., 271-2
Emerson, R. M., 214
Emery, F. E., IS7, 166, 171
Engels, F., 34, 94, 282, 285, 329-31,
33S-8, 343, 346
Esland, G., 320
EIZ.ioni, A., 120, 211
Faris, R. E. L., 78
Fayol, H., 127
Feuerbach, L., 281
Fichte, J. F., 279-83, 302
Filmer, P., 267
Follett, M. P., 127
Fox, A., 202, 211
French, J. R. P .• 216
Freud, S., 228, 292
Fromm, E., 291-2
Gadamer, H. G .• 23S, 237, 238, 294
Garfinkel, H., 21, 247-9, 250, 274
Giddens, A.. 8S, 214, 232, 237-8,
249-SO
Goffman, E., 190-92, 209-10
Gold, R. L., 194
Goldmann, L., 284
Goldlhorpe, J. H., 87, 9S, 17S, 190,
194-S, 206, 209, 384
Gouldner, A. W., IS, 94, ‘Tl-9, 184-9,
2(11, 208,284,313,316,334,387
Gramsc:i, A., 33, 283-4, 288-91,
341-2, 348
Guest, R. H., 144, 161
Habennas, J., 33, 238, 254, 269-70,
2n, 291-6,313,316,320,321
Hage, J., 163
Hall, R. H., 65, 163, 166, 175
Hegel, G., 33,227, 2n. 280-82,285-7,
300,303,331,346,3n
Heideger, M .• 237, 240, 243, 269
Henderson, L. J., 61, 62, 148
Herzberg, F., 144, 145, 174
Hickson, D. J., 65, 119, 162, 166, 173,
211,216
Hindess, B., 356
Hirst, P., 356
Romans, G. C., 57, 61, 62, 88, 89, 100,
103, 190
Hoppock, R., 143
Horkheimer, M .• 290-91
Hughes, E., 194, 228. 230
Hussain, A., 356
Husserl, E., 31, 33, 228. 232-S,
240-46,279-80,283,285,302-03,
348
Hyman, R., 384
Dlicll, I., 33, 312, 314, 316
Jaques, E., 173
James. W., 46,76
Jarvie, I. E., SO
Johnson, J. E. M., 249
Jones, J., 267-70, 320-21
Kant, 1., 31, 33, 227-8, 279. 284, 349
Kahn,R.I.,S7,63.6S, 120,157-60,206
Katz, D., 57, 63, 65, 120, 157-60, 206
Keat, R .• 25
Kierkegaard, S., 303
Kropotkin, P .. 333-4, 338-41
Kuhn, T. S., 24, 2SS
Laing, R. D., 33, 306
Landsberger. H. A., 130
Lawrence, P.R., 164-7, 171, 173, 179,
206
Lenin, V. I., 34, 331, 333, 334, 336, 348,
3n
Lewin, K., 144
Uchtheim, G., 285
Ukert, R., 144
Locke, E. A .• 145
Lockwood, D., 10, II, 55, 355-7
Lorscll,J. w .. 164-7,71,79,206
Lowenthal, L., 291
Name Index 431
Luckmann, T., 21, 193, 199
LukAcs, G., 33, 282, 284-91, 303,
341-2, 344-S, 388
Lukes, s., 44, 45, 388
Lupton, T., 128, 129, 190, 191, 206
Malinowski, 8., SO, 51, 53, 54, SS, 64
Manis, J. G., 82
Mardi, J. G., lSI, 152, 206
Marcuse, H., 33, 86, 291-S, 313, 317,
320, 331, 347
Marshall, A., 46, 84, 85
Marx, K., II, 25, 33, 34,87, 90, 93-6,
98, 99, JOB. 211. 269. 2n. m,
282-7, 290-91, 2’T1-9, 300, 303,
305,307,319,327-31,334,337-8,
342-3,346-S2,3SS,3S7,36S,371,
372,374,377,379,381,385,387
Maslow, A., 145, 174
Mayo, E., 61, 129, 131, 139, 142, 148,
380
McCullough, A., 375, 376
Mc:Grqor. D., 176
McHugh, P., 249
McNall, S. G., 249
Mead, G. H., 27, 46, 69, 73-81, 86-7,
90,92, 100,101,189,190,235,247,
251, 304
Meakin, D., 312, 317
Merleau-Ponty, M., 240, 243
Meltzer, 8., 82
Merton, R. K., IS, 49, 56, 69, 88,
90-100, 106-7, 122, 152. 184-90,
2(17-8, 3SS
Mezaros, I., 284
Michels, R., 186, 374
Miliband, R., 35, 371, 372-4
Miller, E. J., 63, 157
Mills, C. Wright, 14, lOS
Morris, C., 14-S
Mouton, J. S., 176
Mouzelis, N., 374-S
Natanson, M., 76, 232-3
Nisbet, R. A., 71, 72, 334
Pareto, V., 11. 26,47-8, 61-2. 84-S,
108, 132, 138-9, 141, 153, 33.5
Park, R. L., 78, 100
Parsons, T., 14, 43, 54-7, 61-S, 84-S,
90-91, 96-7, 100-01, ISS, 198,
200-01,214,228,249
Perrow, C., 148, 153, 172
Pettigrew, A. M., 213
Phillipson, M., 267
Piaget, J., 383
Pirsig, R. M., 312, 314
Plekhanov, G., 34,330-35,341,345-6
Poulantzas, N .• 34, 373
432 Sociological Paradigms and Organisational Analysis
PUp, D. S., 6S, 119, 162, 166, 173, 211. Sudnow, D .• 267. 271, 272
216 Sweezy, P., 370, 377-81
PUIIbci’J, S .• 21, 193, 199
Radcliff~ Brown, A., 50-57. 63-S, ISS
Raven, B., 216
Reich, C. A., 312, 314-16
Rex, J.,lS, 87, 3SO, 353-S, 371. 373
Rice, A. K., 6S, ISS, IS6, IS7, 172
Rickman, H. P., 237
Rocher, G .• S4
Rocthlisberger,F.J.,61, 131-6,138-9,
142, 144
Rose, A., 79, 80, 82, 194
Roszak, T., 312, llS-16
Roy, D., 190, 191
Runciman, W. G., 230
Sacks, H .• 249
Sahlins, M .• l87
Salaman. G.. 118
Sanre, J. P.,ll, 239,240,243,254,277,
283,302-0S.310,348
Sayles, L. R., 161
Schcglotr, E. A., 249
Schein, E., Ill
Schroyer, Trent, 296
Schutz.A.,31,86,190,193-4,197,200,
230-32,23S,240,243-9,255,265,
266,302
Scott, J. F., 120
Sclznick, P .• 12S, ISO, 152-4, 184-9,
207-8. 262
Shannon, M .• 37S-6
Silverman, D., 10. 87, 122, 190,
195-201, 209-10, 266-70, 275,
277. 320, 321
Simmel, G., 27, 46, 69-73, 76-8,
86-90, 93, 9S, 100, 189, 191, 211
Simon, H. A., 125, 150-54, 206, 213
Skinner, B. F., 102-S
Small. A., 78, 100
Spencer, H .• 26, 41, 43, 44,47, 49, 5S,
68, 108,374
Spiegelberg, H., 234
Spinoza. B .• 349
Stalker, G. M .• 161. 166, 171, 172, 17S
Stirncr, M .• 28l, 299,300,301,305
Tannenbaum, A. S .• 207
Taylor, F. W .• 126-30, 132, 144, 146,
174, 380
Terrebcrry, S., 171
Thevenaz,P .• 241-2
Thom, R •• 387
Thomas. W. I., 78
Thompson, J. D .• 120, 166, 171
Thompson, K .• 118
Trist, E. L.,6S, 146,15S,IS7,161, 166,
171, 206
Turner, A. N., 173
Turner, B. A., 190. 192-4, 209
Udy, S., 166
Urry, J., 2S
Urwick, 127
Veblen, T .• 96
Van Den Berghe, P. L., 10
Vickers, G., 120
Von Bertalantry, L .• SS, S9, 60, 62,68
Vroom, V. H .• 144
Walker, J .• 144. 161
Walsh. D., 267
Weber, M., II. 27, 31,46, 69,82-7,90,
96. 118-19, 122. 148, 1.50, ISl,
161-3. 17S, 184-5, 187-90, 193,
19S, 197, 201,217,228-35,244-7,
252. 2S3, 262, 266, 27S, 292,
330-34, 349-52, 355-7, 366, 371,
373, 374, 38S
Whitehead, A. N .• 76, 132
Whyte, W. F .• 119, 144, 206
Wieder, D. L.. 2SI, 2S2. 264, 26S
Wingenstein, L., 2Soi-S
Wood, S., 384
Woodcock, G., 301
Woodward, J .• 120, 161-2, 166, 17.5,
192
Wrong, D. H .• 216
Zald, M. N .• 213
Zimmerman, D. H., 251-2, 264-7
Cover
Title
Copyright
Contents
List of Figures
List of Tables
Acknowledgements
Introduction
PART I: IN SEARCH OF A FRAMEWORK
1 Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science
The Strands of Debate
Analysing Assumptions about the Nature of Social Science
2 Assumptions about the Nature of Society
The Order-Conflict Debate
‘Regulation’ and ‘Radical Change’
3 Two Dimensions: Four Paradigms
The Nature and Uses of the Four Paradigms
The Functionalist Paradigm
The Interpretive Paradigm
The Radical Humanist Paradigm
The Radical Structuralist Paradigm
Exploring Social Theory
PART II: THE PARADIGMS EXPLORED
4 Functionalist Sociology
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The Structure of the Paradigm
Social System Theory
Interactionism and Social Action Theory
Integrative Theory
Objectivism
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
5 Functionalist Organisation Theory
Theories of Organisation within the Functionalist Paradigm
Social System Theory and Objectivism
Theories of Bureaucratic Dysfunctions
The Action Frame of Reference
Pluralist Theory
Debate within the Functionalist Paradigm
6 Interpretive Sociology
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The Structure of the Paradigm
Hermeneutics
Solipsism
Phenomenology
Phenomenological Sociology
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
7 The Interpretive Paradigm and the Study of Organisations
Ethnomethodological Approaches to the Study of Organisational Activities
Phenomenological Symbolic Interactionism and the Study of Organisational Activities
The Phenomenological Challenge to Contemporary Organisation Theory
Phenomenological Approaches to the Study of Organisational Situations: Problems and Dilemmas
8 Radical Humanism
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The Structure of the Paradigm
Critical Theory
Anarchistic Individualism
French Existentialism
The underlying Unity of the Paradigm
9 Anti-Organisation Theory
Towards Alternative Realities
Towards an Anti-Organisation Theory
10 Radical Structuralism
Origins and Intellectual Tradition
The Structure of the Paradigm
Russian Social Theory
Contemporary Mediterranean Marxism
Conflict Theory
The Underlying Unity of the Paradigm
11 Radical Organisation Theory
Radical Weberian Approaches to a Radical Organisation Theory
Marxian Structuralist Approaches to a Radical Organisation Theory
Towards the Further Development of Radical Organisation Theory
PART III: CONCLUSIONS
12 Future Directions: Theory and Research
Bibliography
Index
Subject Index
Name Index
Social Aspects of
Computing
Rob Kling
Editor
Four Paradigms of
Information Systems
Development
Developing computer-based information systems necessarily in volves making
a number of implicit and explicit assumptions. The authors examine four
diffeen t approaches to information systems development.
Rudy Hirschheim and Heinz K. Klein
All systems developers approach the development task of systems failures. (The importance of implicit assump-
with a number of explicit and implicit assumptions tions has also been noted more generally in [3,4, 76,
about the nature of human organizations, the nature of 80, 891). We agree with the previous research that a
the design task, and what is expected of them. These better understanding of developer assumptions is im-
assumptions play a central role in guiding the informa- portant and we wish to extend the line of inquiry. In
tion systems development (ISD) process. They also dra- particular, we feel there is a need to explore the most
matically affect the system itself. This article will ex- fundamental foundations from where such assumptions
amine the kinds of implicit assumptions made during arise, and this is done by applying a philosophical line
systems development. of analysis.
Depending on the assumptions adopted, different sys-
tems development approaches are identifiable and each
of these leads to different system outcomes. Based on a
detailed analysis of the literature, we will examine the
fundamental assumptions of four major kinds of sys-
tems development approaches and discuss how they
lead to different outcomes.
More specifically, we wish to show (1) that although
there is a strong, orthodox approach to systems devel-
opment, there are recently developed alternatives that
are based on fundamentally different sets of assump-
tions; (2) that these assumptions primarily deal with the
attitudes adopted toward reality and how to obtain
knowledge about it; (3) that these assumptions are
either explicitly or implicitly made in adopting a partic-
ular development approach: (4) that the ways in which
system objectives are legitimized are directly related to
the development approach adopted; and (5) that impor-
tant social consequences result from applying a particu-
lar systems development approach.
The article is organized as follows. We begin by in-
troducing two case examples that illustrate how differ-
ent systems development assumptions become manifest
in practice. These assumptions are then grouped into
four paradigms of information systems development
and explained in detail. The rhetorical vehicle used for
explicating the paradigms are generic story types. The
paradigms are analyzed using the story types, dividing
the discussion into three parts: story line, interpreta-
tion, and analysis. We return to the case examples to
show how the manifest differences in the develop-
ment process and outcomes can be explained by the
four paradigms. We conclude by noting a number of
benefits associated with the identification and analysis
of the paradigms. The article provides a new vehicle for
theorizing about the nature, purpose, and practice of
information systems development.
TWO EXAMPLES
Other researchers have also noted the importance of
systems developer assumptions, but their work has fo-
cused on more specific aspects, e.g., analyst models of
the users [25, 421, analyst hypotheses about the nature
of requirements and behavior related to structuring
problems [96], and analyst and user values [57].
Whereas these studies employ empirical means to doc-
ument these assumptions, Bostrom and Heinen [14]
have relied on an analysis of the literature to document
seven implicit theories and views of designers as causes
Consider how the approaches taken in the following
two systems development projects differ.
@1989ACM0001-0782/89/1000-1199 $1.50
Automating Typesetting or Enhancing Craftsmanship?
Traditional newspaper production involves four major
processes: writing, editing, typesetting, and printing.
Reporters and columnists write copy which is then ed-
ited. Typesetters take the edited copy and relevant pic-
torial material, and lay out pages. Printers take the re-
sults and print the newspapers. Typical systems designs
focus on rationalizing newspaper production by com-
bining tasks that can logically be done on the same
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1199
Articles
electronic device, such as editing and formatting. Page
layout is conceived as a natural extension of format-
ting. A requirements analysis along these lines suggests
tha.t editors can perform the typesetting function be-
cause computers already aid the editors with editing
and page layout. Editors can embed typesetting com-
mands directly in the final copy. Page layout is done on
screen and sent to phototypesetting equipment. The ed-
itors become responsible not only for editing but also
for page make-up. Migh resolution screens; electronic
cut, paste, and scaling facilities; and previewing appara-
tus permit the typesetting function to be assigned to the
editors.
In the UTOPIA project [Zg, 471, an alternative ap-
proach was tried at one newspaper company. The sys-
tems development team consisted of union representa-
tivles and typesetters. Their goal was to establish an
electronic typesetting support system that would en-
hance the position of the typesetting craft in the news-
paper industry. The newspaper’s management was ex-
cluded from the design team so that typesetters’
interests were given primacy in all design decisions.
Ex:isting turnkey systems were considered inappro-
priate because of built-in design constraints and man-
agement biases that did not take into account the
unique requirements of the typesetting craft. These
management biases emphasized cost savings, efficiency,
and control leading to de-skilling, job losses, and an
aesthetically inferior product. Data processing special-
ists assumed an advisory role serving the typesetters’
interest. In the requirements analysis, the design team
viewed typesetting as an essential task requiring spe-
cia.list skills that would be lost by its integration with
editing. Two types of requirements were established:
(1) transformation of edited texts into made-up pages;
and (2) creation of an aesthetically pleasing product.
Typesetting skills differ from editorial skills; editors are
in charge of content, and typesetters are in charge of
form.* The typesetters were interested in retaining the
quality of typesetting and possibly enhancing their own
productivity. To retain quality, systems design options
focused on providing the flexibility and diversity of the
tratditional tools of the typesetting trade by electronic
means. To meet this objective, the team found it neces-
sary to use hardware mock-ups to overcome the limita-
tions of the then-available technology. While similar to
prdotyping, the hardware mock-ups overcame the bias
inherent in the technology used for prototyping. The
available prototyping tools were unable to accommo-
date the craft skills that were used to meet the aes-
thetic requirements of newpaper page layout. To en-
hance the quality of typesetting output, additional
system capabilities, such as scaling and finetuning the
contrast of pictures, were added. The UTOPIA ap-
proach resulted in an electronic typesetting support
’ The results of editorial work (planning content, planning pages. and text
editinel mav be called a iournalistic model of the news~amx owe. The iour-
I I _ . . . I I
nalistic competence involved lies in improving the readability of the product.
The make-up person refines the product by giving the journalistic model a
graphic design. The graphic competence involved lies in improving the legi-
bility of the product [‘La].
system that enhanced the typesetters’ skills and pro-
ductivity.
The UTOPIA model also required the establishment
of a new work organization [28]. While reporters have
access to display terminals to write their articles, they
do not code the text with typesetting commands. A
central production unit, where journalists and graphic
workers cooperate closely, is responsible for page edit-
ing and make-up, typing manuscripts, proofreading, in-
corporating major revisions, editing standard features
such as TV listings, and coding individual articles. The
editorial staff comprises editors and subeditors, whose
responsibilities are also changed. Subeditors work most
closely with the typesetters to make up the pages. Edi-
tors are primarily responsible for maintaining a consis-
tent overall viewpoint among different articles and
serve as discussion partners for subeditors [28].
Developing an Expert System or a System for Experts?
Deregulation has forced airlines to become increasingly
cost conscious, yet airline safety depends on costly,
high quality engine maintenance. In order to rational-
ize engine maintenance, one airline com:pany devel-
oped an expert system consisting of the rules for engine
maintenance and repair. During the knowledge acquisi-
tion phase, rules were extracted from engineering spec-
ifications and maintenance handbooks.
When engines arrived at the maintenance plant, me-
chanics disassembled them and placed the parts on
work tables. Robots diagnosed possible faults through
automated measuring and sensing. The facts gleaned
about the state of the engine parts were fed to the
expert system which then applied its rule base to deter-
mine necessary repairs. It printed out a work schedule
for making the repairs which was then followed by the
mechanics.
When the system was implemented, the promised
cost decrease in engine maintenance did not material-
ize; on the contrary, maintenance costs increased by
13 percent. A redesigned system based on an alterna-
tive design strategy was sought. A new dlesign team that
included union representatives and mechanics was
formed. Their cooperation was motivateld by a coalition
with management which they saw as necessary to se-
cure the viability of the company, and with it, their
jobs. The design team first analyzed the reasons for the
decrease in maintenance productivity and found that
under the old system, mechanics relied too heavily on
computer-based fault diagnosis. They did not check nor
challenge the computer diagnosis for possible errors.
These errors were the product of difficulties in formal-
izing the knowledge base. Apparently, the mechanics’
knowledge acquired through education and experience
could not easily be formalized and put i:nto the rule
base of the expert system. There may also have been an
error margin in the automatic sensing which created
ambiguities. The new design team shifted the focus of
requirements analysis from the acquisition of an expert
rule base to the support of the mechanics’ judgment in
diagnosing maintenance needs. The requirements study
1200 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10
Articles
focused on the subtleties that come into play in decid-
ing which maintenance is actually required for each
engine part. The new design left the mechanics in
charge of the fault diagnosis, because their experience
and judgment was now considered indispensible. After
the mechanics had decided on the necessary repairs
they would then consult the computer system for avail-
able repair options, availability of needed parts, etc. For
this purpose the computer system turned out to be very
useful. This design approach resulted in a system for
experts rather than an expert system.
These two examples pose an interesting and impor-
tant question: Do they point to subtle yet fundamental
differences that originate from conflicting systems de-
velopment philosophies, or are they merely variations
of a single theme, namely one where a family of devel-
opment approaches shares the same underlying philos-
ophy? The answer to this question is important because
different underlying philosophies may lead to radically
different options in terms of design features, implemen-
tation strategies, user satisfaction, and system use.
We seek to show that these differences are the prod-
uct of fundamentally different underlying systems de-
velopment assumptions. We identify dominant patterns
resulting from differing sets of core assumptions that
can be used to characterize the array of current system
development approaches. We do not claim that this is
the only way to organize them, nor that the assump-
tions necessarily correspond to actual beliefs to which
practitioners are committed.’ Rather, the core assump-
tions have been derived from studying the descriptions
of various systems development approaches that appear
in the literature.3
FOUR PARADIGMS
The most fundamental set of assumptions adopted by a
professional community that allows its members to
share similar perceptions and engage in commonly
shared practices is called a “paradigm.” Typically, a
paradigm consists of assumptions about knowledge and
how to acquire it, and about the physical and social
world.4 As ethnomethodological studies have shown
[x] such assumptions are shared by all scientific and
professional communities. As developers must conduct
inquiry as part of systems design and have to intervene
into the social world as part of systems implementation,
it is natural to distinguish between two types of related
‘To establish this would need a representative empirical follow-up study of
the belief systems held by practitioners. A first step in this direction is the
study undertaken by Vitalari and Dickson [96]. It showed that the processes
used by analysts in determining information requirements were more com-
prehensive than the literature on structured systems development approaches
had suppested.
’ Only insofar as the literature influences ISD practice would the assumptions
derived from the descriptions of systems development approaches also be
representative of the actual beliefs held by practitioners.
‘Paradigms are defined by Eiurrell and Morgan [IS] as “meta-theoretical as-
sunmtions about the nature of the sub&t of studv.” This differs somewhat
from Kuhn’s classic conception of paradigms which were defined as “univer-
sally recognized scientific achievements that for a time provide model prob-
lems and solutions to a community of practitioners” [56].
assumptions: those associated with the way in which
system developers acquire knowledge needed to design
the system (epistemological assumptions), and those
that relate to their view of the social and technical
world (ontological assumptions).
Two types of assumptions about knowledge
(epistemological) and the world (ontological) are given
by Burrell and Morgan [18] to yield two dimensions: a
subjectivist-objectivist dimension and an order-conflict
dimension. In the former, the essence of the objectivist
position “is to apply models and methods derived from
the natural sciences to the study of human affairs. The
objectivist treats the social world as if it were the natu-
ral world” [18, p. 71. In contrast, the subjectivist posi-
tion denies the appropriateness of natural science
methods for studying the social world and seeks to un-
derstand the basis of human life by delving into the
depths of subjective experience of individuals. “The
principal concern is with an understanding of the way
in which the individual creates, modifies, and inter-
prets the world in which he or she finds himself [or
herself]” (p. 3). In the order-conflict dimension, the or-
der or integrationist view emphasizes a social world
characterized by order, stability, integration, consensus,
and functional coordination. The conflict or coercion
view stresses change, conflict, disintegration, and co-
ercion. The dimensions when mapped onto one another
yield four paradigms (see Figure 1): functionalism
(objective-order); social relativism (subjective-order);
radical structuralism (objective-conflict); and neohu-
manism (subjective-conflict). This particular framework
has been chosen because it allows us to capture the
distinguishing assumptions of alternative approaches to
information systems development in a simplified yet
philosophically grounded way.
The functionalist paradigm is concerned with provid-
ing explanations of the status quo, social order, social
integration, consensus, need satisfaction, and rational
choice. It seeks to explain how the individual elements
of a social system interact to form an integrated whole.
The social relativist paradigm seeks explanation within
the realm of individual consciousness and subjectivity,
and within the frame of reference of the social actor as
opposed to the observer of the action. From such a
perspective “social roles and institutions exist as an
expression of the meanings which men attach to their
world” [93, p. 1341. The radical structuralist paradigm
emphasizes the need to overthrow or transcend the
limitations placed on existing social and organizational
arrangements. It focuses primarily on the structure and
analysis of economic power relationships. The neohu-
manist paradigm seeks radical change, emancipation,
and potentiality, and stresses the role that different so-
cial and organizational forces play in understanding
change. It focuses on all forms of barriers to emancipa-
tion-in particular, ideology (distorted communication),
power, and psychological compulsions and social con-
straints-and seeks ways to overcome them.
