due 3 hours ASAp pages

only have 3 hours 

PHL273 – Environmental Ethics

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
due 3 hours ASAp pages
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

Philosophy 273
T/R 1:00pm-2:30pm

BB COLLAB
All classes will be recorded (except

“discussion classes” – see below)

Jordan Thomson
Jackman Humanities Building 432

jordan.arthur.thomson@utoronto.ca
Office Hours: Tuesday, 2:30pm (In our BB

Collab room) or email me for an
appointment.

  • Course Description
  • When we think about morality, we usually think about obligations we have to other human
    beings. But we have relationships to all kinds of other things, including non-human animals and
    the planet we share with them. These relationships raise ethical questions of their own: Do non-
    human animals have rights? Is the environment valuable in itself or only in virtue of its benefits
    to humans? How should we resolve conflicts between our duties to human beings and those we
    may have to the environment which sustains them? In this course, we will examine these issues.

  • Readings
  • There are no books to buy. I will distribute all readings electronically via Quercus.

  • Methodology and Expectations
  • This is a philosophy course. This means that our readings will feature people arguing for
    positions on controversial questions. I do not expect you to have any experience reading or
    writing philosophy, nor do I expect you to be familiar with the course material. However, I will
    be asking you to write philosophical papers. That is, I will be asking you to do what the people
    you are reading are doing, namely arguing for a position on a philosophically interesting and
    controversial matter. We will spend some class time talking about how to do this well.

    Some of our class meetings have been designated “Discussion Classes” (see the reading
    schedule). These are classes I have set aside for discussion. There are no readings to do for these
    classes and no new material will be covered. Instead, it is your chance to come and ask questions
    about the material we have covered so far. I do this for a number of reasons. For one, it gives us a
    bit of a break in what will be a very busy semester. For another, it allows you to ask questions
    that did not occur to you during the class time. Note that in order to encourage those who feel
    uncomfortable asking questions in recorded lectures, I will NOT be recording these discussion
    classes.

  • Grading Breakdown
  • Assignment Type Total

    Short Essay 1 (3-4 pages) Due February 14 25% or 35%

    Short essay 2 (4-5 pages) Due March 28 25% or 35%

    Final Exam (Take home) Due April 20 40%

  • Grading/Essay Notes
  • 1. The essay on which you do best will count for 35% of your final grade, the other will

    count for 25%
    2. Your essays must be uploaded to Quercus.
    3. Late papers from students who have not received an extension will be docked 0.25

    percentage points for each day late.

  • Teaching Assistants
  • C Dalrymple-Fraser (they/them) – c.dalrymple.fraser@mail.utoronto.ca
    Nate Oppel (he/him) – nate.oppel@mail.utoronto.ca
    Chris Longley – chris.longley@mail.utoronto.ca

  • Email Policies
  • 1. When possible, ask questions about course material in class or office hours. Something that

    takes 4 or 5 minutes to explain in person can take more than half an hour to type in an email.
    Speaking in person is also much more effective: misunderstandings can be cleared up easily
    and follow-up questions can be dealt with immediately.

    2. Always use your university email address for course business.
    3. Place “PHL273” at the beginning of your email subject line. Your email is far less likely to get

    lost in the shuffle if you do.

  • School Policies and Regulations
  • I am committed to honoring all school policies pertaining to the accommodation of students with
    disabilities, regulations pertaining to sexual harassment and other forms of discrimination, and
    observance of religious holidays. If observing any religious holidays will prevent you from
    attending a class or meeting one of our deadlines, please let me know within the first two weeks
    of our semester and arrangements will be made.

  • Academic Integrity
  • The school (and I) take academic integrity very seriously. Punishments can be very harsh for
    any and all forms of academic misconduct, including, but not limited to, plagiarism. All students
    are expected to understand which actions constitute violations of academic integrity and must
    adhere to all school policies on the subject. As such, all sections of the school’s website on
    academic integrity are required reading for this course. The relevant information can be found
    here: http://academicintegrity.utoronto.ca

    Some Important Dates – For More, Visit:
    https://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/dates-deadlines/academic-dates

    February 14: First essay due
    March 15: Last day to cancel S courses
    March 28: Final essay due.
    April 20: Take Home Final Due

    Academic Integrity

    https://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/dates-deadlines/academic-dates

  • Writing Support for Students
  • The Philosophy Department offers an essay clinic for all undergraduates enrolled in a philosophy
    course. Want to discuss a draft of your essay? This is the place to go. Unfortunately, your TA
    simply does not have time to read drafts.
    http://undergraduate.philosophy.utoronto.ca/philosophy-essay-clinic/

    Language Support for Students
    Whether you are an ESL student or simply want to improve your English language skills, check
    out the English Language Learning resources available to all UofT students enrolled in the
    Faculty of Arts and Science. Information is available at the following website:
    http://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/advising/ell

  • Other Support for Students
  • UofT offers support services of many kinds, including support for mental health, housing crises,
    sexual assault, and financial distress. If you need help, please ask for it. There are good people
    ready and waiting to offer assistance. For more information, visit the following website:
    http://studentlife.utoronto.ca/feeling-distressed

    http://studentlife.utoronto.ca/feeling-distressed

    http://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/advising/ell

    http://undergraduate.philosophy.utoronto.ca/philosophy-essay-clinic/

      Course Description
      Readings
      Methodology and Expectations
      Grading Breakdown
      Grading/Essay Notes
      Teaching Assistants
      Email Policies
      School Policies and Regulations
      Academic Integrity

    • Some Important Dates – For More, Visit: https://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/dates-deadlines/academic-dates
    • Writing Support for Students
      Other Support for Students

    Paper Prompt #1 (Due February 14 at 11:59pm on Quercus)

    In “The Radical Egalitarian Case for Animal Rights” Tom Regan argues for the complete
    dissolution of commercial farming on the grounds that it violates the right of animals in the sense
    of reducing them to the status of “mere things”. That is to say, it violates their right not to be
    treated as though their value is exhausted by their usefulness to others.

    In a paper of 3-4 pages (double-spaced), critically evaluate Regan’s argument.

    Here are some suggestions for what you might do with this paper:

    • Argue that Regan is correct that commercial animal farming is wrong, but that there is a
    better argument for this conclusion than Regan’s own.

    • Argue that Regan is wrong to think that commercial farming violates the rights of
    animals.

    • Defend Regan against a compelling criticism.

    Some notes:

    • I am not asking you to go out and read what others have to say about the topic of animal
    rights. In fact, I discourage you from doing so. Not only would this take valuable time,
    but you would run the risk of writing a report on what others have to say rather than a
    philosophical paper. I want to see an original take on the issue at hand, not a summary of
    what some other people think.

    • I am not asking you to appeal to any other readings on our syllabus.
    • Write as though your reader has no familiarity with the subject matter (e.g., Don’t assume

    that your reader knows what Regan’s argument is) Your paper should be accessible to any
    reasonably intelligent adult.

    • All students must upload their essays to Quercus by 11:59pm.
    • If you need an extension, contact me (not your TA).

    Assignment Breakdown

    A complete essay will contain all of the following (we’ll talk about this in class):

    • A short introduction. This is your opportunity to introduce your reader to the topic and
    your thesis. Briefly explain the topic you will engage and give your reader a sense of
    how your paper is structured. What can he or she expect to encounter in what follows?

    • An explicit thesis