These paradigms, initially identified by Burrell and
Morgan [18] in the context of organizational and social
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1201
Bryan
Highlight
OBJECTIVISM <
Functionalism
Radical
Structuralism
ORDER
A
Social
Relativism
) SUBJECTIVISM
Neohumanism
V
CONFLICT
FIGURE 1. Information Systems Development Paradigms (adapted from [18])
research, also manifest themselves in the domain of
information systerns development.5 Yet to show how
the paradigms are actually reflected in ISD is compli-
cated. The paradigms are largely implicit and deeply
rooted in the web of common-sense beliefs and back-
ground knowledge [go] which serve as implicit “theo-
ries of action” [4]. A simplifying vehicle was sought to
help develop and articulate the paradigms, in particu-
lar, the types of behaviors and attitudes that follow
from them. Such a vehicle was found in the notion of
“generic stories” or, more precisely, generalized story
types (genres). Each story type consists of typical classes
of behavior that follow from the assumptions of a par-
ticular paradigm. For example, different types of behav-
ior in requirements determination arise depending on
whether one believes in an objective organizational
reality or not. These types of behavior were identified
and grouped into story types. Each of these was derived
by interpreting pools of systems development literature
that share the assumptions of a particular paradigm.
These pools have been identified by analyzing the spe-
cific core assumptions and beliefs that are revealed in
the concepts and examples they employ. This allows us
to explicitly compare sets of assumptions that typically
have not been widely articulated or systematically
compared.
‘The view that these four paradigms capture the whole of sociological and
organizational research is not without its critics. Numerous writers have criti-
cized the Burrell and Morgan framework for being oversimplified [cf. 21, 46).
For example, many are unhappy with the way functionalism is portrayed.
e.g., that it denies conflict and that functionalists always adopt positivism.
Coser’s [23] treatment of functionalism does take into account conflict; and
certain functionalists did not necessarily adopt positivism (cf. Talcott Parsons].
Others argue that the dichotomies projected by Burrell and Morgan are artifi-
cd. Although there iwe other frameworks for categorizing social science re-
search [37, 911, none is xs representative of the IS development domain. We
see the framework proposed by Burrell and Morgan–with some modifica-
tion-as best depicting the different classes of systems development ap-
proaches, relatively speaking. This is not meant, however, to rule out the
need to explore other alternatives.
After each story type has been articulated in some
detail, we provide a theoretical interpretation and dis-
cuss some of its potential consequences. (For stylistic
reasons, we shall now drop the qualifier type and sim-
ply speak of story. The theoretic interpretation will take
the form of discussing the (1) key actors of the story-
the “who” part of the story; (2) narrative-the “what”
of the story, what are the key features and activities;
(3) plot-the “why” of the story, why did the action of
the story take place the way it did; and [4) assump-
tions-the fundamental beliefs held by the actors of the
story, discussed in terms of epistemologi.cal and onto-
logical assumptions.
The four stories are neither equally well-developed
nor known. The same is true of their consequences. For
the first story, there is a large experiential base from
which to draw. It is the orthodox approach to systems
development and has been used to develop information
systems for decades. Its consequences, therefore, are
reasonably clear cut. The other three stories are more
recent and have not been widely applied. Thus practi-
cal knowledge about them is sparse and their conse-
quences largely conjectural. They are presented in the
rough chronological order in which they emerged.
The four paradigms, as depicted through the stories,
are not as clear cut nor as animated as they are made
out to seem. There is overlap and their differences are
overstated for the purpose of effect. They are, in fact,
archetypes-highly simplified but powerful concep-
tions of an ideal or character type [80]. ‘These ideal
types do not exist as real entities; rather their proper-
ties which are exhibited (to a greater or lesser degree)
in existing entities give the archetype meaning. The
archetypes reflected in the stories play #an important
role in conveying the essential differences that exist in
alternative conceptions of, and approaches to, systems
development.
1202 Communications of the ACM October 1989 V&me 32 Number 10
Articles
STORY I: THE ANALYST AS SYSTEMS EXPERT
Interpretation
Systems Development as Instrumental Reasoning
This story has progressed considerably over the years
[24, 87, 88, 941, and has been the source of many suc-
cessful systems. The story suggests that all information
systems are designed to contribute to specific ends. The
role of management is that of the leadership group in
the organization that knows or develops the ends
which are then translated and specified in terms of
systems objectives. The usual assumption is that the
specification is as objective as possible. The resolution
of polemical issues associated with objectives is seen as
the prerogative of management and not normally
within the domain of the systems developer. As a re-
sult, the ends can be viewed as being articulated,
shared, and objective. Of course, there are many kinds
of conflicts with which the system developer does deal,
but the tools and methods used typically concern only
the choice of means to prespecified ends, not the sub-
stance of the ultimate ends of a system.
Key Actors: Management, the system developer and
users. Managers are responsible for providing the sys-
tem objectives. The systems developer is the expert
who takes the objectives and turns them into a con-
structed product, the system. Management dictates the
ends; the developers use specific means to achieve the
ends. Users operate or interact with the system to
achieve organizational objectives.
The primary role of the analyst is to be the expert in
technology, tools and methods of system design, and
project management. Their application helps to make
systems development more formal and rational, placing
less reliance on human intuition, judgment, and poli-
tics. Politics is seen irrational as it interferes with maxi-
mal efficiency or effectiveness. As noted by DeMarco,
[27, p. 131 “Political problems aren’t going to go away
and they won’t be ‘solved.’ The most we can hope for is
to limit the effect of disruption due to politics. Struc-
tured analysis approaches this objective by making
analysis procedures more formal.”
Nnrrutive: Information systems are developed to sup-
port rational organizational operation and effective and
efficient project management. The effectiveness and ef-
ficiency of IS can be tested by objective means tests
which are similar to the empirical tests used in engi-
neering. Requirements specification builds on the no-
tion of a manifest and rational organizational reality.
Information systems development proceeds through the
application of “naive realism”-the notion that the va-
lidity of system specifications, data models, decision
models, and system output can be established by
checking if they correspond to reality. Reality consists
of objects, properties, and processes that are directly
observable.
PIot: The ideal of profit maximization. As an organiza-
tion’s primary goal is to maximize its shareholders’
wealth, the developed information systems must con-
tribute to its profitability. Management is the most ap-
propriate group to decide how profitability is to be at-
tained and thus, is empowered to specify what the
system objectives should be.
In this story there is one reality that is measurable
and essentially the same for everyone. Otherwise it
would not be possible to have what McMenamin and
Palmer [77] call the “true requirements of the system.”
The role of the developer is to design systems that
model this reality [36] in a way that will turn the sys-
tem into a useful tool for management to achieve their
ends [7]. In principle, these ends coincide with organi-
zational goals.
Through the concept of economic requirements, eco-
nomic reality becomes measurable, taking on a nature-
like, given quality. The economic reality (translated
into quantitative, financial goals, and systems perfor-
mance characteristics) allows system objectives to be
derived in an objective, verifiable, and rational way.
Systems design becomes primarily a technical process6
Assumptions: The epistemology is that of positivism in
that the developer gains knowledge about the organiza-
tion by searching for measurable cause-effect relation-
ships. The ontology is that of realism since an empirical
organizational reality that is independent of its per-
ceiver or observer is believed to exist. The paradigm is
that of functionalism, which is defined by Burrell and
Morgan as an overall approach which: “seeks to provide
essentially rational explanations of social affairs”
[18, p. 26
1.
Analysis and Discussion
The developer-as-systems-expert story, through its em-
phasis on various forms of modeling, focuses on grasp-
ing the underlying order of the domains in which or-
ganizational actors operate. In the process, it assumes
that there are general laws or regular patterns that help
to explain and predict reality. It seeks to capture these
by identifying key organizational relationships and as-
pects in IS that help the actors to orient themselves and
achieve their objectives. This simplifies a complex real-
ity, making organizational life more rational. Rational-
ity, in this case, relates to choosing the best means for
achieving given ends (i.e., maximize efficiency and ef-
fectiveness). The systems development approach sug-
gested by this story attempts to follow the scientific
‘This is in part due to the reification of economic requirements which hides
the human authorship of systems objectives, presenting them more as techni-
cal objectives. Such a view has a rich historical backing. The belief that the
economic laws are not of human authorship is very clearly portrayed by
Adam Smith in The Wealth of Nations who writes of an “invisible hand” that
directs management de&i& to realize the economic interests of individual
companies for the common good. From a social and economic policy perspec-
tive. it is therefore unwise to question the legitimacy of management in
deciding system objectives. This could only reduce the general welfare by
leading to suboptimal allocation of economic resources. Furthermore this
stow adouts manv features of the “bureaucraw ideal tvoe” of Weher 1971 such
. . _ ~1 . 1
as instrumental rationality, formalization, and depersonalization.
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1203
Bryan
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
Articles
method. This aids its clarity and comprehensibility, and
makes it widely acceptable to the community at large.
Moreover, it helps operationalize fuzzy issues and di-
rects efforts to finding productive technical solutions.
The features of this story support a number of appar-
ently appealing beliefs. First, it allows the developer to
play a neutral and objective role during systems devel-
opment which helps in clarifying the implications of
alternative system design options. Second, many would
claim it makes the issues of power, conflicting interests,
and system goals appear to be largely outside the do-
main of the systems developer. Moreover, a large num-
ber of systems have been successfully completed by
foll.owing the tenets of this story.
However, as Bostrom and Heinen [14] have pointed
out, the systems designer’s assumptions associated with
this story can lead to a number of conditions that con-
tribute to system failure. The story, therefore, has a
number of potential dysfunctional consequences. For
one, the primary emphasis is on investigating means
rather than discussing ends. There is an implicit as-
sumption that the ends are agreed. But in reality, ends
are controversial and the subject of considerable dis-
agreement and debate. By assuming the ends and thus
sys,tem objectives are agreed, legitimation can become
little more than a hollow force or thinly concealed use
of power. The prespecified ends meet the needs of cer-
tain system stakeholders at the expense of others.
There are also more fundamental problems with legiti-
macy. It is now widely doubted that economic laws
govern social affairs in a similar way as natural laws
govern the physical universe. Instead, it is believed that
economic affairs are governed by social conventions
and the decisions of a powerful socio-political elite.
There are no rational, deterministic laws that emerge
from an objective reality.
A reaction to the erosion of these legitimating beliefs
is end user resistance to change. To overcome resist-
ance to change, systems developers have relied on a
series of approaches, games, and strategies. These have
taken the form of planned change models (e.g., the
Lewin-Schein and Kolb-Frohman models), implementa-
tion strategies [2, 631, counterimplementation and
counter-counterimplementation strategies [6, 491, and
the like. These approaches, however, simply perpetuate
the notion that systems development and implementa-
tion is a type of game. They continue to concentrate on
means not ends. The assumption that the system objec-
tives are legitimate and agreed remains. Failure to fo-
cus on the legitimation of the ends has led to an inap-
propriate conception about why users resist change.
The adoption of functionalism as the preferred para-
digm for organizational knowledge acquisition also
poses problems. As Burrell and Morgan [18] point out,
the assumptions intrinsic to functionalism have proved
to be at odds with much of recent social science think-
in,g. Functionalism’s two essential assumptions. (1) that
there exists an objective empirical reality and positivis-
tic: methods are the best way to make sense of it, and
(2) that the nature of the social world is best conceived
in terms of an integrated order rather than conflict, are
widely felt to be problematic. Many now argue that
functionalism has not been a particularly successful
paradigm for understanding organizational and societal
life, as the subject of study-people-does not lend it-
self to study through positivistic means (cf. [12, 32, 43,
53, 62, 951). People have free will and observation is not
neutral. This latter point reflects the fact .that people as
objects of study always “observe back.” Tlhey can per-
ceive the observer’s plan of study and counteract it.
Note, however, that the more recent forms of function-
alism (cf. [l, 311) have recognized these p:roblems and
have proposed ways to overcome them.
In some of the more advanced thinking in ISD, there
is an awareness of the changing nature of organi-
zational reality facing the developer. It is explicitly rec-
ognized that at any point in time a system can, at best,
approximate the changing requirements emerging from
the constantly shifting trends and policies of organi-
zational life which can never fully be known to devel-
opers.7 Such insight transcends the mental “cage” of
functionalist tenets in ISD and insofar as practitioners
realize the consequences, they will see value in the
following stories.
STORY II: THE ANALYST AS FACILITATOR
Systems Development as Sense Making
The second story has emerged relatively recently (cf. [5,
9, 13, 20, 54, 731). It is partly a reaction to the shortcom-
ings of the first and in many ways its opposite. It recog-
nizes that knowledge about human means and ends is
not easily obtained because reality is exceedingly com-
plex and elusive. There is no single reality, only differ-
ent perceptions about it. Business does not deal with an
objective economic reality, but one that evolves
through changing traditions-social laws, conventions,
cultural norms, and attitudes. Trying to discern eco-
nomic laws is one way in which people try to make
sense of confusing experiences by imposing a possible
order. No one has a privileged source of knowledge, all
see different parts. Furthermore, the role of people in
shaping reality is very unclear. What they subjectively
experience as a willful choice of action may simply
be a reaction induced by enculturated habits or by
circumstances.
Management, too, tries to make sense of the confu-
sion and instill others with a commitment to the organ-
izational mission that is constantly evolving. IS are part
of the continually changing social environment and
somehow should help to identify which ends are desir-
’ In particular. consider the case when users and management are identical,
such as in executive support systems. In such cases, the goals of systems
development cannot be treated as if they were predetermined by higher
authoritv. Rather. the coals are derived from an analvsis of the shifting
forces f&n the envir&nent that affect the continueh vzability of the &gani-
zation. This is the responsibility of senior management. On the other hand, in
the classical data processing era, it was easy to set the gc& for systems
development because the systems dealt with well-understood and structured
tasks.
1204 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
User
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
able and feasible. The distinction between ends and
means is fluid and reversible. System objectives emerge
as part of the organizational construction of reality, the
“sense-making process” [8]. The role of the system de-
veloper is to interact with management to find out
what type of system makes sense, but there is no objec-
tive criterion that distinguishes between good and bad
systems. It all depends on what the parties come to
believe to be true. The developer should work from
within the users’ perspective and help them to find
their preferred views. He or she should ease the transi-
tion from one viewpoint to another, thereby alleviating
possible resistance to change. Ideally the developer-by
virtue of prior experiences, wisdom or special in-
sights-is able to reduce the pains of change. But, the
purpose and direction of change is hidden from him or
her just as much as it is from everyone else. The devel-
oper’s expertise is similar to that of the midwife who
can ease the process of birth and make sure that the
baby emerges safe and sound, but has no part in design-
ing its genetic characteristics.
Any system that meets with the approval of the af-
fected parties is legitimate. To achieve consensus or
acceptance, continuous interaction among all parties is
critical. Through interaction, objectives emerge and be-
come legitimized through continuous modification. Sys-
tems cannot be designed in the usual sense, but emerge
through social interaction. The mechanism of prototyp-
ing or evolutionary learning from interaction with par-
tial implementations is the way technology becomes
embedded into the social perception and sense-making
process.
Interpretation
Key Actors: Users and the systems developer. Users are
the organizational agents who interpret and make sense
of their surroundings. The systems developer is the
change agent who helps users make sense of the new
system and its environment.
Nurrafive: Information systems development creates
new meaning. The effectiveness of the information sys-
tem rests on its ability to help users better understand
the currently accepted conventions and meanings. In-
formation systems development proceeds through the
application of symbolic interactionism, which suggests
that organizational actors interpret system objectives
and specifications and act according to the meaning
their interpretation provides for them. Mead [78, p. 781
captures the essence of symbolic interactionism when
he writes “Language does not simply symbolize a situa-
tion or object which is already there in advance; it
makes possible the existence or appearance of that situ-
ation or object, for it is part of the mechanism whereby
that situation or object is created.”
Plot: None manifest. As the social environment is un-
der continuous evolution, no particular rational expla-
nations can be provided to ‘explain’ organizational
reality.
Assumptions: The epistemology is that of anti-positiv-
ism reflecting the belief that the search for causal, em-
pirical explanations for social phenomena is misguided
and should be replaced by sense-making. The ontology
is that of nominalism in that reality is not a given,
immutable “out there,” but is socially constructed. It is
the product of the human mind. Social relativism is the
paradigm adopted for understanding social phenomena
and is primarily involved in explaining the social world
from the viewpoint of the organizational agents who
directly take part in the social process of reality con-
struction.
Analysis and Discussion
The developer-as-facilitator story focuses on the com-
plexity of reality which is by its very nature, confusing.
It does not try to conceal this complexity by pretending
that there is an underlying order that can be captured
in simplifying models. Reality is socially constructed
and the product of continual social interaction. The
involvement in the social interaction produces unique
experiential knowledge. The emerging meanings are a
function of experience which is always changing and
never quite the same for two people. The uniqueness
and idiosyncratic nature of each situation does not al-
low it to be handled only by applying universal laws
and principles. There is a shift from the rigorous scien-
tific paradigm of prediction by expanatory laws to in-
terpretative accounts of experiences. The concept of
rationality does not play any significant role here. De-
velopers act rationally if they simply accept prevailing
attitudes and values, remain consistent with general
opinion, and implement changes in a way that does not
threaten social harmony.
As this story emphasizes the complexity of systems
development, it doubts the efficacy of objective and
rigorous methods and tools. Instead, it favors an ap-
proach to systems development that facilitates the
learning of all who are concerned and affected. This
implies a switch in the role of the developer from one
of system expert to facilitator who helps to stimulate
reflection, cooperation, and experiential learning. In
practice, the social relativist approach seeks to provide
specific tools that facilitator at his or her discretion may
use to support the project group interaction. Examples
are diary keeping, various forms of mappings (histori-
cal, diagnostic, ecological, and virtual [XI]), special
group pedagogy, use of metaphors to stimulate mental
shifts (breakthrough by breakdown [70], etc. These tools
can be used by the organizational actors for exploring,
learning, increasing awareness, inventing solutions to
problems, and undertaking action [%I. This is accom-
panied by the belief that it is not so much the result of
systems development that is important, but the way it
is achieved. Hence it intrinsically favors strong partici-
pation. The kind of systems that this story produces
stimulate creativity and sense making. The use of crea-
tivity is not seen as a means to achieve any specific or
wider benefits. The local or global effects of ISD, good
or bad, are not a conscious concern. This story does not
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 20 Communications of the ACM 1205
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
support the notion of a political center that attempts to
strike a balance between individual and collective in-
terests. Consequently, consensus is not viewed as a so-
cial means to maintain interest-based coalitions or for
achieving an overall global optimum to which individ-
uals interests are subordinate.
The story suggests that all is relative; acceptance is
the only thing that matters. Social interaction is crucial
for acceptance but there is no way to distinguish be-
tween valid and fallacious (inauthentic, manipulative)
consensus (what Habermas [39], terms “naive consen-
sus”). Because of its relativist stance, it is completely
uncritical of the potential dysfunctional side effects of
using particular tools and techniques for ISD. Different
products of systems development are simply viewed as
the result of different socially constructed realities.
Note how this differs from the next two stories.
STORY III: THE ANALYST AS LABOR PARTISAN
Systems Development as Dialectic Materialism
The third story is also a fairly recent reaction to the
first (cf. [16, 30, 47, 58, 921). It differs from the second
by postulating that a fundamental social conflict is en-
demic: to society; yet it agrees with the first in that
there is an objective economic reality. The conflict al-
legedly exists between the interests of those who own
the sources of production (shareholders of the organiza-
tion) and labor (cf. [IS]). Economic reality is explained
in ter:ms of the interdependent unfolding of the conflict
between these two social classes. The conflict results
from the objective condition of private ownership and
contends that the invention of economic laws is a ploy
by the owners of the sources of production to make
the working class believe that there is no alternative
way to arrange working conditions. Management has
sided with the owners and are mere agents of their
interests [34].
In this story, the developer is faced with a choice: to
side with management and become their agent, or join
the interests of labor. In the first case, the systems
would rationalize the interests of management and the
owners. In this case, the developer will direct systems
rationalization against the workers’ interests by affect-
ing the intensity of work, changing the instruments of
work, or replacing the object of work altogether. Sys-
tems development in the interest of management in-
creases intensity of work by using computers to direct
the work flow or supervise workers, for instance by
issuing detailed, optimally sequenced work schedules
[30], monitoring machine operations (keystroke count-
ing, measuring idle time), etc. An example of changing
the instruments or tools of work is the replacement of
typevvriters by word processors. An example of where
the object of work has been replaced is in the watch
industry where integrated circuits replaced mechanical
watch movements. In all these cases worker interests
are jeopardized because of loss of jobs, decreased de-
pend’ence of management on labor, deskilling of jobs by
increased specialization or standardization, and so forth.
Systems developers can choose, however, io side
with the workers, designing systems which help their
interests. In this case, they should use technology to
enhance labor’s traditional skills and craftmanship, at-
tempting to make work both more rewarding-econom-
ically and psychologically-and deliver a better prod-
uct. There may also be productivity gains, but these
must benefit the worker: by shorter work weeks, more
time spent on planning and organizing the creative part
of their work, time for continuing education, more au-
tonomy, and better wages. The systems developer
needs to avoid replacing labor by capital through auto-
mation. Technology could also help workers to manage
their own productive concerns-the interest of those
who manage and those who do the productive work
would then coincide.
Trade union-led projects in Scandinavia such as
DEMOS [30] and UTOPIA [47] are instances where
systems development was placed in the hands of the
workers.’ No matter which role the systems developer
chooses, the source of system objectives is the collec-
tive interest of the conflicting classes: profits for the
owners or improvement of working conditions for la-
bor. From a radical structuralist perspective, choosing
the former leads to the exploitation of the common
man. Thus, legitimate system objectives enhance the
lot of the workers who must earn a living through their
labor.
Interpretation
Key Actors: Two classes [owners and labor), manage-
ment, and the systems developer. The two antagonistic
classes, the owners of the productive resources and la-
bor, are engaged in a classic struggle. The owners be-
come the beneficiaries of information systems while la-
bor becomes the victim of system rationalization.
Management acts as the agent of the owners. The sys-
tems developer chooses between being an agent for
management or labor.
Narrative: Information systems are developed to sup-
port managerial control. System objectives reflect the
desire to support the interests of the owners at the
expense of the interests of labor. Information systems
development is embedded in the historical unfolding of
class struggle-it either strengthens the side of the
owners (ruling class) or their opponents, labor. The un-
derlying hypothesis, that of dialectic materialism, sug-
gests that the material economic conditions are funda-
mental for the shaping of class interests. The social
conflict between the two classes follows the pattern of
the dialectical triad: exploitation of one class by the
other, revolt, and synthesis. The synthesis takes the
form of a new political order and ideology. Information
systems development is part of the rationalizing forces
by which the owner class exploits labor.
’ Currently the approach does not make it clear how system development
could help those who are not employed at all or those who live in countries
that have not developed along the lines of the Scandinavian democracies.
(This point also applies to the other paradigms.)
1206 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
Plot: The ideal of evolution from slavery through feu-
dalism and capitalist market economy to a collectively
planned and managed economy. The purpose of sys-
tems development should be to help labor overcome
the constraints of capitalism by supporting labor activ-
ism.
Assumptions: The epistemology is that of positivism in
the specific form of a materialist view of history and
society. The ontology is that of realism reflecting the
belief in a preexisting empirical reality. The paradigm
is that of radical structuralism reflecting a critique of
the status quo with the aim of providing the rationale
for radical change.
Analysis and Discussion
The developer-as-labor-partisan story focuses on the
claim that systems development intervenes in the con-
flict between social classes for prestige, power, and re-
sources. Conflict is seen as endemic to society and gen-
erally follows a predictable pattern that can be
discerned by analyzing vested social interests and the
structures and relationship supporting them. An exam-
ple of this is the effects of rationalization on workers.
The story deliberately exhorts the developer to become
an advocate of labor to redress the balance of power
between management and labor as the only morally
acceptable course of action. The story promotes the in-
sight that all knowledge relates to human interests and
thus a neutral science is impossible (cf. [32]). Culture,
knowledge, and human interests are seen as intimately
related. Cultural norms and values are revealed to be
subtle, but nevertheless effective mechanisms of behav-
ior control. They are a ploy to legitimize managerial
goals and turn workers into faithful servants of the rul-
ing elite.
As a consequence, user resistance is seen as positive
because it is a sign of labor becoming aware of its col-
lective interest which in turn is a prerequisite for social
progress. The story motivates the developer to seek co-
operation with labor and their representatives. It advo-
cates a participative approach but only with one
party-labor. Only system objectives that evolve from
the cooperation between labor and the developer are
considered legitimate. This is thought to lead to systems
that emphasize enhancement of craftmanship and
working conditions, and a higher quality of products for
the consumer (although possibly at a higher price). Ra-
tionality is tied to the interests of labor. Only system
objectives, tools, and methods that enhance the posi-
tion of labor and thereby lead to social progress are
considered rational.
The story leads to a number of potentially dysfunc-
tional consequences. It embraces the notion of activism
(in which it is more important to change the world than
to interpret it) which reduces the possibility of a justi-
fied consensus where cooperation instead of conflict is
sought. It is uncritical of the effects of social differentia-
tion introduced by organizing class interests into
unions or other forms of worker organization (political
parties and the like); such effects are the manipulation
of the constituency by their leaders, and the effects of
“co-optation” and relative isolation of the leaders who
often become involved in different social spheres than
their constituency. Ehn [28, p. 3581 also notes the de-
marcation disputes that new technology creates be-
tween different professional groups and trade union ju-
risdictions: “. . , the lack of trade union cooperation, not
the technology, not the newspaper owners, suppliers,
may ironically become the decisive factor frustrating
the dream of UTOPIA.” That the UTOPIA team first
contacted the graphics worker union “made the other
unions, [whether] on good grounds or not, critical to-
wards UTOPIA, and thus frustrated the dream of a joint
design.”
Moreover, this story has a tendency to oversimplify:
for example, there are only two parties, there is no
conflict between workers and their representatives,
there is a homogeneous management/owner class, and
so on. It also sees the lack of conflict as undesirable in
that it reinforces the status quo, except when the class-
less society is reached as the end product of the strug-
gle. It assumes there are immutable nature-like laws
that determine the future of society. This leads to the
so-called fallacy of historicism where all events are
seen in terms of an inevitable, evolutionary conflict.
STORY IV: THE ANALYST AS EMANCIPATOR
OR SOCIAL THERAPIST
Systems Development as Emancipation through
Rational Discourse
The last story is a reaction to the previous three.
Whereas the others can be observed in actual systems
development cases, this story is hypothetical to a large
degree in that it has been constructed from theory [65,
67, 68, 851. Yet a number of individuals have noted its
attractiveness and claim to have incorporated some of
its principles in their systems development approaches
[20, 731. Through information systems development, or-
ganizational life is changed, but the rationality of this
change is heavily constrained by social influences
which channel the values, norms, and perceptions of
all participants. Through many forms of communica-
tion, shared meanings evolve into a complex culture
that cannot be reduced to a bipolar conflict among two
principal ideologies. There are two societal arenas of
human action. One is the realm of work where people
extract their sources of livelihood. The second is con-
nected to the medium of language use for the purpose of
establishing mutual understanding (as in the second
story) and engaging in emancipatory discourse. The
concepts of work, mutual understanding, and emanci-
pation are the three fundamental domains around
which society and other forms of social organization are
arranged. They are also the domains where knowledge
needs to be acquired, and each domain is related to
different types of knowledge. Habermas [38] terms
these types “knowledge interests.”
Work is the first domain and it is related to the
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1207
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
knowXedge interest of technical control of natural ob-
jects, forces (weather, gravity, temperature, etc.), and
people (as in coordinating the movements of a work
force). It is a unique characteristic of the human being
to seek knowledge to exercise better control over na-
ture and people and thereby rationalize work [%, 971.
Habermas refers to this as the technical knowledge in-
terest (TKI), and it :is aimed at overcoming natural and
social obstacles to obtaining products and services for
the continued maintenance and reproduction of the hu-
man species. The principal means by which the TKI is
realiz’ed is through the applied physical sciences. They
are characterized by the dominance of instrumental
reasoning, or adopting positivism as the basis for check-
ing the validity of knowledge claims. Information sys-
tems {are an important resource for achieving the TKI.
The first story suggests how this can be done. However,
information systems play an equally important role in
the realization of two other knowledge interests, mu-
tual understanding and emancipation.
The knowledge interest in mutual understanding is
aimed at improving the understanding of one’s culture,
one’s own psyche, and the psyches of those with whom
we interact (i.e., kin, friends, enemies). As opposed to
the engineering sciences which serve primarily the
TKI, the cultural sciences (history, literature, philoso-
phy, psychoanalysis, etc.) serve the interest in mutual
understanding. As mutual understanding in the social
world is problematic, hermeneutics has evolved to help
with the difficulties of interpretation. Hermeneutics
comprises the study of principles that can be applied to
make sense of situations and texts that are difficult to
interpret because no established meanings apply. An
example of a hermeneutic process is the way in which
a court interprets the law to deal with a new case in a
way which is consistent with prior rulings. In this story,
the developer is faced with a hermeneutic issue when
interpreting system requirements because the existing
system is like an alien text that needs to be read [12].
Further, ED poses a hermeneutic issue to the user in
that it intervenes in the established modes of sense
making and communication.
The knowledge interest in mutual understanding on
its own lacks a critical perspective for two reasons:
(1) It does not guard against distorted interpretations.
Such distortions can arise from biases such as ideology
and the limits of language use because “our implicit
belie:6 and assumptions cannot all be made explicit”
[99, pQ 321; (2) It does not necessarily lead to action
against unjustifiable situations. Hermeneutics in this
case helps in understanding the limitations and barriers
to the improvement of the quality of the human condi-
tion in the direction of maximal freedom from physio-
logical needs and social domination, The removal of
these barriers is achieved through the historical process
of emancipation. This leads to the third knowledge in-
terest whose purpose is the establishment of truth and
justice as the norm to regulate all human affairs-from
the family to organizations, government and interna-
tional relations. The emancipatory knowledge interest
is concerned with social criticism and applications of
the TKI and shared understandings to remove all un-
warranted contraints to social freedom and personal
growth.
In pursuing the knowledge interest in emancipation,
the system developer elicits (through interaction) a
shared understanding of the many obstacles to human
communication. The developer needs to acquire an ap-
preciation (insider knowledge) of the different view-
points and existential situations of the different stake-
holder groupings. But this cannot be done by external
objective observation, genuine participation is crucial,
Obstacles, however, abound. The developer needs to
consider the following typical obstacles to human com-
munication throughout systems development:
4.
5.
Authority and illegitimate power-they create
anxieties and cause people to distort or withhold
information in order to protect themselves.
Peer opinion pressure (“group think”)-it creates
tunnel vision for the sake of loyalty, reducing the
validity of judgments by suppressing possible valid-
ity checks through criticism.
Time, space, and resource limitations they prevent
universal access to knowledge even though in prin-
ciple it is available. This includes the common situa-
tion that knowledgeable people remain silent due to
lack of motivation to participate because of work
overload or the socially created need to withhold
important information unless it is to one’s advantage
to engage in a debate.
Social differentiation-differences in the level of ed-
ucation, specialization and personal values and be-
liefs increase the risk of misunderstanding.
The bias and limitation of language use–distort per-
ceptions and lead to narrow problem definitions
through jargon and cognitive anchoring.
All of these create difficulties of understanding the rel-
evance and implications of design issues across social
and organizational boundaries. Legitimate system ob-
jectives emerge from a free and open discussion that
leads to a shared understanding and does not suffer
from the harmful effects of these barriers.
In order to illustrate the tenets of this story more
clearly, it is helpful to envisage some key aspects of
how systems might appear if their development follows
this story. All systems development would proceed
with the three knowledge interests in mind. Systems
would have features to support the technical knowl-
edge interest and these would be similar to those devel-
oped under the functionalist influence. Other features
would support the creation of shared meanings and re-
flect the knowledge interest in mutual understanding.
This is similar to systems inspired by social relativism.
Finally, there would be a comprehensive set of features
to support emancipatory discourse. This means that in-
formation systems are developed that facili-tate the
widest possible debate of organizational problems such
that truly shared objectives could be agreed upon as
well as policies for achieving them. Such a debate, free
1208 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
of all social pressure, which has the best chance to cor-
rect psychological distortions due to individual bias, is
called a rational discourse or an ideal speech situation.
The goal of information systems is to help with the
institutionalization of an ideal speech situation which
in turn validates a consensus about system objectives
and modes of design and implementation. The ideal
speech situation would legitimate a moving balance be-
tween the fundamental three objectives of information
systems development, namely improved technical con-
trol, better mutual understanding and continued eman-
cipation from unwarranted social constraints and
psychological compulsions.
Interpretation
Key Actors: Stakeholders and the systems developer.
The stakeholders are a diverse group of individuals in-
cluding customers, labor, and their representatives, het-
erogeneous levels of management, and the owners of
the productive resources. They exist within a complex,
intertwined set of social relationships and interactions.
The stakeholders take part in communicative action.
The systems developer acts as a social therapist and
emancipator in an attempt to draw together, in open
discussion, the various stakeholders.
Narrative: Information systems are developed to re-
move distorting influences and other barriers to ra-
tional discourse. Systems development is governed by
the three knowledge interests. The technical knowl-
edge interest directs the developer to be sensitive to
issues associated with effective and efficient manage-
ment of the system project. The interest in mutual un-
derstanding directs the developer to apply the princi-
ples of hermeneutics, which examine the rules of
language use and other practices by which we improve
comprehensibility and mutual understanding, remove
misunderstandings, and disagreement or other obstacles
to human communication [7g]. The knowledge interest
in emancipation directs the developer to structure sys-
tems development to reflect the principles of rational
discourse.
Plot: The ideal of emancipation. Information systems
should lead to an emancipation from all unwarranted
constraints and compulsions (e.g., psychological, physi-
cal, and social) toward a state of justice, freedom, and
material well-being for all.
Assumptions: The epistemology adopted in this story is
of two types: positivism for knowledge interests in tech-
nical control (which includes both nature and man);
and anti-positivism for knowledge interests in mutual
understanding and emancipation. The ontology adopted
is also of two types: realism for technical interests and
nominalism or social constructivism for mutual under-
standing and emancipation of interests. The adopted
paradigm is that of neohumanism which reflects the
desire to improve the existence of organizational actors
(through their emancipation) by developing information
systems that support a rational discourse.
Analysis and Discussion
The story of developer-as-emancipator focuses on hu-
man potential and how it is threatened by ideology,
power, and other distorting and unwarranted con-
straints. In distinction to the first story, it emphasizes
what could be rather than what is. This story adds to
the notion of instrumental rationality (in affairs associ-
ated with the TKI) and communicative rationality (in
affairs governed by the knowledge interest in mutual
understanding) the notion of discoursive or emancipa-
tory rationality. It emphasizes the use of human reason
to both recognize deficiencies in the conditions of hu-
man existence and to suggest improvements. Such
emancipation is nurtured in the arena of a rational dis-
course where the intelligibility, veracity, truthfulness,
and appropriateness of all arguments are checked
through maximal criticism. Checks and balances on in-
dividual opinions are needed to guard against unwar-
ranted constraints and biases to allow undistorted com-
munication to occur, which means that both the
physical and social barriers to a rational discourse need
to be identified and removed for maximal criticism to
occur. The concept of rational discourse applies both to
the development and use of information systems [67].
Rational discourse is an ideal that cannot be fully
implemented. By the use or development of informa-
tion systems some, but not all, of the barriers to a ra-
tional discourse could be mitigated. For example:
(1) data modeling could correct some of the bias and
distortion by semantic integrity checks; (2) proper orga-
nization of the system development process could pro-
vide rational motivations to participate, share and elicit
missing information; (3) networks could help to over-
come the limitations of time and space; (4) conferencing
systems could motivate people to contribute their ex-
pertise by advertising agendas and making it easy to
append comments and suggestions; (5) highly interac-
tive, object oriented designs could help to overcome
educational differences; and (6) proper security controls
could protect individual rights through anonymity and
motivate people to communicate criticisms and radical
change proposals by shielding them from the threats of
the powerful.
This story seems appealing because it captures many
positive features of the previous stories and adds the
important notion of emancipation. However, while the-
oretically strong, it is difficult to see how the story
actually works in practice. The story is normative with-
out providing clear details on how it could be imple-
mented. For example, it is not clear how notions like
the systems development life cycle should be modified
to accommodate the three knowledge interests; what
tools and techniques should be developed to apply the
concept of rational discourse to systems development;
how to broaden the methods for integrity checking to
guard against the numerous forms of fallacious reason-
ing; and so forth. A more fundamental issue is whether
people would be willing and able to radically change
October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1209
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Bryan
Highlight
Articles
their behavior to fit the ideal of rational discourse. Nor
is it clear that people would be motivated to participate
in the debate or wish to take part if given the option.
More’over, one must question the implicit assumption
in the story that there are no natural limits to human
potential, that through emancipation we can overcome
the psychological and social constraints on human ca-
pabihties which have been inherited from the distort-
ing influences of the past. It is difficult to see how the
goal of a society free of ideology and domination can be
realized. One must also question the assumption that
technological progress will be sufficiently powerful to
overc,ome the significant physical constraints confront-
ing the emancipation of all.
Table I summarizes and highlights the salient details
of the paradigms.
THE TWO EXAMPLES REVISITED
The stories provide a relatively simple and straightfor-
ward way of outlining the possibility of alternative con-
ceptions about IS development. We have suggested four
stories, but there could be more. The importance, how-
ever, lies not so much in the fact that there are four (or
more) stories, but rather that alternative conceptions of
ISD which differ in very fundamental and striking ways
exist. It is specifically because of these fundamental
differences (largely based on differences in adopted as-
sumptions), that the systems produced will also differ.
This can be noted in the two introductory examples
presented earlier. The systems development approach
taken in each case builds on a set of core assumptions
which differ from those of the functionalist approach.
Differences can be observed in both the development
process, and in the developed system.
Development Process Differences
Process differences relate to the decisions made during
systems development. In the typesetting example, the
UTOPIA project team made a conscious decision to re-
tain and enhance the craft, not to include management
representatives, and not to be bound by the then-
available page layout technology. The rationale for
these decisions can be traced back to the paradigmatic
assumptions that guided the development team. For ex-
ample, the assumption that conflict is endemic to soci-
ety in the radical structuralist paradigm, motivated the
project team to focus on the conflict between typeset-
ters and management. The denial of the possibility of
the system developer being a neutral expert committed
them to bolstering the position of the worker in the
perceived social struggle and to enhancing the craft of
the typesetters. This led to an emphasis on union lead-
ership that put control of systems developmlent in the
hands of a homogeneous group. It also heightened the
sensitivity to the effects of ideological, managerial bias
in that the existing typesetting systems would make the
craft largely redundant thereby enhancing management
control over workers. Moreover, the UTOPIA project
team believed the ideological bias was manifest in the
components of the technology itself: the social neutral-
ity of technology was denied. As Kubicek notes: “This
approach is based on the assumption that ElDP-knowl-
edge is not impartial to the interests of capit.al and labor
but rather biased by the perspective of capital and man-
agement” [55, p. 91. If available technology had limita-
tions that would not allow the enhancement of the
craft’s future, then it would not be in the interest of the
workers to accept existing technology as a design con-
straint. In the words of Ehn et al.: “The trad.e unions’
TABLE 1. Summary of the Four Paradigms
Functionalism Expert or
Platonic
Philosopher
King
Social Catalyst or
Relativism Facilitator
Radical Warrior
Structuralism far Social
Progress
or Partisan
Systemidwebpment pro&ds Elements used fn defining IS Examples
From without, by application of formal People, hardware, software, rules !3ructured
concepts through planned intervention (organizational procedures) as physical analysis,
with rationalistic tools and methods or formal, objective entities infonation
engineering
From within, by improving subjective Subjectivity of meanings, symbolic Ethnographic
understanding and cultural sensitivity structures affecting evolution of sense, approaches,
through adapting to internal forces of making and sharing of meanings, FLORENCE
evolutionary social change metaphors project
From without, by raising ideological People, hardware, software, rules Trade-union projects
Neohumanism Emancipator From within, by improving human People, hardware, software, rules Critical social 1210 Communications of fhe ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Bryan Bryan Bryan ability . . . is limited in an increasing number of situa- In the engine maintenance case, influence from the Developed System Differences ‘On the other hand, several characteristics in this case were consistent with “These eight features are derived from an analysis of the literature dealing 1. 2.
3.
4. 6.
7.
8.
Articles Technology architecture refers to the way in which Tables II and III provide a comparison of the systems October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 1211 Articles Fmtionalism
TABLE II. The UTOPIA Project
Technology Architecture
Radical st~~~turalism
Link word processors of writers/editors with typesetting soft- Link word processors of writers/editors with file servers of Kind of Information Flows
From editors/writers to machines; productivity controls Having typesetters process work of writers/editors before me- Control of Users
Productivity controls for writers/editors; visual quality control Typesetters remain in control of the quality of their Iproduct Technical experts.
Control of Systems Development
Union officials and workers, against prevailing technology Access to Information
Writers/editors only. Typesetters and writers/editors.
Editors and visual quality control partly eliminated. Customers Typesetters; quality control according to professional typeset- Training
Basic computer skills and typesetting skills for writers/editors. New typesetting and computer skills for typesetters.
Raison d’Etre
Maximize cost savings, reduce production time, and eliminate Enhance traditional typesetting craft, making them more pro- parison is hypothetical,” but nevertheless expresses ” Note that the ideal of conducting a controlled experiment involving the here is not only to make money, but to transfer the Mixing of Influences 1212 Cominunications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10 Articles TABLE III. SAS Engine Maintenance System
social Relativism/Neehumanism
Technology Architecture Automated measurement and sensing of engine components Determination of maintenance needs by skilled mechanics Kind of information Flows
Instructions from system to mechanics (users) regarding what User/mechanic describes the problem to the system, and Control of Users Mechanic is controlled by system in terms of what is Mechanic is in control, and thereby feels responsible for the Control of Systems Development Technology experts. Mechanics and their union representatives in co-operation with Access to Information Mechanics and management. Mechanics and management.
Error Handling
Detection of problems by statistical reports (e.g., productivity Setter quality control by the mechanics who feel responsible Training Limited to the operation of the maintenance system. Begins with the discussion of feelings and attitudes to Raison d’Etre Expert systems to replace human judgments, which are seen System for experts whose judgments are seen to be the key true requirements as is evident from McMenamin and rigidity of the functionalist assumption of modeling As is evident from the discussion of the typesetting CONCLUSIONS October 1989 Volume 32 Number 10
vc,vucr lJV.7 ““‘UII‘C JL ‘Vl*,,,“5, I”
Communications of the ACM 1213 Articles
had to rely solely on the inventiveness of creative prac- Moreover, a documentation of the assumptions un- set of philosophical assumptions which each embraces Acknowledgments. This article has benefitted from REFERENCES
For the researcher, these systems development para- 1,
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Alexander, J., Ed. Neofunctionalism. Sage Publications, Beverly 7.
7. 8.
9.
10,
Second, although it was not possible to relate systems 11.
11. 12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
Third, the identification of paradigms along with the
I2 R e l a t i n g s y s t e m s d e v e l o p m e n t m e t h o d o l o g i e s t o p a r a d i g m s i s a c o m p l i c a t e d 17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
Bariff, M. and Ginzberg, M. MIS and the behavioural sciences. Data 1214 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Number I0 Articles 2 4 . C o u g e r , J . D . , C o l t e r , M . , a n d K n a p p , R . A d v a n c e d S y s t e m s D e v e l o p – 25. Dagwell, R. and Weber, R. System designers’ user models: A com- 26. Davis, G. and Olson, M. Management Information Systems: Conceptual 27. DeMarco, T. Structured Analysis and System Specification. Yourdon 28. Ehn, P. Work-Oriented Design of Computer Artifacts. Arbetslivs- 29. E h n , P . , K y n g , M . , a n d S u n d b l a d , Y . T h e U T O P I A P r o j e c t : O n 30. Ehn, P. and Sandberg, A. Local union influence on technology and 31. Faia, M. Dynamic Functionalism: Strategy and Tactics. Cambridge 32. Fay, B. Social Theory and PoZificaZ Practice. George Allen and Unwin, 3 3 . G a n e , C . a n d S a r s o n , T . S t r u c t u r e d S y s f e m s A n a l y s i s : T o o l s a n d T e c h – 3 4 . Garfinkel, H. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Prentice-Hall, Englewood 3 5 . Goldkuhl, G., and Lyytinen, K. A language action view of informa- 36. Griethuysen, V., Ed. Concepts and Terminology of the Conceptual 3 7 . Gutting, G., Ed., Paradigms and Revolutions. University of Notre 3 8 . Habermas, J. Theory and Practice. Heinemann, London, 1974. Reason and the Rationalization of Society Beacon Press, Boston, 1984. Comput. 17, 10 (Oct. 1984), 263-273. Man’s vision of man as an integral part of the system design pro- 4 % Hirschheim, R. Information systems epistemology: An historical ti. Hirschheim, R. and Klein, H. Paradigms and methodologies: An I’z, Hirschheim, R., Klein, H. and Newman, M. A social action perspec- &. Hopper, T. and Powell, A. Making sense of research into the organ- 9:. t loward, R. UTOPIA: Where workers craft new technology. Tech. 14. Jackson, M. System Development. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, ti Keen, P. Information systems and organizational change. Commun. m Klein, H. and Hirschheim, R. Issues and approaches to appraising 4 1 hlein, H. and Hirschheim, R. Fundamental issues of decision sup- & E;lein, H. and Hirschheim, R. Social change and the future of infor- 48 hlcin, H. and Lyytinen, K. The poverty of scientism in information 54. Kling, R. Social analyses of computing: Theoretical perspectives in 55. Kubicek, H. User participation in systems design: Some questions 56. Kuhn, T. The Sfructure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. University of 57. Kumar, K. and Welke, R. Implementation failure and system devel- 58. Kyng, M. and Ehn, P. STARDUST memories: Scandinavian tradi- 59. Lanzara, G. and Mathiassen, L. Mapping situations within a system 60. Laudan, L. Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific 61. Lehtinen, E. and Lyytinen, K. Action based model of information 62. Lessnoff, M. The Strucfure of Social Science. George Allen and 63. Lucas, H. Implementation: The Key to Successful Information Systems. 64. Lundberg, M., Goldkuhl, G. and Nissen, N. Information Systems De- 65. Lyytinen, K. Critical Social Theory and Information Systems-A 66. Lyytinen, K. A taxonomic perspective of information systems de- 67. Lyytinen, K. and Hirschheim, R. Information systems as rational 68. Lyytinen, K. and Klein, H. The critical theory of Jurgen Habermas 69. Lyytinen, K. and Lehtinen, E. On information modeling through 70. Madsen, M. Breakthrough by breakdown. In Znformation Systems 71. Markus, M.L. Power, politics and MIS implementation. Commun. 72. Markus, M.L. Systems in Organizations: Bugs and Features. Pitman, 73. Mathiassen, L., and Bogh-Anderson, P. Systems development and 74. Mathiassen, L., Rolskov, B. and Vedel, E. Regulating the use of EDP 7 5 . M c C a r t h y , T . T h e C r i t i c a l T h e o r y o f Jurgen H a b e r m a s . M I T P r e s s , 76. McGregor, D. The Human Side of Enterprise. McGraw-Hill, New 77. McMenamin, S. and Palmer, J. Essential Systems Analysis. Yourdon 78. Mead, G. Mind, SeZf and Society. University of Chicago Press, Chi- 79. Misgeld, D., Discourse and conversation: The theory of communi- 80. Mitroff, I. Stakeholders of the Organizationa Mind. Jossey-Bass, San 81. Mumford, E. Designing Human Systems For New Technology: The ~abrr 2989 Volume 32 Number 10 Communications of the ACM 121s 82. Naumann, J. and Jenkins, M., Prototyping: The new paradigm for 83. Newman, M. Managerial access to information: Strategies for pre- 84. Newman, M. and Rosenberg, D. Systems analysts and the politics of 85. Ngwenyama, 0. Fundamental issues of knowledge acquisition: To- 86. Olle, T. W., Sol, H., and Verrijn-Stuart, A. Eds. Information Systems CR Categories and Subject Descriptors: H.l.O [Models and Princi- General Terms: Design, Human Factors tives, value conflicts, and knowledge interests in systems developme I. 87. Olle, T. W., Sol, H. and Tully, C. Eds. Znformafion Sysfems Design 8 8 . Olle, T . W . , S o l , H . a n d V e r r i j n – S t u a r t , A . , E d s . I n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s A B O U T T H E A U T H O R S :
89. Pettigrew, A. The Polifics of Organizational Decision Making. 90. Quine, W. and Ullian, J. The Web of Belief. Random House, New 91. Reason, P. and Rowan, J., Eds. Human Inquiry: A Sourcebook of New 92, Sandberg, A. Socio-technical design, trade union strategies and ac- 93. Silverman, D. The Theory of Organizafions. Heinemann, London, RUDY HIRSCHHEIM is an associate professor of information 94. Teichroew, D. and David, G., Eds. System Description Methodologies. 95. Van Maanen, J. Reclaiming qualitative methods for organizational 96. Vitalari, N. and Dickson, G. Problem solving for effective systems 97. Weber, M. The Profesfanf Efhic and the Spirif of Capifalism. Allen 98. Weinberg, V. Strucfured Analysis. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, HEINZ K. KLEIN is an associate professor of information sys- 9 9 . W i n o g r a d , T . a n d F l o r e s , F . U n d e r s t a n d i n g C o m p u t e r s a n d C o g n i t i o n . 1 0 0 . W o o d – H a r p e r , A . T . , Antill, L . , a n d Avison, D . I n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s 103. Yourdon, E. Managing fhe Systems Life Cycle: A Software Development Permission to copy without fee all or part of this material is granted Even a single use of a CALGO algorithm will save many times the cost Collected Algorithms Editor-in-Chief Robert J. Renka Vol. I only, ISBN O-89791-017-6 M .
T disk and magnetic-tape versions are available sepa- Initial subscription, 4 volumes: includes casebound Vol. III only, ISBN O-89791-103-2 Please send all orders and inquiries to: Circle #IO5 on Reader Service Card
1 2 1 6 Communications of the ACM October 1989 Volume 32 Numblv 11 Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Accounting, Organizations and Society
j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / a o s Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and sustainability http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.aos.2014.12.003 � 2014 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. ⇑ Corresponding author. (M. Laine), rroberts@ucf.edu (R.W. Roberts), michelle.rodrigue@fsa. Charles H. Cho a,⇑, Matias Laine b, Robin W. Roberts c, Michelle Rodrigue d a b s t r a c t Sustainability discourse is becoming ubiquitous. Still, a significant gap persists between � 2014 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Introduction
The expansion of human societies and economic activi- meetings and global leader summits. Simultaneously, http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/j.aos.2014.12.003&domain=pdf http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.aos.2014.12.003 mailto:cho@essec.edu mailto:matias.laine@uta.fi mailto:rroberts@ucf.edu mailto:michelle.rodrigue@fsa.ulaval.ca mailto:michelle.rodrigue@fsa.ulaval.ca http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.aos.2014.12.003 http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/03613682 http://www.elsevier.com/locate/aos C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 79 organizations. Despite the influx of sustainability talk, the This tension between sustainability discourse and prac- In this paper, we argue that while sustainability report- 1 We contrast signaling theory and legitimacy theory understanding that mately improve corporate social and environmental stew- Our paper’s overarching purpose concerns the signifi- To illustrate the use of these theoretical concepts, we 2 The Arctic National Wildlife Refuge (ANWR) Bill (also known officially 80 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 and developing commercial energy resources and energy The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. The The role of sustainability disclosures in society
Corporate sustainability reporting spurred a substantial Legitimacy theory operates at a very broad level of anal- congruent with the most general norms of society. It is In the legitimacy-based research, corporations are char- Malsch (2013) views the growing standardization of The long-term time horizon [for addressing systemic C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 81 [rationally or pragmatically] for a firm or a country to As detailed by Malsch (2013; also Archel et al., 2011; After all, why would any corporation voluntarily wish Nevertheless, corporations are expected to provide Hypocrisy and façades in managing legitimacy and Hypocrisy as strategy
An organization’s management is compelled to develop management in a precarious moral position. If different As mentioned, Brunsson (2002, 2007) posits that organi- A logical question that follows from this reasoning is: Hypocrisy and its relation to organizational façades
These sub-structures are often placed on organizational 82 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 (Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008; Nystrom & Strabuck, First, a rational façade is a key to market legitimacy. Second, according to Abrahamson and Baumard (2008, Third, a reputation façade ‘‘displays accounting and rhe- attainment of an industry excellence award. Reputation Talk, decisions, and actions as tools of legitimacy and building Brunsson (1989) views talk, decisions, and actions as an In the model of [organized] hypocrisy talk, decisions Lipson (2007) explains that talk and decisions compen- C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 83 a selective set of an organization’s actions, an organiza- Potential consequences of organized hypocrisy and So, what might be the potential organizational conse- Legitimacy theory and the related notion of impression of its legitimacy within society (Merkl-Davies & Brennan, The preceding discussion can be undertaken without Certainly, the communication strategies used by corpo- 84 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 illusioned by organizational inconsistencies among talk, Conventional theories of voluntary disclosure, both sig- As Abrahamson and Baumard (2008, p. 451) purport, a efforts and reporting as essentially economic opportunities Of course, just because organized hypocrisy and organi- Applying organized hypocrisy and organizational façades to In analyzing corporate sustainability reporting practices We hold that corporations build a rational façade based While the demands of the market seem preeminent, C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 85 feature regularly in social discussions and political Shareholders are, however, not the only stakeholders of As discussed by Brunsson, the key to maintaining these 3 While our analysis is focused on social and environmental innovation actions within each façade and that their talk, decisions, Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and Located in Northern Alaska, the Arctic National Wildlife Because corporate actions that continue to promote oil Data and methods
Our period of interest is from 2004 to 2006 as it corre- 86 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 represent approximately 30% of the market share in the oil Our qualitative data consists of annual reports, sustain- to ensure the broadest coverage of disclosure possible. The Overall, despite the use of Atlas.ti software, the inter- 4 As an indication of the market share, we computed the 3-year average 5 The third major member of the Arctic Power lobbying group was Exxon, 6 The specialized website does not systematically archive all webpages rounds of interpretation and sense-making from different Findings: corporate talk, decisions, and actions
Rational façade: Business sustainability that oil and gas companies are sustainable from a core eco- At ConocoPhillips, we welcome the relentless challenge [ConocoPhillips, 2005a, p. 4, emphasis added]
Not only was 2003 one of our best years ever, but we [Chevron, 2003a, p. 2, emphasis added]
Relatedly, an essential element of the capitalist econ- We feel we are uniquely positioned for creating value http://www.archive.org C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 87 thing we do, and driven to deliver on our promises and [ConocoPhillips, 2004a, p. 7, emphases added]
In practice, the core business of our case companies is The company’s long-term competitive position, particu- [Chevron, 2005a, p. 26, emphases added]
Likewise, obtaining future drilling rights is related to Chevron makes contributions to political candidates [Chevron, 2004b, p. 38, emphases added]
[. . .], the U.S. employee political action committee [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 15, emphasis added]
In addition, ConocoPhillips offered general statements national energy policy. It first highlights a misalignment We also observed that the corporate actions are coupled These systems are aimed at achieving top operating [Chevron, 2004a, p. 15, emphasis added]
As the world’s need for oil and natural gas continues to [ConocoPhillips, 2005a, p. 4, emphases added] Progressive façade: Social and environmental innovation and In contemporary society, operating with a mere rational 88 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 goals, shareholder value, and future growth can be inte- Functioning in tandem with business units around the [ConocoPhillips, 2004a, p. 26, emphases added]
ChevronTexaco has a 125-year history of rising to chal- [Chevron, 2004a, p. 1, emphases added]
A progressive façade offers and emphasizes the poten- The first phase of this effort is a project to identify and [Chevron, 2004b, p. 58, emphasis added]
Systematic approaches produce positive ideas which Human Rights and Community Engagement – Our are planning to test implementation of the statement [Chevron, 2004c, emphases added]
We continue to build on our knowledge of sustainable [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 3, emphasis added]
In these disclosures we note that progressive talk and Recognizing there is always room for improvement, the [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 15, emphasis added] We posit that the progressive façade may serve to high- Advancing energy technologies in ways that are market- [Chevron, 2003b, p. 15, emphases added]
In a similar vein, we note actions regarding the develop- Since 1999, Chevron has invested approximately $60 [Chevron, 2004b, p. 48, emphases added] C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 89 Reputation façade: Social and environmental stewardship Baumard (2008) is labeled a reputation façade. We main- Protecting people and the environment is a core value for [Chevron, 2004b, p. 42, emphases added]
ConocoPhillips is committed to protecting the health and [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 23, emphases added]
Beyond these broad commitments toward environmen- Biodiversity is the life support system of the planet, and [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 36-37, emphases added]
Moreover, specific and more focused initiatives for bio- The tundra of the Alaska North Slope and northwest [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 30, emphases added] We view this talk as elevating biodiversity to be a pri- ANWR is, however, not only a matter of environmental Respecting the rights, traditions, livelihoods and cultural [Chevron, 2004b, p. 17, emphases added]
Respecting indigenous communities is an important part [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, p. 20, emphases added]
At the heart of these talks is an apparent commitment ConocoPhillips engages with residents surrounding our [ConocoPhillips, 2004b, inside cover page, emphases Collectively, this talk seems to highlight how oil and gas In addition to sustainability reports, we observe that 90 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 promoting ‘‘key fish and wildlife habitats conservation in Again, as is the case with progressive façade, the funda- Discussion
Brunsson (2007) argues that corporations engage in As a commercial enterprise, we have a responsibility to [Chevron, 2003b, emphases added]
We live and operate in a world of needs and demands. [ConocoPhillips, 2003, emphases added]
Under Brunsson’s reasoning (also Lipson, 2007), organi- Nevertheless, as suggested by Brunsson, organizations [. . .] we’re serious in our efforts to pursue promising [ConocoPhillips, 2005a] Furthermore, the incompatibility of reputation talk and ChevronTexaco’s case-by-case approach makes most [Chevron, 2005d, p. 42–43]
We are not claiming, however, that organizational talk, The organizational façades identified in this paper are Although we have presented the three façades as sepa- C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 91 limit the risk for organized hypocrisy to be exposed, and 7 It is also worth bearing in mind that work based on signaling or Conclusions
The possible role that corporate sustainability disclo- However, whether organized hypocrisy and organiza- champions and other individuals influence how voluntary As noted earlier in this paper, prior research has sought In addition, we believe that this stream of sustainability Malsch (2013) eloquently points out that corporations 92 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 context argued to force organizations and corporate man- Research in sustainability reporting can benefit from Hypocrisy can be seen as ‘a tribute that vice pays to vir- The theoretical and empirical illustration included in strategic tools for managing conflicting stakeholder Acknowledgments
The authors wish to thank Editor-in-Chief Christopher References
Abrahamson, E., & Baumard, P. (2008). What lies behind organizational http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0005 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 93 Adams, C. A. (2004). The ethical, social and environmental reporting Adams, C., & Narayanan, V. (2007). The ‘standardization’ of sustainability Aras, G., & Crowther, D. (2008). Corporate sustainability reporting: A Archel, P., Husillos, J., Larrinaga, C., & Spence, C. (2009). Social disclosure, Archel, P., Husillos, J., & Spence, C. (2011). The institutionalisation of Atlas.ti (2004). Atlas.ti 5.0 user’s guide and reference. Berlin: Thomas Muhr Ballou, B., Heitger, D. L., & Landes, C. E. (2006). The future of corporate Bansal, P., & Hoffman, A. J. (2012). The Oxford handbook of business and the Barnett, M. L. (2007). Stakeholder influence capacity and the variability of Bebbington, J., & Larrinaga, C. (2014). Accounting and sustainable Bebbington, J., Larrinaga, C., & Moneva, J. M. (2008). Corporate social Bebbington, J., Unerman, J., & O’Dwyer, B. (2014). Sustainability accounting Boiral, O. (2013). Sustainability reports as simulacra? A counter-account Brunsson, N. (1989). The organization of hypocrisy. Talk, decisions and Brunsson, N. (1990). Deciding for responsibility and legitimation: Brunsson, N. (1993). Ideas and actions: Justification and hypocrisy as Brunsson, N. (2002). The organization of hypocrisy. Oslo: Abstrakt Liber Brunsson, N. (2007). The consequences of decision-making. Oxford: Oxford Bryman, A., & Bell, E. (2003). Business research methods. New York: Oxford Campbell, J. L. (2007). Why would corporations behave in socially Chen, J. C., & Roberts, R. W. (2010). Towards a more integrated Chevron (2003a). Annual report. corporateregister.com>. corporateregister.com>. archive.org/web/web.php> Under 16.04.04. senate energy and natural resources committee and the senate Chevron (2005c). Current speeches: U.S. energy policy: A declaration of Chevron (2005d). Proxy statement. environmental disaster: A French case study of Total S.A’.s Erika and Cho, C. H., Freedman, M., & Patten, D. M. (2012). Corporate disclosure of Cho, C. H., Michelon, G., & Patten, D. M. (2012). Impression management Cho, C. H., Roberts, R. W., & Patten, D. M. (2010). The language of U.S. Christensen, L. T., Morsing, M., & Thyssen, O. (2013). CSR as aspirational Clarkson, P. M., Li, Y., Richardson, G. D., & Vasvari, F. P. (2008). Revisiting Collison, D. J. (2003). Corporate propaganda: Its implications for ConocoPhillips (2003). Our commitment to sustainable development. ConocoPhillips (2004a). Annual report. corporateregister.com>. metrics. report. environmental reporting: An Italian narrative. Accounting, Crane, A., Matten, D., & Spence, L. J. (2008). Corporate social responsibility. Deegan, C., & Blomquist, C. (2006). Stakeholder influence on corporate Dhaliwal, D. S., Radhakrishnan, S., Tsang, A., & Yang, Y. G. (2012). Elkington, J. (1997). Cannibals with forks. The Triple Bottom Line of 21st Gray, R. (2002). The social accounting project and Accounting Gray, R. (2010). Is accounting for sustainability actually accounting for Gray, R., Kouhy, R., & Lavers, S. (1995). Corporate social and Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change [IPCC] (2014). IPCC fifth Jackson, T. (2009). Prosperity without growth. London: Earthscan. reports. Social and Environmental Accounting Journal, 27(2), 8–11. philanthropy. Business Ethics: A European Review, 20(3), 267–279. sustainability in Finnish corporate disclosures 1987–2005. European Langley, A. (1999). Strategies for theorizing from process data. Academy of Lehman, G. (1999). Disclosing new worlds: A role for social and Levy, D. L. (1997). Environmental management as political sustainability. Lindblom, C. K. (1993). The implications of organizational legitimacy for Lipson, M. (2007). Peacekeeping: Organized hypocrisy? European Journal http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0025 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0025 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0025 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0045 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0045 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0060 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0060 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0060 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0065 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0065 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0465 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0465 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0085 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0085 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0085 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0105 http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0175 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0175 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0175 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0180 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0180 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0190 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0190 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0190 http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://www.archive.org/web/web.php http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0270 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0275 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0275 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0280 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0280 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0285 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0285 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0285 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0310 94 C.H. Cho et al. / Accounting, Organizations and Society 40 (2015) 78–94 Malsch, B. (2013). Politicizing the expertise of the accounting industry in Merkl-Davies, D. M., & Brennan, N. M. (2007). Discretionary disclosure Meyer, J. W., & Rowan, B. (1977). Institutionalized organizations: Formal Milne, M. J., & Gray, R. (2013). W(h)ither ecology? The triple bottom line, Milne, M., & Gray, R. (2007). Future prospects for corporate sustainability Milne, M., Tregidga, H., & Walton, S. (2009). Words not actions! The Mitchell, R. K., Agle, B. R., & Wood, D. J. (1997). Toward a theory of Neu, D., Warsame, H., & Pedwell, K. (1998). Managing public impressions: Nystrom, P. C., & Strabuck, W. H. (1984). Organizational façades. Academy Owen, D. L. (2008). Chronicles of wasted time? A personal reflection on O’Donovan, G. (2002). Environmental disclosures in the annual report: O’Dwyer, B. (2004). Qualitative data analysis: Illuminating a process for O’Dwyer, B., Unerman, J., & Hession, E. (2005). User needs in sustainability Parker, L. D. (2005). Social and environmental accountability research: A Patten, D. M. (2002). The relation between environmental performance Patten, D. M. (2012). White tigers, zoos and sustainability reporting: A Prasad, P., & Elmes, M. (2005). In the name of the practical: Unearthing Pulver, S. (2007). Making sense of corporate environmentalism: An Raworth, K. (2012). A safe and just space for humanity. Oxford: Oxfam. et al. (2009). A safe operating space for humanity. Nature, 461(7263), Rodrigue, M., Magnan, M., & Cho, C. H. (2013). Is environmental Simons, T. (2002). Behavioral integrity: The perceived alignment between Spar, D., & LaMure, L. (2003). The power of activism: Assessing the impact Spence, C. (2007). Social and environmental reporting and hegemonic Spence, C. (2009). Social accounting’s emancipatory potential. Critical Spence, C., Husillos, J., & Correa-Ruiz, C. (2010). Cargo cult science and the Suchman, M. C. (1995). Managing legitimacy: Strategic and institutional THOMAS. (2009). The Library of Congress. class contradictions at General Motors: 1917–1976. Accounting, Tregidga, H., Milne, M., & Kearins, K. (2014). (Re)presenting ‘sustainable Unerman, J., & Chapman, C. (2014). Editorial: Academic contributions to Van Bommel, K. (2014). Towards a legitimate compromise? An Yin, R. K. (2009). Case study research: Design and methods. Thousand Oaks: http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0320 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0320 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0320 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0340 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0340 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0340 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0345 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0345 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0345 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h9030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0380 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0380 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0380 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0395 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0400 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0400 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0400 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0410 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0410 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0410 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0415 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0415 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0415 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0425 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0425 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0435 http://thomas.loc.gov http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0440 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0440 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0440 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0445 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0445 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0455 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0455 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0455 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0460 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0361-3682(14)00104-4/h0460 Introduction Discussion
conscience and consciousness (organizational procedures) as physical led
through organized political ac:tion and or formal, objective entities put in the
or Social
Therapist
understanding and the rationality of (organizational procedures) as physical theory,
human action through emanc:ipation of or formal objective entities for the TKI; SAMPO
suppressed interests and liberation subjectivity of meanings and project
from unwarranted natural and social intersubjectivity of language use in
constraints other knowledge interests
Highlight
Highlight
Highlight
tions to a choice between yes or no to the purchase of
‘turn-key packages’ of technology and organization”
[39, p. 4391.
social relativist paradigm was evident in the belief that
mechanics’ subjective skills (involving experience and
judgment) were key in interpreting the symptoms of
wear and tear in maintenance diagnosis. Knowledge
was recognized as being subjective; there was no single
‘reality.’ Social relativist notions can also be seen in the
way the system was designed. It emerged through the
interaction of the design team which comprised a coali-
tion of union representatives, mechanics and system
developers. Hence control of systems development lay
in the hands of a heterogeneous group. Members of the
design team shared insights and concentrated on the
acceptance of the system by the mechanics. Neohu-
manist influence in the development process was visi-
ble in the recognition that there might be communica-
tion barriers within the coalition which needed to be
addressed by standards of fairness. Note the difference
here regarding the nature of conflict which is assumed
to be negotiable in neohumanism but ineradicable in
radical structuralism.g
Differences in developed systems relate to the output of
systems development and include the following eight
features:”
more than one paradigm. For example, the assumption that a coalition be-
tween management and unions may be productive, was consistent with func-
tionalism, social relativism, and neohumanism. The emphasis on overcoming
the computational limitations of the human mind is consistent with function-
alism and neohumanism, but there are differences. The functionalist might
see the increase of computational power (memory capacity, retrieval reliabil-
ity, speed) as necessary for meeting objective requirements. The neohumanist
system developer would first focus on the principal causes of distorted com-
munication in rational discourse. If these causes are primarily due to lack of
time and easy access to computational resources then the approach taken
would be similar to functionalism. However, in most cases there are social
asymmetries and psychological reasons that lead to distorted communication,
such as power, mistrust, group egoism. bias, and prejudice. Therefore more
computational power does not necessarily lead to a more rational social dis-
course; in fact, it could amplify the distortions. [The attitude of social relativ-
ism is not to focus so much on the computational limits, hut on the impor-
tance of sense making as a uniquely human endeavor.)
with system differences. They are by no means exhaustive. as others could
have been chosen. (1) Technology architecture was derived from Ciborra [ZZ]
who notes the importance of technology architecture for lowering the costs of
organizational transactions. (2) Kind of information flow was derived from the
language action view of information systems [35] which focuses on the pur-
poses of information flows. (3) Control of users was derived from Kling [54]
who notes that it “is often assumed that when automated information systems
become available, managers and line supervisors exploit them to enhance
their own control over different resources, particularly the activities of their
subordinates.” (4) Control of systems development was derived from Briefs et
al. [17] who note the importance of internal and external control of the actors
who participate in systems development. (See also Mathiassen et al.‘s critique
of both traditional management strategies of ISD and trade union agreements
“primarily aiming at controlling the development process from outside” either
with the purpose of minimizing costs or predetermining fixed points
for participative decisions [74].) (5) Access to information was derived from
Markus [71] who vividly shows through her FIS case that the access to infor-
mation could change the balance of power between different interest groups.
A similar point is made in Newman 1831. (6) Error handling was derived from
Markus’ [Z] case where an error was treated as a feature. (7) The impor-
tance of training was derived from Kubicek’s 1551 observation that worker-
sponsored production and distribution of information technology-related
knowledge should involve learning activities that are based on previous expe-
rience of the workers [cf. 291. (8) F&on d’etre was susested by studying the
goals of information systems in the four paradigms.
5.
specific hardware and software components are con-
figured and matched with the structural units of the
organization. As is evident from both the typesetting
and engine maintenance example, the structural dif-
ferentiation supported by alternative technology ar-
chitectures has a considerable impact on the oppor-
tunities and privileges afforded various user groups.
Different types of technology architecture in typeset-
ting for example, can abolish, maintain or enhance
typesetters’ responsibilities.
Kind of information flows refers to the intended mean-
ings of the information dealt with by the IS. For
example, the meaning of the information of the first
engine maintenance system was to formalize the
mechanics’ diagnostic skills so as to leave them out
of the diagnostic loop. This differs from information
intended to improve the diagnostic capabilities of
the mechanics.
Control of users refers to how the information system
would contribute to or diminish opportunities for
one group exercising power, authority or other forms
of social influence over another.
Control of systems development refers to the locus of
influence over the systems development process. In
principle this can lie with the people affected by the
system or some external group or a mixture. (This
has been dealt with more fully in the section enti-
tled Development Process Differences.)
Access to information refers to who would have access
to the information provided by the IS and with it,
who stands to benefit from improved information.
Error handling refers to the arrangement for detecting
errors and who would deal with them. Depending on
how errors are looked upon, they can be used as a
basis for external sanctions and rewards, as a means
of subjugation, or, more positively, as a challenge to
creativity, source of learning and creation of new
meanings.
Training refers to the role that education plays as
part of system change, who will be selected for train-
ing, whether it is seen as a means to enhance the
individual and his or her social position, or whether
it is confined to mechanical skills for operating the
system.
Raison d’etre refers to the primary reason for the
existence of the information system. For example, is
it seen as a means for overcoming social barriers, for
improving policy formation and competitive advan-
tage, for enhancing management control over work-
ers, for achieving cost-savings by replacing labor,
etc.?
developed in the typesetting and engine maintenance
examples. The tables are structured in such a way that
they can be related to the description of the two exam-
ples given earlier. The tables compare the features of
the systems which would likely have been developed if
a functionalist approach had been adopted. The com-
ware to eliminate ma.nual processes of typesetting.
typesetting support system; provide extra workstations with
specific hardware requirements to support typesettilng (elec-
tronic cropper, large area, high resolution screen to provide
similar capabilities as backlit panels).
to management.
chanical printing; feedback loop for quality control between
writers/editors and typesetters. Productivity controts possible,
but not the key issue.
of typesetting reduced or eliminated; no need for typesetters
and control of their work.
and the details of task sequencing on how to achieve it.
which was seen to reflect managerial bias.
forced to receive a bwer quality product but theoretically at ting standards. Customers receive a higher quality product but
lower prices. possibly forced to buy at a higher price.
demands from typesetters by making them redundant. ductive, and providing a more appealing product to customers.
what we think would be the likely system differences
in terms of the eight features introduced above. Table II
summarizes the system differences arising from a type-
setting system developed under a moderated radical
structuralist approach. It was moderated because the
archi.tects of the typesetting system, while denying co-
operation with management and refusing to take funds
from them, nevertheless did not seek to wrestle com-
plete control from them. Moreover, they did not chal-
lenge the basic tenets of a free market economy, i.e.,
they wanted to develop a competitive system which
could be sold to other newspaper companies. The idea
same people developing the same system under more than one approach is
imposjihle. Constructing hypothetical cases was therefore chosen. To mitigate
the inherent problems of using these hypothetical cases. we have relied, in
the first case, on the extensive published information that exists on typeset-
ting systems. These systems are well-understood and have been widely imple-
mented using functionalist approaches. In the second case, we rely on the
published literature on functionalist approaches to building expert systems, in
particular [40, 411. A detailed analysis of the dominance of functionalist influ-
ence in the expert systems literature is provided in [ES]. We thus feel reason-
ably comfortable with suggesting how the differences might be manifest.
software to other locations so that the typesetter’s craft
as a social class is enhanced. Indeed, several UTOPIA
reports “state that there is not incompatibility between
making profits and demanding quality of training,
work, and product,” [28, p. 3531. Table III a,ddresses the
differences between an engine maintenance system
first developed under the functionalist tradition, and
then redone with a development approach character-
ized by influences from the social relativist and neohu-
manist paradigms.
In practice, information systems development ap-
proaches are influenced by assumptions from more
than one paradigm. However, the influence from one
paradigm is typically dominant. As an example con-
sider the adaptation of the structured systems analysis
and design approaches (e.g., [27, 33, 48, 98, 1011 to the
complexities of practice. The dominant influence is
clearly functionalist with the emphasis on identifying
Functionalism
(disassembled manually) to detect faults.
relying on visual and tactile inspection and interpretation in
light of their experience and tacit knowledge.
maintenance needs to be done and how to most efficiently seeks advice regarding possible strategies on how to
carry it out. correct it.
performed and how. end result (which is contended to improve quality).
management (union entered into a coalition with management
to improve the front line service and retain their jobs).
figures and mean average failure rates); correction by better for their work; correction of remaining errors by quality circles
knowledge engineering and corrective maintenance. and group problem solving.
computer-based systems in general, with the view to remove
unwarranted objections. It also includes some key concepts to
understand the underlying design and logic of the system; and
then training on the operation of the systems.
to be unreliable and error-prone.
for success, and are relieved from the burden of remembering
and keeping track of numerous routine details.
Palmer [77, p. 31 who state: “the specification should
contain all the true requirements and nothing but the
true requirements,” the assumption of a clearly defina-
ble system purpose, the belief that it is possible to ob-
jectively model the current system which can be tested
through various structured techniques [33], the distinc-
tion between the logical and physical system exists and
the suggestion that one can be derived from the other
[Zi’], “that there are precisely defined ways to partition
essential features in such a way that the principles of
essential modeling are observed” [77, p. 471. Neverthe-
less, there is often a recognition of the subjectivity and
evolutionary nature of requirements. Prototyping is the
practical way of handling the subjective and emerging
nature of requirements (cf. [26]). Prototyping, though
originally conceived as an approach in its own right
[82], is incorporated within the requirements specifica-
tion stage of the structured approaches to mitigate the
“true requirements.” In prototyping, users and analysts
interact to construct a working model of the system
which is then “refined and modified in a continuous
process, until the fit between user and system is accept-
able” [19, p. 1631.
and engine maintenance cases, the mixing of influences
of various paradigms can and does occur in a number
of creative solutions to systems development problems
which advance the state of the art. The UTOPIA project
is a good example. It shows systems development under
a radical structuralist approach, but with moderating
influences.
In practice, it can be seen that the mixing of paradig-
matic influences leads to interesting and creative solu-
tions; however, the development of these solutions has
titioners who may or may not have been conscious of
the philosophical assumptions belonging to alternative
paradigms. Should the finding of such ‘creative’ solu-
tions rely only on serendipity? We contend that ad-
vancement could come about from the explicit docu-
mentation of the assumptions underlying the various
paradigms. It would permit the generation of creative
solutions to practical problems to proceed in a more
conscious and systematic way.
derlying the paradigms allows systems developers to
become better aware of the assumptions and beliefs
that they employ in their day-to-day activities. A better
understanding of the conceptual foundations of their
beliefs including the recognition of other belief alterna-
tives can lead developers to seek creative solutions us-
ing the strengths of each paradigm. However, each par-
adigm has weaknesses that will affect the quality of the
solutions it inspires. Without a systematic documenta-
tion of alternative paradigmatic assumptions, some of
these weaknesses may escape the attention of the prac-
ticing systems developer. A concise documentation of
paradigmatic assumptions invites critical assessment.
provides a new vehicle for investigating new theories
about the nature and purpose of information systems
development. Currently, most research is focused
only on the functionalist paradigm. This, we argue,
is not enough. Functionalist systems development is
grounded in a set of common assumptions that concom-
itantly enlighten and enslave. Alternative conceptions
of ISD seem warranted (cf. [&I) and will hopefully
emerge through further research.
the helpful comments of Kalle Lyytinen, Rob Kling,
Niels Bjorn-Andersen, John Venable, and four anony-
mous referees. Kalle Lyytinen’s help in constructing a
preliminary version of Table I is gratefully acknowl-
edged.
digms pose a number of interesting but difficult chal-
lenges. First, each paradigm is capable of further devel-
opment and refinement, It is the task of IS researchers
to attend to such refinement. For example, the func-
tionalist paradigm, as reflected in the current ISD liter-
ature, does not incorporate the latest thinking about
functionalism as it exists in social theory [1, 311. The
challenge facing researchers is to incorporate these ad-
vances into the various ISD paradigms. This appears to
have been taken up by Winograd and Flores [99] in
their absorption of essential insights from social relativ-
ism-namely a hermeneutic and phenomenological
analysis of human understanding-into their treatment
of the software design problem.
Hills, 1985.
Alter, S. Decision Support Systems: Current Practice and Continuing
C h a l l e n g e s . A d d i s o n – W e s l e y , R e a d i n g , M a s s . , 1980.
Argyris, C. Reasoning, Learning and Action: Individual and Organi-
zational. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, 1982.
Argyris, C., and Schon, D. Theory in Practice. Jossey-Bass, San Fran-
cisco, 1974.
Banbury, J. Towards a framework for systems analysis practice. In
Critical issues in Information Systems Research, R. Boland and R.
Hirschheim, Eds. Wiley, Chichester, 1987, pp. 79-96.
B a r d a c h , E . T h e I m p l e m e n t a t i o n G a m e . M I T P r e s s , C a m b r i d g e , M a s s . ,
197
development methodologies to paradigms in this article,
an exploration of their relationship would nevertheless
appear to be a key research issue? Methodologies such
as ISAC [64], Soft Systems Methodology [ZO], and Multi-
view [loo], which combine features of different para-
digms need to be critically appraised. A criticism and
grounding of existing methodologies by analyzing them
from the vantage point of different paradigms would
seem to be a useful vehicle for obtaining a detailed
understanding of them [66]. Moreover, the identifica-
tion of new ISD paradigms [65] could lead to the con-
struction of new methodologies. An example in this
direction is provided by the work of Goldkuhl and
Lyytinen [%I, Lyytinen and Lehtinen [69], and Lehti-
nen and Lyytinen 16
p r o c e s s , a s m e t h o d o l o g i e s o f t e n e x h i b i t p r o p e r t i e s o f m o r e t h a n o n e p a r a d i g m .
E l s e w h e r e [&I], w e h a v e a t t e m p t e d t o d o c u m e n t t h e r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n t h e
t w o b y m a p p i n g v a r i o u s s y s t e m s d e v e l o p m e n t m e t h o d o l o g i e s o n t o t h e two-
d i m e n s i o n a l s p a c e g e n e r a t e d t h r o u g h v i e w i n g t h e p a r a d i g m s i n t e r m s o f
c o n t i n u a .
Base. 23, 1 (1982), 19-26.
Berger, P. and Luckmann, T. The Social Construction of Reality: A
T r e a t i s e i n t h e S o c i o l o g y o f K n o w l e d g e . D o u b l e d a y , N e w Y o r k , 1967.
Bjerknes, G. and Bratteteig, T. The application perspective-an-
other way of conceiving systems development and EDP-based sys-
tems. In The Seventh Scandinavian Research Seminar on Systemeering,
M. Saaksjarvi, Ed. (Helsinki, Finland, Aug. 1984).
Bjerknes, G. and Bratteteig, T. FLORENCE in wonderland-sys-
tems development with nurses. Paper presented at the Conference
on Development and Use of Computer-Based Systems and Tools
(Aarhus, Denmark, Aug. 1985).
Bodker, S., Ehn, P., Romberger, S., and Sjogren, D. The UTOPIA
Project: An alternative in text and images. Graffiti 7 (May 1985).
Boland, R. Phenomenology: A preferred approach to research in
information systems. In Research Methods in Information Systems. E.
Mumford, R. Hirschheim, G. Fitzgerald et al., Eds. North-Holland,
Amsterdam, 1985, pp. 193-202.
Boland, R. and Day, W. The process of systems design: A phenome-
nological approach. In Proceedings of the Third International Confer-
ence on information Systems (Ann Arbor, Mich., Dec. 1982), 31-45.
Bostrom, R. and Heinen, S., MIS problems and failures: A socio-
technical perspective- Part I: The causes. MIS Quart. 2, 3 (Sept.
1977), 17-32.
Braverman, H. Labour and Monopoly Capital. Monthly Review Press,
New York, 1974.
Briefs, U. Participatory systems design as approach for a workers’
production policy. In Systems Design For, With, and By the Users. U.
Briefs, C. Ciborra, and L. Schneider, Eds. North-Holland, Amster-
dam, 1983.
B r i e f s , U . , C i b o r r a , C . a n d S c h n e i d e r , L . , E d s . , S y s t e m s D e s i g n F o r ,
With and By the Users. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1983.
B u r r e l l , G . a n d M o r g a n , G . S o c i o l o g i c a l P a r a d i g m s a n d O r g a n i z a t i o n a l
A n a l y s i s . H e i n e m a n n , L o n d o n , 1979.
Capron, H . S y s t e m s A n a l y s i s a n d D e s i g n . B e n j a m i n C u m m i n g s ,
Menlo Park, 1986.
C h e c k l a n d , P . S y s t e m s T h i n k i n g , S y s t e m s P r a c t i c e . W i l e y , C h i c h e s t e r ,
1981.
Chua, W. Radical developments in accounting thought. Account.
Rev. 62, 4 (Oct. 1986), 601-632.
Ciborra, C. Information systems and transactions architecture.
Inter. Policy Anal. Info. Syst. 5, 4 (1981), 305-323.
C o s e r , L . T h e F u n c t i o n s of S o c i a l C o n f l i c t . F r e e P r e s s , N e w Y o r k ,
1956.
ment/Feasibility Techniques. Wiley, New York, 1982.
parative study and methodological critique. Commun. ACM 26, 11
(Nov. 1983), 987-997.
Foundations, Structure and Development. McGraw-Hill, New York,
1 9 8 5 .
P r e s s , N e w Y o r k , 1 9 7 8 .
centrum, S t o c k h o l m , 1 9 8 8 .
training, technology, and products viewed from the quality of work
perspective. In Systems Design For, With and By the Users. U. Briefs,
C. Ciborra, and L. Schneider, Eds, North-Holland, Amsterdam,
1 9 8 3 , p p . 4 3 9 – 4 4 9 .
work organization: Some results from the DEMOS project. Systems
Design For, With and By the Users. U. Briefs, C. Ciborra, and L.
Schneider, Eds. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1983, pp. 427-437.
University Press, Cambridge, 1986.
London, 1975.
niques. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1979.
Cliffs, N.J., 1967.
t i o n s y s t e m s . I n P r o c e e d i n g s o f t h e T h i r d Z n t e r n a t i o n a l C o n f e r e n c e o n
I n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s . M . G i n z b e r g a n d C . R o s s , E d s . , A n n A r b o r ,
Mich. 1982, pp. 13-30.
Schema and the Information Base. IS0 Report No. ISO/TC97/SCs/
N 6 9 5 , 1 9 8 2 .
D a m e P r e s s , S o u t h B e n d , I n d . , 1 9 8 0 .
3 0 . Habermas, J. The Theory of Communicative Action: Volume One-
40 Harmon, P. and King, D. Expert S&ems. Wiley, New York, 1985.
41 Hayes-Roth, F. Knowledge-based expert systems: A tutorial. IEEE
4 2 Hedberg, B. and Mumford, E. The design of computer systems:
cess. In Human Choice and Computers. E. Mumford and H. Sackman,
Eds. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1975, pp. 31-59.
perspective. In Research Methods in Information Sysfems. E. Mum-
ford, R. Hirschheim, R. Fitzberald et al., Eds. North-Holland, Am-
sterdam, 1985, pp. 13-38.
analysis of their underlying philosophical assumptions. Templeton
College, Oxford, working paper, 1988.
tive of information systems development. In Proceedings of the
E i g h t h Z n t e r n a t i o n a l C o n f e r e n c e o n Z n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s . J. DeGross
and C. Kriebel, Eds. (Pittsburgh, Pa., 1987) pp. 45-56.
izational and social aspects of management accounting: A review of
its underlying assumptions. J. Manage. Stud. (Sept. 1985), 429-465.
Kev. 88, 3 (Apr. 1985), 43-49.
1 9 8 3 .
ACM 24, 1 (Jan. 1981), 24-33.
u!chnological change in the office: A consequentialist perspective.
Office: Tech. People 2, (1983), 15-42.
port systems: A consequentialist perspective. Decis. Supp. Syst. 2, 1
(Iiln. 1985), 5-23.
ttlation systems development. In Critical Zssues in Znformafion Sys-
crams R e s e a r c h . R . B o l a n d a n d R . H i r s c h h e i m , E d s . W i l e y , Chiches-
tcr, 1987, 275-305.
5 Itystems. In Research Methods in Information Systems. E. Mumford, R.
cI t iirschheim, G. Fitzgerald et al., Eds. North-Holland, Amsterdam,
;; IOH5, pp. 131-161.
recent empirical research. ACM Comput. Surv. 22, 1 (Mar. 1980),
61-110.
about structure and content arising from recent research from a
trade union perspective. In Systems Design For, With and By the
Users. U. Briefs, C. Ciborra, and L. Schneider, Eds. North-Holland,
Amsterdam, 1983, pp. 3-18.
Chicago Press, Chicago, 1970.
oper values: Assumptions, truisms, and empirical evidence. In Pro-
ceedings of t h e F i f t h Z n t e r n a t i o n a l C o n f e r e n c e o n I n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s .
(Tucson, Ariz., 1984), l-13.
tion and research on development and use of systems and tools.
Paper presented at the Conference on Development and Use of
Computer-Based Systems and Tools (Aarhus, Denmark, Aug. 1985).
development project – a n intervention perspective on organi-
zational change. DIAMI PB-179, University of Aarhus, Denmark,
M A R S R e p o r t N o . 6 , N o v e m b e r 1 9 8 4 .
Growth. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1977.
systems. Info. Syst. II, 3 (1986), 299-317.
Unwin, London, 1974.
Columbia University Press, New York, 1981.
veZopment: A Systematic Approach. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs,
1 9 8 1 .
Social Action Perspective to Information Systems. Ph.D. disserta-
tion University of Jyvaskyla, Finland, 1986.
velopment: Theoretical constructs and recommendations. Critical
Z s s u e s i n Z n f o r m a t i o n S y s t e m s R e s e a r c h . R . B o l a n d a n d R . H i r s c h h e i m ,
Eds. Wiley, Chichester, 1987, 3-41.
discourse: An application of Habermas’ Theory of Communicative
Rationality. Scandinavian J. Manage. Stud. 4, l/2 (1988), 19-30.
as a basis for a theory of information systems. In Research Methods
in Information Sysfems. E. Mumford, R. Hirschheim, G. Fitzgerald,
Eds. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1985, pp. 219-236.
i l l o c u t i o n a r y l o g i c . I n P r o c e e d i n g s o f t h e T h i r d S c a n d i n a v i a n R e s e a r c h
Seminar on Information Modeling and Data Base Management
(Tampere, Finland, 1984), 35-l 15.
Development for Human Progress in Organizations. H. Klein and K.
Kumar, Eds. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989,41-5X
ACM 26,6 (June 1983).
B o s t o n , 1 9 8 4 .
use: A science of the truth or a theory of lies. In Computers and
D e m o c r a c y . G . B j e r k n e s , P . E h n , a n d M . K y n g , e d s . A v e b u r g , Alder-
shot, 1987, 395-417.
by law and agreements. In Systems Design For, With and By the
Users. V. Briefs, C. Ciborra, and L. Schneider Eds. North-Holland,
Amsterdam, 1983, 251-264.
C a m b r i d g e , M a s s . , 1 9 8 2 .
Y o r k , 1 9 6 0 .
P r e s s , N e w Y o r k , 1 9 8 4 .
c a g o , 1 9 3 4 .
cative competence and hermeneutics in the light of the debate
between Habermas and Gadamer. Cultural Hermeneutics 4, (1977).
F r a n c i s c o , 1 9 8 3 .
ETHICS Method. Manchester Business School Press, Manchester,
1 9 8 3 .
systems development. MIS Quatf. 6, 3 (Sept. 1982), 29-44.
vention and promotion. J. Manage. Stud. 22, 2 (Mar. 1985), 193-211.
organizational control. Omega 23, 5 (3985) 393-406.
ward a human action perspective of knowledge acquisition. Ph.D.
dissertation, Watson School of Engineering, State University of
N e w Y o r k , B i n g h a m t o n , 1 9 8 7 .
Design Methodologies: A Comparutive Review. North-Holland, Am-
s t e r d a m , 1 9 8 2 .
ples]: General; H.4.0 [Information Systems Applications]: General;
K.4.3 [Computers and Society]: Organizational Impacts; K.6.1
[Management of Computing and Information Systems): Project and
People Management-systems development
Additional Key Words and Phrases: Legitimatization of system o\+
paradigms; philosophy and epistemology of systems design; system ~111
velopment approaches, functionalist, radical structuralist, social relat i \
ist, neohumanist approaches
Mefhodologies: A Feature Analysis. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1983.
Design Methodologies: improving the Practice. North-Holland, Am-
s t e r d a m , 1 9 8 6 .
Tavistock, London, 1973.
York, 1979.
P a r a d i g m R e s e a r c h . W i l e y , C h i c h e s t e r , 1 9 8 1 .
tion research. In Research Methods in Informafion Sysfems. E. Mum-
f o r d , R . H i r s c h h e i m , G . F i t z g e r a l d a n d A . T . W o o d – H a r p e r , E d s .
North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1985, 79-92.
1970.
systems in the College of Business Administration at the
University of Houston. His current research interests in-
clude the social impacts of computing, systems developmenl
methodologies, office automation, and the evolution and rn;t II
agement of the information systems function. Author’s Presc:rlt
Address: College of Business Administration, University of
H o u s t o n , H o u s t o n , T X 7 7 2 0 4 6 2 8 2 ; disct6@uhupvml.
North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1985.
research: A preface. Admin. Sci. Quart. 24,4 (Dec. 1979), 520-526.
analysis: An experimental exploration. Commun. ACM, 26, 11 (Nov.
1983), 948-956.
a n d U n w i n , L o n d o n , 1 9 6 2 .
N.J. 1980.
tems at the School of Management of the State University 01’
New York at Binghamton. His current work is concerned wil I I
the socio-theoretic foundations of information systems, the :I 1 t
plication of social action and systems theory, information en!:!
neering, and system development methodologies. Author’s
Present Address: School of Management, State University of’
New York, Binghamton, NY 13901; HKLEIN@BINGVAXA.
Ablex Publishers, Norwood, N. J., 1986.
Definition-A Mu!k/view Methodology. Basil Blackwell, London,
1985.
Methodology Ove&ew. Yourdon Press, New York, 1982.
provided that the copies are not made or distributed for direct cornnlt*l
cial advantage, the ACM copyright notice and the title of the public:! III’:.
and its date appear, and notice is given that copying is by permission 111
the Association for Computing Machinery. To copy otherwise, or to
republish, requires a fee-and/or specific permission.
of the subscription…
f r o m a c m
University of North Texas Algorithms I-220 (1960-1963) casebound.
Collected Algorithms from ACM (CALGO) offers Order No. l20001$50.00 – Mbn. $30.00
quarterly code listings in machine readable and micro- Vol. 11 only, ISBN O-89791-026-5
fiche form. Even a single use of a CALGO algorithm Algorithms 221-492 (1964-1974) casebound.
will save many times the cost of a subscription. Order No. 120002 580.00 – Mbn. 548.00
he code listings for an algorithm printed in any of
the ACM journals is included in microfiche
format in its entirety. Remarks and certifications
are also given, often with driver code. Floppy
rately through the ACM Algorithms Distribution
Service (address in box).
Vols. I, II, III and looseleaf Vol. IV, with a 3-ring
binder, one year’s quarterly Supplements of new and
updated algorithms, complete listings on microfiche
for those algorithms (from 1981) and a fiche holder.
Order No. 120000 $270.00 – Mbrs. $150.00
Student Mbrs. $145/year
Algorithms 493545 (1975-1979) casebound.
Order No. 120003 $80.00 – Mbrs. S48.00
Vol. IV and Supplements Algorithms 546 and o n f r o m
1980,.including 3-ring binder and one year’s quarterly
updating Supplements. Order No. 120004 $120.00 –
Mbm. $60.00 Student Mbn. bSS/year
S i n g l e S u p p l e m e n t s : Order No. 120010 $18.00 –
Mbrs. $12.00
A n n u a l S u b s c r i p t i o n – S u p p l e m e n t s : $ 5 0 . 0 0 –
Mbn. $30.00 Student Mbrs. 825.OO/year
P.O. Box 12115
Church Street Station
N e w Y o r k , N Y 1 0 2 4 9
reporting
0361-3682/
E-mail addresses: cho@essec.edu (C.H. Cho), matias.laine@uta.fi
ulaval.ca (M. Rodrigue).
a ESSEC Business School, 1 Avenue Bernard Hirsch, CS 50105 Cergy, 95021 Cergy Pontoise Cedex, France
b School of Management, 33014 University of Tampere, Tampere, Finland
c Kenneth G. Dixon School of Accounting, University of Central Florida, 4000 Central Florida Blvd, Orlando, FL 32816-1400, USA
d École de comptabilité, Faculté des Sciences de l’Administration, Université Laval, Pavillon Palasis-Prince, 2325 rue de la Terrasse, Québec, Québec G1V 0A6, Canada
corporate sustainability talk and practice. Prior research on corporate sustainability report-
ing has relied primarily on two competing theoretical framings, signaling theory and legit-
imacy theory, which often produce contradictory results regarding the significance and
effects of such disclosures. Thus, despite this substantial body of research, the role that sus-
tainability disclosures can play in any transition toward a less unsustainable society
remains unclear. In an effort to advance our collective understanding of voluntary corpo-
rate sustainability reporting, we propose a richer and more nuanced theoretical lens by
drawing on prior work in organized hypocrisy (Brunsson, 1989) and organizational façades
(Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008; Nystrom & Strabuck, 1984). We argue that contradictory
societal and institutional pressures, in essence, require organizations to engage in hypoc-
risy and develop façades, thereby severely limiting the prospects that sustainability reports
will ever evolve into substantive disclosures. To illustrate the use of these theoretical con-
cepts, we employ them to examine the talk, decisions, and actions of two highly visible
U.S.-based multinational oil and gas corporations during the time period of significant
national debate over oil exploration in the Alaskan National Wildlife Refuge. We conclude
that the concepts of organizational façade and organized hypocrisy are beneficial to the
sustainability disclosure literature because they provide theoretical space to more formally
acknowledge and incorporate how the prevailing economic system and conflicting stake-
holder demands constrain the action choices of individual corporations.
ties is exceeding the ecological boundaries of our planet
(IPCC, 2014; Rockstrom et al., 2009). Sustainability is, for
instance, now a regular feature in high profile business
however, an interlinked debate exists concerning the role
global business can play in the aspired transition toward
a less unsustainable future (e.g., Bansal & Hoffman, 2012;
Bebbington & Larrinaga, 2014; Bebbington, Unerman, &
O’Dwyer, 2014; Jackson, 2009). The spread of social and
environmental issues into the corporate boardrooms is
perhaps most noticeable through corporate sustainability
reporting practices, which have in recent years diffused
swiftly and become institutionalized as one element
of the information stream produced by commercial
global environmental indicators show a constant decline
in the state of the natural environment (Milne & Gray,
2013). A significant gap between corporate sustainability
discourse and its practice continues to persist (Malsch,
2013; Spar & LaMure, 2003).
tice spawned extensive analyses of corporate voluntary
sustainability disclosure and reporting, often generating
contradictory conclusions (e.g., Archel, Husillos, & Spence,
2011; Dhaliwal, Radhakrishnan, Tsang, & Yang, 2012;
Milne & Gray, 2013; Unerman & Chapman, 2014). Propo-
nents of sustainability reporting support its potential to
make corporations more accountable and transparent
about their social and environmental impacts (see
Bebbington, Unerman, & O’Dwyer, 2014). The claims
expressed in sustainability reports are viewed, at the very
least, as credible voluntary signals to the market that these
corporations are proactively managing social and environ-
mental risks (Malsch, 2013). Critics question voluntary
sustainability reporting because it tends to be limited in
scope (Jupe, 2007; O’Dwyer, Unerman & Hession, 2005),
disingenuous (Aras & Crowther, 2008), and utilized as a
legitimacy tool (Cho, Michelon, & Patten, 2012; Milne &
Gray, 2007). Moreover, the argument exists that corpora-
tions do not walk the sustainability talk, resulting in sus-
tainability reports consisting largely of spurious claims
and unmet commitments rather than signaling rational
plans and actions that address substantive concerns (e.g.,
Adams, 2004; Boiral, 2013; Patten, 2012). A significant
body of research suggests that companies engage in social
and environmental reporting mainly to secure their own
position and private interests (e.g., Cho, 2009; Milne &
Gray, 2013; Tinker & Neimark, 1987). Accordingly, legiti-
macy or reputational threats tend to drive sustainability
reporting decisions, with corporate management being
most concerned with deflecting, obfuscating, or rationaliz-
ing their relatively poor social and environmental perfor-
mance (Cho, Roberts, & Patten, 2010).
ing research can continue to glean new insights from the
broad theoretical lenses of signaling theory and legitimacy
theory,1 our collective attempts to understand voluntary
corporate sustainability reporting can be moved forward
by examining sustainability reporting through a richer and
more nuanced theoretical lens. Richer by acknowledging
the likelihood that sustainability reports overreach in their
claims, yet also may report honestly on the implementation
of corporate social responsibility plans that differentiate
them from other corporations in their industry. More
nuanced by acknowledging the significant limitations of
market reforms and the potential for regulatory capture by
corporate interests (Archel et al., 2011; Malsch, 2013), and
by allowing space for corporate maneuvers which could ulti-
there are many applications of these theories that are labeled differently
within social and environmental accounting research. In this study,
signaling theory represents work also characterized as voluntary disclosure
and incremental accounting information research. Legitimacy theory also
relates to work in impression management.
ardship. For example, Christensen, Morsing, and Thyssen
(2013) argue that discrepancies between corporate talk
and actions might actually be beneficial and should there-
fore be tolerated. They maintain that such aspirational talk
can serve as an avenue through which organizations stay
motivated in their explorations of a less unsustainable
future.
cance that corporate voluntary sustainability reporting
can have in attempts to solve contemporary social and
environmental problems (IPCC, 2014; Raworth, 2012;
Rockstrom et al., 2009). More specifically, our interest is
in discussing the broader role structural factors have on
the content of sustainability disclosures, particularly as
they relate to expectations regarding the congruence
between corporate talk and corporate action. In order to
explore this issue systematically, we draw on Brunsson’s
model of organized hypocrisy (1989, 1990, 1993, 2002,
2007) and related research (e.g., Christensen et al., 2013;
Lipson, 2007), as well as on prior research on organiza-
tional façades (Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008; Nystrom &
Strabuck, 1984). Organized hypocrisy attempts to explain
the discrepancies between a corporation’s talk, decisions,
and actions, and how these discrepancies may allow corpo-
rations flexibility in their management of conflicting stake-
holder demands. Research on organizational façades
moves beyond a model of a unitary façade, setting forth
the notion that rational, progressive, or reputation façades
might serve organizational purposes beyond societal legit-
imacy (Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008). By utilizing the
concepts of organizational façade and organized hypocrisy,
the sustainability disclosure literature moves beyond its
usual focus on signaling, or legitimacy and impression
management by more formally acknowledging and incor-
porating constraints on an individual corporation’s action
choices given the current economic system. Further, these
two concepts, when taken together, raise the possibility
that incongruence between a corporation’s talk and its
actions may generate beneficial consequences for a broad
set of organizational stakeholders.
present an empirical example of the application of these
two concepts. To achieve this, we explore the talk, deci-
sions, and actions of two highly visible U.S.-based multina-
tional oil and gas corporations during the time period of
significant national debates over allowing oil exploration
and drilling in the Alaskan National Wildlife Refuge
(ANWR). This study qualitatively analyzes the annual
reports, stand-alone sustainability reports, website disclo-
sures and shareholder resolutions during the deliberation
period of the ANWR Bill.2 The ANWR provides us a suitable
research setting as the debate juxtaposes incommensurable
issues such as protecting the biodiversity in fragile environ-
ments, respecting the human rights of Alaskan Aboriginals,
as the American-Made Energy and Good Jobs Act) is a piece of legislation
passed to provide a platform to explore and develop hydrocarbon-based
resources in the Arctic National Wildlife Refuge area, thus resulting in the
creation of a potential boost in the economy (THOMAS, 2009).
independence. Our empirical analysis revealed that these
corporations’ messages and activities appear to be generally
consistent within each façade. However, in line with Bruns-
son’s idea of organized hypocrisy, we show how differences
between corporate talk and actions become evident when
exploring across façades—while rational and progressive faç-
ades have more common features and fewer contradictions,
we identified more incompatibilities between the rational
and reputation façades in our case firm disclosures.
role of sustainability disclosures in society is discussed
next. The third section offers insights about the relation
between hypocrisy and façades and their role in managing
legitimacy and conflicting stakeholder interests. The fourth
section provides an empirical illustration of how the ideas
of organized hypocrisy and façades can be fruitful in corpo-
rate sustainability reporting research. The paper ends with
a discussion and conclusions.
body of research exploring the characteristics of this con-
temporary phenomenon (see reviews by Gray (2002),
Owen (2008), Parker (2005)). Specifically, this paper
relates to prior work exploring why private organizations
engage in sustainability reporting (e.g., Clarkson, Li,
Richardson, & Vasvari, 2008; Deegan & Blomquist, 2006;
O’Donovan, 2002; Patten, 2002) and the role of sustainabil-
ity reporting in society (e.g., Gray, 2010; Malsch, 2013). In
broad terms, the heightened interest in corporate sustain-
ability reporting is driven primarily by increasing stake-
holder concerns regarding organizations’ impacts on the
social and natural environment (Adams & Narayanan,
2007; Ballou, Heitger, & Landes, 2006; Bebbington,
Larrinaga, & Moneva, 2008). Much corporate social and
environmental reporting research is based in legitimacy
theory (Gray, Kouhy, & Lavers, 1995), which is grounded
in the notion that an implicit contract exists between indi-
vidual organizations and the society in which they operate
(Chen & Roberts, 2010). The essence of this implicit con-
tract lies in civil society having the authority to grant and
remove an organization’s permission to exist and conduct
business within that society. Societal expectations are
based upon numerous agreed-upon social norms, thus an
organization’s survival depends on its ability to meet soci-
ety’s expectations in the fulfillment of this implicit con-
tract. In general, research based on legitimacy theory
considers corporate sustainability reporting as a mecha-
nism through which organizations can influence how they
are perceived by society (Lindblom, 1993; Suchman, 1995).
ysis, viewing an organization’s implicit contract with soci-
ety as essentially a single contract that is either enforced or
broken. Society is, thus, a unified actor with a cohesive set
of societal norms. As such, legitimacy theory focuses on
whether the norms exhibited by an organization are
important to point out that legitimacy theory considers
the organization also to be a unified (or unitary) actor. This
assumption allows conclusions regarding the strategic
intent of disclosure decisions to be inferred.
acterized as using sustainability disclosures and reports
strategically for window-dressing and impression manage-
ment purposes. Disclosures can be explained in part by the
voluntary, unregulated nature of sustainability reporting
(Boiral, 2013; Merkl-Davies & Brennan, 2007). Selective,
incomplete, and/or biased disclosures have been judged
problematic, since inaccurate and possibly misleading dis-
closures can lead stakeholders to make erroneous assess-
ments of particular organizations. More broadly, it has
been argued that sustainability reports serve not only to
promote the interests of individual corporations, but also
collectively to present current structural arrangements
within society as able and willing to act on escalating sus-
tainability challenges (Malsch, 2013; Spence, 2009). Like-
wise, Tregidga, Milne, and Kearins (2014, p. 478) argue
that ‘‘organizations have been able to resist substantive
change to business-as-usual through a process of apparent
identity transformation’’ (see also Laine, 2010; Milne,
Tregidga, & Walton, 2009).
sustainability reporting and the role of the accounting pro-
fession in producing and assuring corporate sustainability
reports as significant, overt attempts to align ‘‘the socially
responsible practices of organizations with the rational
morality of the market’’ (p. 149). As the market evidence
showing that corporate sustainability reports have infor-
mational value mounts, pressures to meet the market’s
expectations of corporate social and environmental
responsibility have increasingly become an organiza-
tional-level risk to be managed. Risks at this level are mit-
igated by managing stakeholders, not through taking
immediate or near short-term unilateral actions aimed at
helping address negative, systemic social and environmen-
tal consequences of economic activity (Rodrigue, Magnan,
& Cho, 2013). The assumed rationality and impartiality of
the market becomes the final arbiter on definitions of cor-
porate social responsibility and its judgment is determined
in the last instance on economic terms (or returns). As
Malsch (2013, p. 155) states so well:
social and environmental issues] is not merely reflected
in the promotion of an ideal of planning and moderate
reformism in which social and environmental responsi-
bility becomes a key factor of economic success.
Another consequence is to consign the social and envi-
ronmental effects of economic activity to a relatively
distant future at the scale of the planet, beyond the
temporal and spatial horizon of most citizens and enter-
prises. Any contribution that companies and even
whole countries might make to the prevention of cli-
mate change or to maintain the well-being of people
is accordingly insignificant. It therefore makes no sense
standardize norms of business sustainability on a uni-
lateral basis. . .
Boiral, 2013), the reformist approach to the development
of sustainability reporting seems preordained to produce
reporting standards and performance evaluations that fall
well short of generating serious change in the way in
which corporate social and environmental responsibilities
are viewed by society. Spence, Husillos, and Correa-Ruiz
(2010) also argue that the role of the prevailing socio-eco-
nomic system, capitalism in its various forms, is often left
unattended in social and environmental accounting
research (but see Collison, 2003; Gray, 2010). Lehman
(1999) maintains that corporate social and environmental
disclosure could facilitate informed public dialogue and
debate through civil institutions. Given the findings, the
question remains whether corporations can realistically
be expected to provide substantial and transparent
accounts of their social and environmental impacts within
the present institutional arrangements (Archel, Husillos,
Larrinaga, & Spence, 2009). Can one expect a corporation
to declare the full scale impacts it has on planetary sustain-
ability within a system which not only penalizes non-eco-
nomic activity, but also expects corporations and their
managers to pursue and deliver short-term financial gains?
As put by Milne and Gray (2007, p. 196):
to admit that it is probably contributing to humanity’s
exceeding of the ecological carrying capacity of the pla-
net, and in need of being phased out in the interests of
environmental sustainability, greater social equity, and
the sake of future generations?
more complete and transparent accounts of their sustain-
ability efforts. Discrepancies between corporate talk and
action are problematic, since without trustworthy report-
ing neither is accountability fulfilled nor is society able to
evaluate corporate activities and impacts appropriately.
The idea that organizations develop and maintain façades
(Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008) and that organizations
engage in hypocrisy are key (Brunsson, 1989, 1990, 1993,
2002, 2007) in providing an alternative perspective that
corporate actions and sustainability talk will remain coun-
ter-coupled. Furthermore, persuasive arguments can be
made that the perpetuation of façades is not necessarily
an undesirable steady state. These arguments are explored
now in more detail.
conflicting stakeholder interests
strategies designed to continually balance or juggle con-
flicting stakeholder expectations to best meet its implicit
contracts with society (Barnett, 2007; Mitchell, Agle, &
Wood, 1997). The complexity of this situation places
influential stakeholder groups, whose approvals are
needed for the organization to retain its legitimacy, place
irreconcilable demands on the organization, management
must develop strategies that at least meet some minimal
level of acceptable agreement by each stakeholder group.
Managing conflicting stakeholder demands can therefore
tempt organizations to adopt specific stakeholder strate-
gies that lack internal consistency, raising fundamental
concerns over the behavioral integrity of the organization
(Simons, 2002). As Brunsson (2007, p. 113) observes:
‘‘Modern organizations are particularly apt to pretend that
they can satisfy a series of conflicting demands.’’
zations often respond to conflicting stakeholder demands
through engaging in organized hypocrisy. Hypocrisy, for
Brunsson, is ‘‘a response to a world in which values, ideas,
or people are in conflict—a way in which individuals and
organizations handle such conflicts’’ (2007, p. 113). Further,
organized hypocrisy is ‘‘a way of handling conflicts by
reflecting them in inconsistencies among talk, decisions,
and actions’’ (2007, p. 115). Brunsson (2007) argues that
organized hypocrisy is practically necessary given the con-
flicting demands of various stakeholders and that organiza-
tional legitimacy may be improved through hypocrisy in
certain environments. Even so, an organization still can be
accused of hypocrisy for ‘‘failing to act in accordance with
the ideals it espouses’’ (Lipson, 2007, p. 5). Thus, corpora-
tions face a major risk that hypocritical strategies will
become too apparent to stakeholder groups (la Cour &
Kromann, 2011) and eventually damage its perceived
behavioral integrity and legitimacy (Simons, 2002).
‘‘How can an organization continually engage in hypocrisy
and maintain any legitimate standing within the organiza-
tion or within society?’’ A potential answer lies in the man-
ner in which organizations develop responses to conflicting
stakeholder demands. Conflicting stakeholder demands can
be said to, in essence, politicize an organization (Brunsson,
1989). By viewing an organization as a political entity, that
organization may no longer be characterized as a unified
actor seeking a single path to societal legitimacy. Rather,
as a political entity, an organization may develop multiple,
somewhat isolated, sub-structures to respond to specific
stakeholder management requirements (e.g., an investor
relations department, sustainability office, or charitable
foundation). If responsibilities and processes for handling
stakeholder pressures are independently developed, their
rather autonomous and inconsistent actions are less likely
to be questioned. For example, an organization may insti-
tute an affirmative action office yet not actually alter its
employment practices (Lipson, 2007). Thus, a key strategy
for senior management is to orchestrate their talk, deci-
sions, and actions in a way that forms a legitimate solution,
pacifies conflicting stakeholder demands, and yet does not
reveal damaging discrepancies across these activities.
display and can be identified as organizational façades
1984). Abrahamson and Baumard (2008, p. 437) define
an organizational façade as ‘‘a symbolic front erected by
organizational participants designed to reassure their
organizational stakeholders of the legitimacy of the organi-
zation and its management.’’ Originally, an organizational
façade was theorized to serve one objective: to create orga-
nizational legitimacy in the eyes of stakeholders. Within
this concept, an organization maintained only one façade
that was relatively stable. This understanding of a façade
resonates with broader conceptions of legitimacy theory
(Lindblom, 1993). More recent theorization notes that an
organization’s façade is not unitary, but has several facets
that serve different roles in managing stakeholders.
Abrahamson and Baumard (2008) discuss three specific,
powerful façades that are relevant to our analysis: a
rational façade; a progressive façade; and a reputation faç-
ade. We can think of each façade as an organizational sub-
structure, whether labeled formally (e.g., the sustainability
department) or merely representing a collection of organi-
zational talk, decisions, and actions utilized to manage
conflicting stakeholder demands.
This façade presents the organization as one that meets
Meyer and Rowan (1977) concept of rational norms. Ratio-
nality in an organization’s decision-making and its actions
are necessary to meet the basic behavioral norms of the
market. For example, managerial decisions are expressly
based on extensive cost/benefit analyses, structured
assessments of market conditions, and an organized logic
to determine appropriate actions. At some point it
becomes rational to incur the costs of producing and dis-
tributing a corporation’s first sustainability report.
p. 445), a progressive façade must ‘‘not only fit the norms
of rationality, but they must also mirror norms of pro-
gress.’’ When stakeholders demand evidence that manage-
ment is acting in their best interest, persuasive evidence is
produced through the adoption of state-of-the-art man-
agement techniques that signify a continuous improve-
ment in rational decision making. For example, a
company may adopt ISO 9000 Quality Management Stan-
dards or agree to follow GRI sustainability reporting stan-
dards. A progressive façade is used to display talk and
decisions about new approaches to solving problems
raised by stakeholders. Talk and decisions are likely to pro-
duce positive ideas that are obviously agreeable to certain
stakeholders (Brunsson, 1990). How can reasonable stake-
holders object to deciding on ‘‘green’’ initiatives? The pro-
gressive decisions are much less costly or difficult than
developing a set of concrete actions that are realistic, prag-
matic or feasible. Yet, they address the potential for reform
and hide the fact that nothing has changed fundamentally
in the manner in which priorities are articulated, decisions
are made, or actions are determined.
torical symbols desired by critical stakeholders, for exam-
ple, most commonly analysts and the press.’’
(Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008, p. 447). These symbols
express corporate values such as the language found in
corporate mission statements and codes of ethics, or the
façade deals in the image of the corporation. This façade
can inflate a corporation’s realistic, achievable goals or
mask performance that is unacceptable to certain groups
of stakeholders.
façades
organization’s three dominant outputs. Talk (i.e., spoken or
written words that an organization utilizes to interact with
its environment), decisions, and actions are tools of legiti-
macy and provide different approaches to stakeholder
management that can be deployed selectively by different
sub-structures within an organization (Brunsson, 2007). If
the organization shows inconsistency across these outputs,
the result is organized hypocrisy. In the context of orga-
nized hypocrisy, talk and decisions are held to be inconsis-
tent with actions. That said, they are not decoupled in the
manner described by institutional theory. Rather, as
Brunsson (2007, p. 115–116) explains:
and actions are still causally related, but the causality
is the reverse: talk or decisions in one direction
decrease the likelihood of corresponding actions, and
actions in one direction decrease the likelihood of corre-
sponding talk and decisions. The model of [organized]
hypocrisy implies that talk, decisions and actions are
‘coupled’ rather than ‘decoupled’ or ‘loosely coupled’,
but they are coupled in a way other than usually
assumed.
sate for inconsistent actions and that actions may, con-
versely, compensate for inconsistent talk or decisions. He
uses the term counter-coupling as a way to label this rela-
tionship. Counter-coupling provides an organization with
a vehicle that allows management to pacify some stake-
holders through less costly activities (i.e., talking about
stakeholder expectations or announcing decisions about
future possible actions relevant to those stakeholders)
while focusing more significant resources on current
actions that address the expectations of more powerful
stakeholders, often those most interested and affected by
its core operations. Hence, the counter-coupling of talk,
decisions, and actions greatly expands the possibilities
open to corporations to erect rational, progressive, and
reputation façades. Hypocrisy permits physical and/or
chronological distance between talk, decisions, and actions
(Brunsson, 1989). We can think of ‘‘physical’’ distance
existing across each façade. A rational façade, for instance,
can be used to justify an action that necessarily must harm
the natural environment, such as a seafood supplier over-
harvesting during the current season to improve profits,
while the reputation façade reports that corporation’s
commitment to sustainable fishing practices in its sustain-
ability report. Consider chronological distance as aiding
the hypocrisy of a progressive façade by setting a time
horizon that keeps fundamental business reform perpetu-
ally postponed. Because almost all stakeholders experience
tion’s talk and decisions can affect how stakeholder groups
assess its complete set of actions. Talk and decisions help
shape stakeholders’ images of an organization’s actions.
organizational façades
quences of sustained organized hypocrisy and organiza-
tional façades? Within the voluntary disclosure literature,
the two major competing theories used to explain corpo-
rate disclosure behavior are signaling theory and legiti-
macy theory (Cho, Freedman, & Patten, 2012; Merkl-
Davies & Brennan, 2007). These stylized theories attempt
to predict the general use of voluntary disclosures by cor-
porate management. Although not explicitly addressed,
each theory predicts consequences associated with a cor-
poration’s strategic use of hypocrisy and façades. Using
the strictly rational intuition provided by signaling theory,
organized hypocrisy and its use in the erection of organiza-
tional façades is untenable by corporate management.
Within this traditional line of reasoning, sustained incon-
gruence between a corporation’s talk and actions will ulti-
mately erode the credibility of its disclosures, in essence
reveal the façade, and thus result in a significant loss of
the trust of financial market participants and other stake-
holders (Merkl-Davies & Brennan, 2007). Under this theo-
retical disclosure regime, the credibility of a corporation’s
talk, or in the theory’s vernacular, the corporation’s signal,
is determined strictly through its verifiability by the mar-
ket (otherwise it is ‘‘cheap talk’’ and is ignored). This con-
sistency is expected, in major part, due to signaling
theory’s assumption that an organization acts as a unitary
actor. The proponents of signaling theory argue that the
market accurately assesses the veracity of a signal by com-
paring the signal, i.e., the content of the voluntary corpo-
rate disclosure, with evidence consistent with the signal,
i.e., observable corporate actions. Non-credible signals are
corporate talk inconsistent with its actions. If a corporation
continually makes non-credible disclosures, the corpora-
tion’s overall reputation is harmed with façades exposed
to stakeholders as hypocritical attempts to manipulate
their conferred legitimacy. Sustainability reports can be
said to be treated under this theory as credible disclosures
of a corporation’s sincere efforts to better manage its rela-
tionship with the environment. Critics of signaling theory
disagree, however, with its focus on the market being the
assessor of disclosure quality (Malsch, 2013). The signal
sent to the market through a corporate sustainability
report is not necessarily consistent with broader notions
of accountability for the social and environmental impacts
of a corporation.
management generate a very different set of expectations
concerning the consequences of organized hypocrisy.
Under legitimacy theory and impression management, a
corporation purposefully obfuscates potentially controver-
sial actions through the use of selective, incomplete, and/or
biased disclosures. This strategic use of voluntary disclo-
sure is undertaken to aid the corporation’s management
2007). This view of corporate environmental disclosure
questions the informational efficiency of the market, pur-
porting that corporate social and environmental disclo-
sures are often used to enhance the reputation of the
corporation, not to provide incremental information to
market participants (Cho et al., 2010; Neu, Warsame, &
Pedwell, 1998).
reference to signaling theory or impression management
theory by simply asking whether organized hypocrisy
and organizational façades are stable or unstable. Can
organized hypocrisy and the organizational façades be sus-
tained? The tenets of signaling theory assume these two
concepts to be unstable and therefore eventually revealed
as deception. The tenets of impression management theory
assume them to be stable, at least in the sense that empir-
ical research is consistent with their theory. Both of these
conclusions can be challenged. The fact that stakeholders
have conflicting demands implies that some stakeholders
always critically examine what the organization is doing.
Establishing organizational goals to manage some stake-
holders, by default, hints at hypocrisy because it discloses
what the organization has presently failed to do
(Brunsson, 2007). A certain level of scrutiny may, therefore,
expose the hypocrisy and the façades. Brunsson (2007)
points out, however, that most corporate stakeholders act
as spectators with very limited first-hand experience
regarding the organization’s actions. He further argues that
talk and decisions are principally used to manage spectator
stakeholder demands, while actions are reserved for the
management of stakeholders most directly involved with
the organization.
rations to execute organized hypocrisy and erect rational,
progressive, and reputation façades can be limited in their
long-term effectiveness. Talk and decisions that promise
future actions may reach a point of reckoning such that
stakeholder groups no longer find the organization’s com-
munications credible; chronological distance closes in and
the future eventually becomes the present. Corporate man-
agement cannot admit that its politicized sub-structures
act independently or that it lacks the power to coordinate
its talk, decisions, and actions. Doing so would undermine
the organization’s ability to enter into implicit contracts
with stakeholders and therefore its legitimacy status. Man-
agement would be admitting to irrationality, an inability to
make progress, and weak controls over reputation risk. An
organization must, therefore, present itself as a unified
actor that possesses the wherewithal needed to deliver
the actions it promises through its talk and decisions. Man-
agement’s continuing insistence that its organization is a
unified actor once again exposes its precarious moral posi-
tion. They must refute organized hypocrisy and organiza-
tional façades. This refutation is ‘‘in itself a form of
hypocrisy, but on a higher level—a ‘meta-hypocrisy’—the
posture that a hypocritical organization is not a hypocrite’’
(Brunsson, 2007, p. 125). Meta-hypocrisy increases as the
degree of counter-coupling among talk, decisions, and
actions increases because more ordinary organized hypoc-
risy exists to refute. When stakeholder groups become dis-
decisions, and actions, meta-hypocrisy will often lead
organizations to acknowledge a lack of immediate success
and a long-term commitment to the alignment of these
activities (Brunsson, 2007). It is imperative that market
participants believe that an organization is a unitary actor;
that the only purpose of talk and decisions are to help cre-
ate action; and, therefore, that there is no hypocrisy
(Brunsson, 1989). In other words, the management will
institute organizational reforms, but the aims of the
reforms are proposed to help re-stabilize hypocrisy and
organizational façades.
naling theory and impression management theory, lead us
to conclude, albeit from very different premises, that orga-
nized hypocrisy and organizational façades are associated
ultimately with negative outcomes for broader society.
However, taken strictly on their own terms as ways in
which organizations manage conflicting stakeholder
demands, organized hypocrisy and organizational façades
may indeed make room for potentially positive outcomes
for broader society (Abrahamson & Baumard, 2008;
Brunsson, 2007). Brunsson stresses that although con-
demning organized hypocrisy as problematic or immoral
is often an initial reaction, there are reasons to hesitate
to come to quick judgment. Hypocrisy can manufacture
opportunities for change that are much less likely to arise
without it, and it can help sustain the societal legitimacy
of organizations that deal with significant conflict among
stakeholders (Brunsson, 2007). If the linear, rational align-
ment of talk, decisions, and actions was the only option
available to organizations, some important stakeholders
would certainly remain totally unsatisfied. Hence, some-
how removing the managerial option of organized hypoc-
risy and the creation of organizational façades may
actually increase the likelihood of negative societal out-
comes. Morality will not necessarily ‘‘improve’’ if these
ways of dealing with conflicting demands were stopped.
If the talk and the decisions used by organizations are more
moral than their actions, then the most likely consequence
is that organizations’ talk and decisions are now consid-
ered as immoral as their actions (Brunsson, 2007). Hypoc-
risy and façade thus allow society the chance to refuse to
acknowledge its complicity with the current state of
affairs. Society can and perhaps must hold onto higher val-
ues than it can live by.
façade can be constructed by an organization with the
express intent of hiding malfeasance. They also explain
that an organizational façade also can ‘‘transmit potential-
ities for change’’ and be ‘‘levers for organizational improve-
ment’’. A reputation façade, for example, can express an
organizational ideal that can be strived for. It may seem
counterintuitive, but ‘‘the more façades lie, the more faç-
ades have the potential to become realities.’’ The façades
can free the organization to experiment and innovate
beyond the rational boundaries of the market’s judgment.
It has the chance to move beyond conventional reform.
Given that most public corporations are subject to stake-
holder demands, and that these demands are metered
out in a market that increasingly views sustainability
and risks to be priced (Malsch, 2013), any chances to move
corporate social responsibility activities and reporting
beyond conventional reform may be welcomed.
zational façades can generate positive societal outcomes
beyond their necessary legitimating functions, this does
not mean that they will. For organized hypocrisy and orga-
nizational façades to carry the potential for additional
positive consequences, organizational talk must not be
duplicitous; instead it should be aspirational (Christensen
et al., 2013). Christensen et al. (2013) refer to such disclo-
sures as aspirational talk, which may bring positive devel-
opments for the organization and for the broader society.
Christensen et al. (2013) maintain that aspirational disclo-
sures may serve as constitutive devices through which
organizations begin to strive for a different future. Aspira-
tional talk is distinguished from lies in that aspirational
talk is publicly visible, includes ideals that generate expec-
tations of future action, and intends to stimulate organiza-
tional change. Thus, this form of hypocrisy is intended to
mobilize actions that are congruent with some future talk.
Brunsson (2007) states that explicitly articulating organi-
zational goals in areas viewed as weak is not unusual.
The public display of these goals admits that relevant
actions have not satisfied certain stakeholder interests,
thus closing the chronological distance between decisions
and actions.
sustainability reporting
through the lenses of organized hypocrisy and organiza-
tional façades, it is important to position a corporation
within the socio-institutional context in which it operates.
This positioning allows the delineation of expectations
about how corporations define and execute rational, pro-
gressive, and reputation façades relative to conflicting
stakeholder demands concerning sustainability.
on the concept of business sustainability. Discussion persists
regarding how strongly the market imperative and power-
ful socio-economic institutions limit organizations’ ability
to be socially and environmentally responsible (see, e.g.,
Campbell, 2007). Also widely accepted are discussions that
capitalism and the market pressures associated with it
limit potential organizational actions that might improve
sustainability. In particular, the very construction of pub-
licly listed corporations leaves their management little
room to maneuver in the face of market pressures requir-
ing delivery of short-term financial returns (see Gray,
2010). In order to prosper, or even survive, within this sys-
tem, corporations sense the need to constantly search for
growth opportunities. A business sustainability discourse,
as opposed to an environmental sustainability discourse,
shifts a corporation’s talk, decisions, and actions related
to its core operations toward justifications couched in eco-
nomic, cost-benefit terms.
societal themes such as climate change and social progress
speeches. Corporations develop a progressive discourse of
sustainability in their voluntary disclosure reports in
response to these demands. We thus conceptualize the
progressive façade as one that privileges social and environ-
mental innovation and reform. Social and environmental
issues began to gain ground in the 1990s, when the ideas
of good environmental management and triple bottom line
spread into managerial practices (Elkington, 1997; Levy,
1997; Prasad & Elmes, 2005). Appearing in various forms,
these discourses clustered around win-win-solutions,
attempting to offer corporations a way to reduce their per-
ceived social and environmental impacts without sacrific-
ing financial results. The progressive façade of
corporations privileges the idea that technology can be
harnessed to remediate the negative social and environ-
mental impacts of continuous expansion of production
and find more sustainable ways to operate.3
corporations. Growing public awareness of biodiversity
protection, climate change, and other social and environ-
mental issues have made broader sustainability concerns
an inherent challenge for corporate management (see
Bansal & Hoffman, 2012; Bebbington & Larrinaga, 2014;
Crane, Matten, & Spence, 2008). Corporations are engaging
with various elements of corporate social responsibility,
with the advancements of CSR committees, green product
lines, and featured philanthropic contributions. Corporate
sustainability reporting diffused swiftly since the turn of
the millennium and most multinational corporations have
provided external disclosures about the social and environ-
mental impacts of their operations for years (Bebbington,
Unerman, & O’Dwyer, 2014). However, an often heard
complaint is that corporations only engage with environ-
mental and social issues on a symbolic level. Through
omitting negative information and highlighting positive
impacts, these organizations seek to appear socially
responsible and environmentally friendly. In sustainability
reports corporations avoid addressing the fundamentally
unsustainable underpinnings of their operations. We
define these types of activities as critical to the develop-
ment of the corporation’s reputation façade. In regard to
social and environmental reporting, the reputation façade
is couched in terms of social and environmental stewardship.
Corporate talk, decisions, and actions focus on providing
evidence of philanthropy, corporate citizenship, and a
commitment to caring for the environment and the less
fortunate.
three façades, and using corporate talk, decisions, and
actions in a counter-coupled way to satisfy conflicting
stakeholder demands, is to establish these discourses in a
parallel form that is not too transparent to conflicting
stakeholders. We conjecture, therefore, that corporations
will maintain relatively more coupled talk, decisions, and
within the progressive façade, we recognize that other progressive façades
could be built by corporations. For example, a company talking about
cutting-edge operational technologies could be characterized as putting on
a progressive façade. Other façades are beyond the scope of this study.
and actions across façades will provide relatively more evi-
dence of the counter-coupling within organized hypocrisy.
In the following section we present an empirical illustra-
tion of how the ideas of organized hypocrisy and organiza-
tional façades can be applied to corporate sustainability
reporting research. For this purpose, we focus on the finan-
cial and sustainability disclosures and reporting of two
very large and highly visible U.S.-based multinational oil
and gas corporations, Chevron and ConocoPhillips, in the
period from 2004 to 2006 during which the ANWR bill
was introduced.
corporate sustainability reporting: ANWR as an
empirical illustration
Refuge (ANWR) is the largest single protected wilderness
area in the United States. It is the object of considerable
debate, as a designated area of its coastal plain allegedly
possesses a large supply of oil and other natural resources.
Congressional authorization is required before energy-
related production activities can take place in this area.
Economic arguments of job creation and reduced depen-
dency on foreign energy sources are forwarded by propo-
nents of allowing energy production in this area, voiced
principally by multinational oil companies and some
Alaska Aboriginal communities. Groups opposed to open-
ing ANWR to energy production activities, mainly environ-
mentalists and some Alaska Aboriginal communities, raise
concerns over issues of biodiversity protection and respect
for human rights, most notably rights regarding Aboriginal
culture and tradition. The debate over ANWR has taken
place since 1977, with its last intensive episode occurring
between 2004 and 2006. During this period, drilling in des-
ignated areas was proposed, debated, and voted on by the
U.S. Senate through what was popularly referred to as the
‘‘ANWR Bill’’, although no definitive conclusion was
reached.
and gas exploration are difficult to reconcile with sustain-
ability narratives, the debate over ANWR is an excellent
context for exploring how corporations engage in orga-
nized hypocrisy and utilize different façades to manage
conflicting stakeholder demands. We are particularly inter-
ested in the oil and gas companies’ position and discourse
on biodiversity protection, human rights and indigenous
people, since these constitute the major social and envi-
ronmental issues at stake.
sponds to the period during which the ANWR Bill was
introduced and (re)debated. We focused on two very large
and highly visible U.S.-based multinational oil and gas cor-
porations: Chevron and ConocoPhillips. These companies
provide typical cases (Yin, 2009) of influential commercial
organizations within the industry. These two companies
and gas industry during that period.4 While their revenues
depend mostly on non-renewable hydrocarbon reserves,
their voluntary disclosures highlight their will to protect
and respect biodiversity, fragile environments and human
rights. Also, both companies explicitly disclosed having busi-
ness operations in Alaska. Examining these specific corpora-
tions can provide interesting insights, as they both withdrew
from the Arctic Power lobbying group that was focused on
opening up the ANWR.5 Despite seeing these companies as
typical cases, our study does not claim that interpretations
presented here apply directly to the broader oil and gas
industry nor commercial organizations more generally. Our
intent is to illustrate how organized hypocrisy and organiza-
tional façades can be utilized to enhance our understanding
of corporate sustainability reporting practices.
ability reports, websites and shareholder resolutions pub-
lished by the two case firms. Eleven annual reports and
stand-alone sustainability reports for the years ending
2003, 2004 and 2005 (because they were published in
2004, 2005 and 2006, respectively) were collected in total.
We also examined the corporate webpages for the period
2004 to 2006 using a website specializing in archives
(www.archive.org). Both firms had website archives avail-
able. Each webpage was visited once per archived month6
reports and websites were examined through a qualitative
content analysis (Bryman & Bell, 2003), for which we uti-
lized Atlas.ti software (Atlas.ti, 2004) primarily to aid in
organizing the data and providing a structure to data analy-
sis. Codes were generated by the authors from the analysis
of the ANWR case and the review of corporate documents.
After reviewing and adjusting the coding, a narrative strat-
egy for data analysis (Langley, 1999) was then applied to
analyze the disclosure content, resulting in a portrayal of
the type of information disclosed in each code. The codes
and their associated quotations were thereafter grouped into
main categories according to common themes (O’Dwyer,
2004). The four major categories that emerged from the
grouping were operational activities, corporate environmen-
tal protection, human rights and indigenous people, and
political strategy. Data were analyzed both within and
across categories to identify trends, prevalent issues, and
possible inconsistencies. The original data were constantly
revisited during the analysis to ensure that all statements
were understood and properly applied in their original
context.
pretations presented in the following discussion were
formed through an iterative process, in which several
proportion of our sample firms’ revenues over the overall total revenues of
all firms with the same Standard Industrial Classification (SIC) codes.
which was the only one to remain in the group as of 2005. Hence, for
consistency purposes, we focused on the two exiting members, Chevron
and ConocoPhillips.
every month. We examined the corporate websites for each available
month.
perspectives were performed over an extended time-per-
iod. We utilize organized hypocrisy (Brunsson, 1989,
2007) and organizational façades (Abrahamson &
Baumard, 2008) as the theoretical lenses through which
our interpretations of the corporate disclosures are made.
From this, we sought to draw insights for the broader dis-
cussion about the role of corporate sustainability reporting
in societies. Analytically, we have distinguished corporate
talk, decisions and actions based on the way the case com-
panies present their disclosure statements. Talk is under-
stood to include descriptive disclosures, generic
statements, and broad commitments that are presented
without any concrete plans or details of implementation.
Decisions consist of future-oriented statements, which
have a tangible and to some extent detailed outline of
forthcoming activities. Finally, actions are implied by dis-
closures, which depict something that has already been
done or is currently in process. In making interpretations
and presenting our findings, we acknowledge that our
study relies on corporate self-disclosures and perhaps pro-
vides only a particular understanding of corporate actions.
A rational façade is an overarching façade which posits
nomic stakeholder perspective. The imperative of maxi-
mizing profit and shareholder value are strong features of
the capitalist market economy prevailing in the United
States. Accordingly, the case companies express how the
creation and maximization of shareholder value is their
predominant goal:
of raising shareholder value. In 2005, we strived to meet
that challenge by delivering good operating and finan-
cial performances, while investing in strong, value-
building opportunities.
also built a solid foundation that should enable us to
deliver sustained, strong performance into the future
and continue to achieve our long-stated goal to be No.
1 in total stockholder return among our peer group.
omy is the constant need to grow. Companies are expected
to maximize their growth opportunities and highlight that
they will keep on doing so into the foreseeable future.
Striving for future opportunities and higher revenues is
interlinked with shareholder value. We observe this rela-
tion in the rational corporate discourse:
and growth—with a strong financial position, an inte-
grated and balanced portfolio of legacy assets, a well-
defined and sustainable growth plan, and expanding
access to resource-rich opportunities around the world.
We are focused on continuous improvement in every-
meet the ongoing challenge of creating superior share-
holder returns.
the production of non-renewable hydrocarbons. To secure
their long-term economic viability, the oil and gas compa-
nies need to ensure that they will have at their disposal
newly discovered oil fields for future drilling. Within the
rational façade, the case companies may seek to highlight
such efforts potentially to convince shareholders of the
positive future outlook the organizations have in respect
to oil reserves:
larly given the capital-intensive and commodity-based
nature of the industry, is closely associated with the
company’s ability to invest in projects that provide ade-
quate financial returns and to manage operating
expenses effectively. Creating and maintaining an
inventory of projects depends on many factors, includ-
ing obtaining rights to explore for crude oil and natural
gas, developing and producing hydrocarbons in promis-
ing areas, drilling successfully, bringing long-lead- time
capital-intensive projects to completion on budget and on
schedule, and operating mature upstream properties
efficiently and profitably.
political decision-making and regulatory developments.
Here, the talk of our case companies suggests they seek
to avoid further regulation by engaging in lobbying and
direct funding to suitable candidates. When explaining
how contributions are attributed to the political candi-
dates, corporations indicate that business interests are
weighted in the selection of the funded candidates.
and political organizations that support economic devel-
opment, free enterprise and good governance. In deter-
mining our support of candidates, we consider their
prior voting records on issues of importance to Chevron,
their leadership or committee assignments, whether
they generally have a pro-business philosophy, and
whether the company or our employees have a constit-
uent relationship.
(PAC), are guided by the following criteria: the candi-
date’s integrity and character; leadership potential;
positions on issues and voting record; relevance to com-
pany operations; nature and strength of the candidate’s
election opposition; and the candidate’s access to other
sources of financial assistance.
about its political strategies without explicitly stating the
issues they support or oppose (ConocoPhillips, 2005b).
Chevron revealed its political strategy through speeches
from its top executives about the development of the U.S.
between environmental and energy policies, by which
some environmental policies preclude energy develop-
ment (Chevron, 2005c). The firm then presses government
representatives to align environmental policies with the
country’s strategic energy objectives and calls for the
‘‘open[ing of] areas currently off-limits, for the environ-
mentally responsible exploration and development of oil
and gas’’ (Chevron, 2005b, emphasis added). In this politi-
cal strategy, economic concerns for energy development
appear to outweigh environmental considerations,
although the firm seems to make an attempt at presenting
the economic development as compatible with environ-
mental protection. In this form, corporate talk fits within
the rational façade as the firm highlights how it seeks to
ensure that it will have new oilfields and associated future
cash flow at its disposal in the future.
with corporate talk in this rational façade. For instance, our
case companies discussed committing extensive invest-
ments to oil and gas exploration and seeking new ways
to extract resources from underground. They present these
measures as required to ensure that sufficient financial
returns and shareholder value are created for the core
financial stakeholders.
performance and ensuring that we direct our $10 billion
2005 capital and exploratory budget toward the highest-
quality opportunities with the greatest potential to cre-
ate future growth and stockholder value.
expand, ConocoPhillips is growing to meet that need
with a portfolio of new energy investments. However,
we recognize that our growth is sustainable only if we
continue to deliver increasing value, along with provid-
ing greater energy supply. Therefore, our growth plans
are highly disciplined and tightly focused on the goal
of building a strong, diversified foundation of value-gener-
ating asset.
reform
façade no longer suffices to satisfy the requirements of dif-
ferent stakeholder groups and future-oriented market par-
ticipants. As evidence of environmental challenges and
climate change mounts, corporations argue that new tech-
nological solutions are needed in order to fulfill future
energy needs. For these purposes, we suggest that oil and
gas companies have an incentive to develop and maintain
a future-oriented progressive façade. Abrahamson and
Baumard (2008, p. 445) discuss how elements of a progres-
sive façade must ‘‘not only fit the norms of rationality, but
also mirror norms of progress’’. The need to better manage
the externalities caused by the production is imperative in
the oil and gas industry (Pulver, 2007). We observe that the
progressive façade of our case firm suggests that business
grated with environmental and social improvements:
world, ConocoPhillips’ corporate staffs are rising to the
challenge of enhancing shareholder value through
effective support of company operations. They are
delivering on commitments in regard to legal compli-
ance, safety and environmental requirements, sustain-
able development, technology and business support, and
employee development.
lenges and creating opportunities. Today, we are
responding to the new energy equation by leveraging our
strengths: a high-impact exploration and development
program; a commitment to safe, efficient and environ-
mentally sound operations; the application of technology
to maximize the value of our existing assets and
develop promising new energy sources; and the crea-
tion of partnerships that benefit our company, our com-
munities and, of course, our many customers around the
world.
tial for reform. In an oil and gas industry setting, challenges
related to the core business are acknowledged, but are rep-
resented as manageable using proactive tactics. Similarly,
future initiatives are presented as potential avenues
through which encountered challenges will be solved and
possible environmental and social consequences will be
mitigated.
gather more comprehensive information about the com-
pany’s exploration and production operations around
the globe in legally designated protected areas, includ-
ing those in World Conservation Union categories I–
IV. With this information, we will be able to better
assess the implications of operating in protected areas
at the earliest stages of project planning and implement
appropriate mitigation measures.
are agreeable to most stakeholders. The companies discuss
how human rights and fragile environments will be
respected in the future, as the corporations have imple-
mented new policies, committed to progressive guidelines
or have begun to formulate a strategy. Alternatively, envi-
ronmental and social issues are portrayed as risks which
will be managed in a proactive way. The ANWR is an exem-
plary case in that both companies describe biodiversity
and human rights concerns as manageable issues:
review identified these two issues as being of particular
and increasing importance to ChevronTexaco. Building
on our existing policy framework, we are developing a
corporate Human Rights Statement to provide additional
guidance on conducting our operations in a manner
consistent with universal human rights principles. We
in the coming year.
development. For example, we are currently studying
the issues of human rights, water management and biodi-
versity to weigh company and stakeholder perspectives,
benchmark best practices and determine appropriate
future steps.
decisions regarding the future are emphasized. This
implies in our setting that the progressive reform does
not deal with the core economic activity of the firm, the
oil and gas production itself. The underlying fundamental
operating logic of the oil and gas industry appears to
remain beyond discussion. The case firms talk of acknowl-
edging environmental protection, sustainable develop-
ment and social issues, but these will be dealt with in
the future through implementing voluntary guidelines,
studying alternative initiatives, or following some guiding
principles:
company plans to continue to identify additional oppor-
tunities for expanded implementation of the [Voluntary]
Principles [of Security and Human Rights].
light how the firms will be increasingly sensitive to the
planet through the use of new and innovative technologies
that are less intrusive and more energy efficient. Likewise,
the progressive façade is employed to show they are
investing in and experimenting with alternative energy
sources like wind and solar.
driven and economically sound is an integral part of
responsibly supplying energy. As part of our compre-
hensive energy development strategy, we are actively
pursuing investments in alternative and renewable tech-
nologies, energy efficiency, cleaner fuels, gas-to-liquids,
and a variety of other promising, practical energy solu-
tions.
ment of alternative energy sources; however, the scale of
these actions remains rather minimal when compared to
Chevron’s $10 billion annual exploratory budget
(Chevron, 2004a).
million in renewable energy projects, including
wind, solar and geothermal energies. We will continue
to take a case-by-case approach to funding particular
projects but, as part of our expanded renewable
energy strategy, we expect to invest approximately $50
million a year on renewable energy projects in the near
term.
The third façade identified by Abrahamson and
tain that for our case companies in the ANWR context, the
reputation façade relates to social and environmental
stewardship. This façade would thus underline how envi-
ronmental protection and consideration of social issues
occupy a significant space in corporate operations. The
companies highlight how they care about the earth and
the people who live on it by expressing a commitment
to protecting the environment and human beings.
Whereas the progressive façade speaks of reform, in
which environmental and social issues are to be taken
into account within business decisions, we observe the
reputation façade as portraying environmental and social
questions as the values that drive the way corporations
operate.
Chevron.
safety of everybody who plays a part in our operations,
lives in the communities in which we operate or uses our
products. (. . .) We will not be satisfied until we succeed
in eliminating all injuries, occupational illnesses, unsafe
practices and incidents of environmental harm from our
activities.
tal protection, specific concerns for biodiversity protection,
one of the key environmental issues in the ANWR, are
expressed:
its loss impacts all people. All aspects of society, includ-
ing business, have a responsibility to conserve biodiver-
sity, to encourage sustainable use of biological
resources, and to promote equitable sharing of biodi-
versity benefits. ConocoPhillips’ HSE policy currently
guides the company in protecting the natural environ-
ment and biodiversity wherever it operates. The company
is studying the biodiversity issue and plans to develop a
strategy for providing a consistent way to protect and
conserve biodiversity.
diversity protection are provided in the case companies’
sustainability reports and on their websites, possibly to
exemplify the means taken to address the issue. For
instance, ConocoPhillips (2004a, 2004b) describes how it
conducts exploring and drilling explorations with great
environmental care in arctic regions. It explains this care
by the need to protect ecosystems:
Russia hold vast oil reserves and also are important
and sensitive ecological systems. ConocoPhillips recog-
nizes stakeholders’ interest that any development be
done in a manner that protects the environment.
mary consideration for the company. Moreover, in this
case the disclosures highlight how oil and gas corporations
present themselves as knowledgeable of the biodiversity
issues surrounding their activities in Alaska and elsewhere.
protection but also a matter of respecting the rights and
interests of the refuge’s neighboring Alaska Aboriginal
communities. As mentioned earlier, some indigenous
groups support oil development while other groups are
opposed to it, but all groups are concerned with the protec-
tion of their human rights, especially their culture and tra-
ditions. Our case corporations use their reports to express
their commitment to human rights protection. In addition
to these broad commitments, specific concerns are also
expressed for indigenous people. These concerns are for-
mulated in terms of a pledge to act respectfully toward
these stakeholders:
attributes of indigenous and other local communities.
of addressing the company’s community impact.
to protect the cultural heritage and local traditions of the
indigenous people living in the areas where the firms oper-
ate. Conoco even reports on its commitment to work with
Alaska Aboriginals specifically:
operations on issues that affect their lifestyle, land
and culture, particularly when there is the potential to
impact indigenous communities. On the Alaska North
Slope, the company employs subsistence representa-
tives and village liaisons to promote clear and open
communication, and consult with elders and subsistence
hunters, scientists and traditional experts.
added]
firms portray themselves as knowledgeable of the human
rights issues surrounding their operations. Their voluntary
reporting is utilized to build a reputation façade, based on
the assumption that these companies are sensitive to the
social issues surrounding the ANWR context.
websites are also utilized to construct the reputation faç-
ade. Our analysis shows that both firms have webpages
showing their awareness of environmental issues and their
commitment to environmental protection. They also go
beyond general statements of environmental concern to
emphasize the attention given to biodiversity protection.
For instance, in its Alaska Charter and Sustainable Develop-
ment 2006 Report, ConocoPhillips mentions repeatedly its
commitment to protect Alaskan land and wildlife
(ConocoPhillips, 2006). It also highlights the funding it pro-
vides to Earth Energy Partners, a community partnership
Alaska’’ (ConocoPhillips, 2006).
mental underlying tenets of the oil and gas industry’s core
actions are not discussed. The actions within social and
environmental stewardship appear to relate to achievable
outcomes, such as making charitable contributions and
encouraging the education of minorities. Similarly, the talk
within their reputation façade acknowledges global social
and environmental challenges and highlights the message
that the companies attempt to take broad stakeholder
demands into account.
organized hypocrisy when seeking to manage conflicting
stakeholder demands and social pressures, as evidenced
succinctly in the following two quotes from our case
corporations:
deliver strong financial performance, thus creating value
for our stockholders. At the same time, we recognize that
we can, and should, create broader economic value for
our stakeholders and that we do so in a variety of ways.
The world needs more energy, more economic growth
and more opportunity for development. Yet the world
demands that these needs are not filled at the expense
of the environmental and social systems we depend on
for survival.
zations counter-couple their talk, decisions, and actions to
attempt to satisfy the inherent stakeholder conflicts
imbedded in statements presented above. We found
Brunsson’s theoretical ideas helpful in analyzing the inter-
nally inconsistent disclosures of the two prominent oil and
gas companies studied. Drawing on Abrahamson and
Baumard (2008), we supplemented Brunsson’s theorizing
on organized hypocrisy with the framework of organiza-
tional façades. We argued that corporations construct
and maintain several discrepant façades focused toward
placating the demands of heterogeneous stakeholder
groups.
cannot satisfy all the conflicting demands stakeholders
set upon them. Based on our exploratory analysis, we sug-
gest that organized hypocrisy is more likely to take place
across the façades, as in the following example in which
progressive talk is countered with a discussion of rational
actions:
alternatives to supplement the traditional oil and gas
resources that will be the mainstay of energy supply
well into the future.
rational actions is illustrated by the following reply, which
the board of Chevron gave to a shareholder resolution
requiring the company to provide further reporting on
the potential environmental damage that could occur from
drilling in protected and sensitive areas, such as the
ANWR:
sense to balance economic and environmental business
needs. Our stockholders have derived value from oil and
gas production from historic and existing Company
operations in protected areas. Continued major global
expansion of the number and size of protected areas
that prohibit natural resource development has the
potential to foreclose much needed oil and gas produc-
tion and thus poses risks for future stockholder value.
decisions, and actions are always incompatible. Instead,
based on our analysis we envision that the organizations
establish and maintain several discrepant organizational
façades, within which their talk and decisions are largely
in line with their respective actions. However, consistent
with Brunsson’s idea of organized hypocrisy, our data
points toward differences between corporate talk and
actions becoming more apparent when exploring corpo-
rate reporting across façades. Nonetheless, this observation
remains largely speculative, since our dataset limits our
possibility to explore and discuss this issue in more detail.
Further research on this matter is therefore welcome.
different in nature. The rational façade follows the market
logic and most of the actions identified from the corporate
disclosures fall within this façade. Most of the talk, deci-
sions, and actions consistent with a rational façade are
found in the corporate annual reports. Innovation and
reform are central features of the progressive façade,
which includes general commitments, future-oriented
decisions and potential actions. Finally, the reputation faç-
ade focuses on corporate image and can be characterized
by broad statements and general commitments, which
are seldom followed by concrete decisions and tangible
actions. Both progressive and reputation façades feature
more commonly in the corporate sustainability reports in
our analysis.
rate, we do not consider their boundaries to be so clear-cut
and hence individual corporate statements and activities
can be argued to be a part of at least two alternative faç-
ades. More specifically, some façades are closer to each
other; that is, rational and progressive façades have com-
mon features and thus fewer contradictions and incompat-
ibilities are found between them. Similarly, the progressive
and reputation façade share some assumptions and fea-
tures. Among the three façades described by Abrahamson
and Baumard (2008), we identified more incompatibilities
between the rational and reputation façades in our case
firm disclosures. In fact, the progressive façade has the
potential to serve as a mediating façade that bridges the
other two. As such, the progressive façade may serve to
therefore reduce the need for a corporation to engage in
meta-hypocrisy.
legitimacy theory often uses only a limited range of information regarding
corporate activities as the basis of analysis.
sures can play in any transition toward a less unsustain-
able society remains unclear. Spence (2007, p. 875), for
instance, remains skeptical and notes that due to the per-
vasive nature of the business case, ‘‘the transformative
potential of [social and environmental reporting] would
appear to be severely limited’’. The interpretation pre-
sented in this paper suggests that within the currently pre-
vailing societal and institutional context the prospects of
sustainability reports developing into substantial disclo-
sures is severely limited by organized hypocrisy. As noted
by Brunsson, organizations do not necessarily choose to
engage in organized hypocrisy. Rather, the contradicting
elements and expectations within their social and institu-
tional environment may practically force organizations to
resort to hypocrisy, which also provides corporate manag-
ers with a solution for managing conflicting stakeholder
demands. Thus, organized hypocrisy and developing
rational, progressive and reputation façades could be ben-
eficial to corporations or they would not persist. These
practices allow corporations to frame their commitment
to sustainability as economically beneficial (rational faç-
ade), embracing of new technologies (progressive façade)
and sensitive to society and the environment (reputation
façade). The adoption of sustainability reporting standards,
in essence, may institutionalize the reporting of these
practices, and, thus, the use of organized hypocrisy and
organizational façades (see Archel et al., 2011; Malsch,
2013).
tional façades are also beneficial for the broader society
is debatable. Christensen et al. (2013) argue that aspira-
tional talk could provide a way through which new ideas
are born, and Abrahamson and Baumard (2008) purport
that organizational façades may allow needed space for
organizations to innovate and improve the realities of their
contributions to society. Therefore, they maintain that
more tolerance of corporations not walking the talk is
needed. ‘‘The tricky issue here, of course, is whether the
motive behind hypocrisy is to conceal an unpleasant truth
or to reduce the difference between current and aspira-
tional reality’’. (Christensen et al., 2013, p. 385). We main-
tain that engagement-based longitudinal case studies can
be useful in providing further insights on this matter.
Engaging with organizations and interacting with actors
inside them may help researchers gain more detailed
views on how talk, decisions, and actions are designed
and executed in an organizational setting. Interpretive case
studies also can seek to draw on multiple data sources,
through which the origins of talk, decisions, and actions
might be traced. Moreover, detailed case studies may allow
researchers to pay more attention to the roles of human
actors in constructing and maintaining organizational
façades, as prior work has shown that organizational
social and environmental disclosure practices develop in
an organization (see Contrafatto, 2014). Case studies may
therefore be used to explore whether organized hypocrisy
helps individual actors find space to improve an organiza-
tion’s social and environmental record, thereby realizing
the potential benefits of organized hypocrisy and related
counter-coupling of talk, decisions, and actions.
to explain corporate voluntary social and environmental
disclosure practices mainly through two competing theo-
retical framings: those viewing voluntary disclosures as
signals to investors and those arguing that voluntary dis-
closures are used for impression management and legiti-
macy purposes. Based on our discussion regarding
organized hypocrisy and organizational façades, we main-
tain that neither signaling theory nor impression manage-
ment theory is sufficient for producing a comprehensive
understanding of corporate disclosure behavior. Our case
analysis provides evidence that in this circumstance corpo-
rate reporting provides avenues for both signaling and
impression management. Both can be described as strate-
gic tools that are available to the organization for manag-
ing conflicting stakeholder demands.7 Drawing on the
work of Brunsson (2007) and Abrahamson and Baumard
(2008), we suggest that organizations are bound to continue
to engage in organized hypocrisy, including establishing and
maintaining several discrepant organizational façades.
Although this conclusion implies that further studies are
also likely to build explanations around both signaling and
legitimacy theories, we concur with the general conclusion
of Unerman and Chapman (2014) that richer and more
nuanced theoretical frameworks are needed to further
enhance our understanding of the complex nature of corpo-
rate sustainability and sustainability reporting.
research will benefit from explicitly acknowledging and
assessing the impact of the broader societal context on cor-
porations’ talk, decisions, and actions. When considering
an organization’s sustainability options within the broader
societal context, the situation may leave an individual
organization with little choice but to engage in organized
hypocrisy and establish discrepant organizational facades
for this purpose. We contend that neither signaling theory
nor legitimacy theory adequately acknowledges this possi-
bility as well, which implies that there are significant lim-
itations in the approaches currently dominating social and
environmental reporting research. Accordingly, future
research on corporate disclosure practices will benefit
from new theoretical approaches, which would not only
acknowledge but also allow taking the complexity of the
socio-institutional elements (Contrafatto, 2014) into
account when attempting to make sense of corporate
social and environmental reporting.
and the broader business sector also affect how the regula-
tory and socio-political context evolves. Hence, the very
agers to resort to organized hypocrisy is partially (and
increasingly?) being shaped by vested interests. It seems
likely that the developments within regulatory and institu-
tional contexts play a key role in determining whether or
not corporate sustainability reporting has a meaningful
role to play in the aspired transition toward a less unsus-
tainable society, as implied in the developments of inte-
grated reporting (see Van Bommel, 2014). Similar to
signaling theory and legitimacy theory, Brunsson offers
only limited insights on these questions, and we therefore
encourage scholars to draw on diverse theoretical framings
to explore the role of power and power relations in the
development of corporate social and environmental
reporting regimes (see Tregidga et al., 2014).
additional research using the concepts of organized hypoc-
risy and organizational façades. They can be utilized, for
example, to help reconcile contradictory research findings
regarding the moral justification and contradictory roles of
sustainability efforts within corporations. Brunsson
expresses this potential complexity by stating (Brunsson,
2007, p. 132–133):
tue’. Morality does not necessarily gain from the cessa-
tion of hypocrisy. If we have previously talked and
made decisions that were more moral than our actions,
then the cessation of hypocrisy means that we are now
talking and making decisions that are as immoral as our
actions. For example, hypocrisy makes it possible for a
company with a polluting production and product
(e.g. a car producer) to establish environmental plans
and to decide upon environmental goals. Without
hypocrisy, it would admit that its operations were envi-
ronmentally hazardous, that it planned to continue
these operations, and it would have to defend them as
being necessary and unavoidable. Then many people
would probably think that the company polluted not
only the physical environment but the moral environ-
ment as well.
this study is an initial step in the consideration of orga-
nized hypocrisy and organizational façades as substantive
contributions to our collective understanding of corporate
sustainability and sustainability reporting. We hope our
work will generate new opportunities for sustainability
research that situates organizations’ management of con-
flicting stakeholder demands within the constraints of cur-
rent societal and institutional arrangements. Our study
focused on the development and application of these con-
structs to social and environmental accounting research
and provided an empirical case example. Much more
empirical work is needed to examine the applicability of
these conceptual notions to other settings, perhaps by
investigating Brunsson’s assertion that talk and decisions
are principally used to manage spectator stakeholder
demands, while the use of actions can be reserved for the
management of those stakeholders who are most directly
involved with the organization. Work is also needed to
develop the idea that organizational façades serve as
demands. Future research could explore whether and
how a progressive façade may serve to mediate between
the contradictory talk, decisions, and actions present
between the rational and reputation façades. Defining
characteristics of rational, progressive, and reputation faç-
ades may vary by societal and institutional setting and
organizations may develop different façades in order to
manage other sets of stakeholders. Perhaps by acknowl-
edging the organized hypocrisy embedded within corpo-
rate sustainability talk, decisions, and actions, a more
constructive dialogue can develop that improves corpora-
tions’ sustainability reporting and challenges their justifi-
cations for actions undertaken to meet only the market
demands of core stakeholders.
Chapman, Guest Editor Jeffrey Unerman, two anonymous
reviewers, Nils Brunsson, Carmen Correa (discussant at
the 35th EAA Annual Congress), Bruno Oxibar (discussant
at the 32ème AFC Congrès), Sherron Roberts and the partic-
ipants of the 22nd International Congress on Social and
Environmental Accounting Research in Saint Andrews,
the 4th GECAMB Conference on Environmental Manage-
ment and Accounting (Portuguese CSEAR Conference) in
Leiria, the 2011 Conference of the American Accounting
Association’s Public Interest Section Mid-Year Meeting in
Chicago, the 32ème Congrès de l’Association Francophone
de Comptabilité (AFC) in Montpellier, the International
Workshop on The Role of Business in Society and the Pur-
suit of the Common Good at ESSEC Business School in Cer-
gy, the 2012 Alternative Accounts Conference in Quebec
City, the 35th European Accounting Association Annual
Congress in Ljubljana and research workshops and semi-
nars at Seoul National University, Pusan National Univer-
sity, Aston Business School, the University of Ottawa, the
Conservatoire National des Arts et Métiers (CNAM), the
Université de Nice Sophia Antipolis, the University of Cen-
tral Florida, the University of Maastricht, Dongguk Univer-
sity, HEC Lausanne, Yonsei University, and Concordia
University for their valuable comments and feedback on
earlier versions of this paper. Charles Cho also acknowl-
edges the financial support provided by the Fonds Québéc-
ois de la Recherche sur la Société et la Culture (FQRSC), the
Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada
(SSHRC) and the ESSEC Research Centre (CERESSEC).
Matias Laine acknowledges the financial support provided
by the Academy of Finland (project 250478). Michelle
Rodrigue acknowledges the financial support provided by
the Université Laval’s Programme de soutien à la recherche
de la Faculté des sciences de l’administration and the École
de comptabilité.
façades and how organizational façades lie: An untold story of
organizational decision making. In G. Gerard, P. Hodgkinson, & W. H.
Starbuck (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of organizational decision making
(pp. 437–452). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
performance-portrayal gap. Accounting, Auditing and Accountability
Journal, 17(5), 731–757.
reporting. In J. Unerman, J. Bebbington, & B. O’Dwyer (Eds.),
Sustainability accounting and accountability (pp. 70–85). New York:
Routledge.
study in disingenuity? Journal of Business Ethics, 87(S1), 279–288.
legitimacy theory and the role of the state. Accounting, Auditing and
Accountability Journal, 22(8), 1284–1307.
unaccountability: Loading the dice of Corporate Social Responsibility
discourse. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 36, 327–343.
Scientific Software Development.
sustainability reporting. Journal of Accountancy, 200(6), 65–74.
natural environment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
financial returns to corporate social responsibility. Academy of
Management Review, 32(3), 794–816.
development: An exploration. Accounting, Organizations and Society,
39(6), 395–413.
reporting and reputation risk management. Accounting, Auditing and
Accountability Journal, 21(3), 337–361.
and accountability. Abingdon: Routledge.
of A and A+ GRI reports. Accounting, Auditing and Accountability
Journal, 26(7), 1036–1071.
actions in organizations. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.
Alternative interpretations of organizational decision-making.
Accounting, Organizations and Society, 15(1/2), 47–59.
alternatives to control. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 18(6),
489–506.
Copenhagen Business School Press. Second edition with a new
introduction.
University Press.
University Press.
responsible ways? An institutional theory of corporate social
responsibility. Academy of Management Review, 32(3), 946–967.
understanding of the organization-society relationship: Implications
for social and environmental accounting research. Journal of Business
Ethics, 97(4), 651–665.
Chevron (2003b). Corporate responsibility report.
Chevron (2004a). Annual report.
Chevron (2004b). Corporate responsibility report.
Chevron (2004c). Corporate responsibility strategy.
Chevron (2005a). Annual report.
Chevron (2005b). Current speeches: Statement to the joint hearing of
commerce, science and transportation committee.
interdependence.
18.02.05.
Cho, C. H. (2009). Legitimation strategies used in response to
AZF incidents. European Accounting Review, 18(1), 33–62.
environmental capital expenditures: A test of alternative theories.
Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 25(3), 486–507.
in sustainability reports: An empirical investigation of the use of
graphs. Accounting and the Public Interest, 12, 16–37.
corporate environmental disclosure. Accounting, Organizations and
Society, 35(4), 431–443.
talk. Organization, 20(3), 372–393.
the relation between environmental performance and environmental
disclosure: An empirical analysis. Accounting, Organizations and
Society, 33(4–5), 303–327.
accounting and accountability. Accounting, Auditing and
Accountability Journal, 16(5), 853–886.
ConocoPhillips (2004b). Sustainable development report.
ConocoPhillips (2005a). Annual report.
ConocoPhillips (2005b). Sustainable development 2005 performance
ConocoPhillips (2006). Alaska charter and sustainable development 2006
Contrafatto, M. (2014). The institutionalization of social and
Organizations and Society, 39(6), 411–432.
Readings and cases in a global context. London: Routledge.
reporting: An exploration of the interaction between WWF-Australia
and the Australian minerals industry. Accounting, Organizations and
Society, 31(4–5), 343–372.
Nonfinancial disclosure and analyst forecast accuracy: International
evidence on corporate social responsibility disclosure. The Accounting
Review, 87(3), 723–759.
Century Business. Capstone, Oxford.
Organizations and Society: Privileging engagement, imaginings, new
accountings and pragmatism over critique? Accounting, Organizations
and Society, 27(7), 687–708.
sustainability. . .and how would we know? An exploration of
narratives of organizations and the planet. Accounting, Organizations
and Society, 35(1), 47–62.
environmental reporting: A review of the literature and a
longitudinal study of UK disclosure. Accounting, Auditing &
Accountability Journal, 8(2), 47–71.
assessment synthesis report.
Jupe, R. (2007). An analysis of disclosures in corporate environmental
la Cour, A., & Kromann, J. (2011). Euphemisms and hypocrisy in corporate
Laine, M. (2010). Towards sustaining status quo: Business talk of
Accounting Review, 19(2), 247–274.
Management Review, 24(4), 691–710.
environmental accounting and auditing. Accounting, Organizations
and Society, 24(3), 217–241.
Organisation and Environment, 10(2), 126–147.
corporate social performance and disclosure. Presented at the critical
perspectives on accounting conference, New York.
of International Relations, 13(1), 5–36.
the realm of corporate social responsibility. Accounting, Organizations
and Society, 38(2), 149–168.
strategies in corporate narratives: Incremental information or
impression management? Journal of Accounting Literature, 26,
116–194.
structure as myth and ceremony. American Journal of Sociology, 83(2),
440–463.
the Global Reporting Initiative and corporate sustainability reporting.
Journal of Business Ethics, 118(1), 13–29.
reporting. In J. Unerman, J. Bebbington, & B. O’Dwyer (Eds.),
Sustainability accounting and accountability (pp. 184–207). New
York: Routledge.
ideological role of sustainable development reporting. Accounting,
Auditing & Accountability Journal, 22(8), 1211–1257.
stakeholder identification and salience: Defining the principle of who
and what really counts. Academy of Management Review, 22, 853–886.
Environmental disclosures in annual reports. Accounting,
Organizations and Society, 23(3), 265–282.
of Management Proceedings, 1, 182–185.
the current state of, and future prospects for, social and
environmental accounting research. Accounting, Auditing &
Accountability Journal, 21(2), 240–267.
Extending the applicability and predictive power of legitimacy
theory. Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 15(3),
344–371.
transforming a ‘messy’ but ‘attractive’ ‘nuisance’. In C. Humphrey & B.
Lee (Eds.), The real life guide to accounting research: A behind-the-scene
view of using qualitative research methods (pp. 391–407). London:
Elsevier.
reporting: Perspectives of stakeholders in Ireland. European
Accounting Review, 14(4), 759–787.
view from the commentary box. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability
Journal, 18(6), 842–860.
and environmental disclosure: A research note. Accounting,
Organizations and Society, 27(8), 763–773.
cynical reflection. Social and Environmental Accountability Journal,
32(1), 17–25.
the hegemony of pragmatics in the discourse of environmental
management. Journal of Management Studies, 42(4), 845–867.
environmental contestation approach to analyzing the causes and
consequences of the climate change policy split in the oil industry.
Organization & Environment, 20(1), 44–83.
Rockstrom, J., Steffen, W., Noone, K., Persson, A., Chapin, F. S., Lambin, E. F.,
472–475.
governance substantive or symbolic? An empirical examination.
Journal of Business Ethics, 114(1), 107–129.
managers’ words and deeds as a research focus. Organization Science,
13(1), 18–35.
of NGOs on global business. California Management Review, 45(3),
78–101.
discourse. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 20(6),
855–882.
Perspectives on Accounting, 20(2), 205–227.
death of politics: A critical review of social and environmental
accounting research. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 21(1), 76–
89.
approaches. Academy of Management Review, 20(3), 571–610.
Tinker, T., & Neimark, M. (1987). The role of annual reports in gender and
Organizations and Society, 12(1), 71–88.
organizations’. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 39(6), 477–494.
enhancing accounting for sustainable development. Accounting,
Organizations and Society, 39(6), 385–394.
exploration of Integrated Reporting in the Netherlands. Accounting,
Auditing and Accountability Journal, 27(7), 1157–1189.
Sage.
The role of sustainability disclosures in society
Hypocrisy and façades in managing legitimacy and conflicting stakeholder interests
Hypocrisy as strategy
Hypocrisy and its relation to organizational façades
Talk, decisions, and actions as tools of legitimacy and building façades
Potential consequences of organized hypocrisy and organizational façades
Applying organized hypocrisy and organizational façades to sustainability reporting
Organized hypocrisy, organizational façades, and corporate sustainability reporting: ANWR as an empirical illustration
Data and methods
Findings: corporate talk, decisions, and actions
Rational façade: Business sustainability
Progressive façade: Social and environmental innovation and reform
Reputation façade: Social and environmental stewardship
Conclusions
Acknowledgments
References
We provide professional writing services to help you score straight A’s by submitting custom written assignments that mirror your guidelines.
Get result-oriented writing and never worry about grades anymore. We follow the highest quality standards to make sure that you get perfect assignments.
Our writers have experience in dealing with papers of every educational level. You can surely rely on the expertise of our qualified professionals.
Your deadline is our threshold for success and we take it very seriously. We make sure you receive your papers before your predefined time.
Someone from our customer support team is always here to respond to your questions. So, hit us up if you have got any ambiguity or concern.
Sit back and relax while we help you out with writing your papers. We have an ultimate policy for keeping your personal and order-related details a secret.
We assure you that your document will be thoroughly checked for plagiarism and grammatical errors as we use highly authentic and licit sources.
Still reluctant about placing an order? Our 100% Moneyback Guarantee backs you up on rare occasions where you aren’t satisfied with the writing.
You don’t have to wait for an update for hours; you can track the progress of your order any time you want. We share the status after each step.
Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.
Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.
From brainstorming your paper's outline to perfecting its grammar, we perform every step carefully to make your paper worthy of A grade.
Hire your preferred writer anytime. Simply specify if you want your preferred expert to write your paper and we’ll make that happen.
Get an elaborate and authentic grammar check report with your work to have the grammar goodness sealed in your document.
You can purchase this feature if you want our writers to sum up your paper in the form of a concise and well-articulated summary.
You don’t have to worry about plagiarism anymore. Get a plagiarism report to certify the uniqueness of your work.
Join us for the best experience while seeking writing assistance in your college life. A good grade is all you need to boost up your academic excellence and we are all about it.
We create perfect papers according to the guidelines.
We seamlessly edit out errors from your papers.
We thoroughly read your final draft to identify errors.
Work with ultimate peace of mind because we ensure that your academic work is our responsibility and your grades are a top concern for us!
Dedication. Quality. Commitment. Punctuality
Here is what we have achieved so far. These numbers are evidence that we go the extra mile to make your college journey successful.
We have the most intuitive and minimalistic process so that you can easily place an order. Just follow a few steps to unlock success.
We understand your guidelines first before delivering any writing service. You can discuss your writing needs and we will have them evaluated by our dedicated team.
We write your papers in a standardized way. We complete your work in such a way that it turns out to be a perfect description of your guidelines.
We promise you excellent grades and academic excellence that you always longed for. Our writers stay in touch with you via email.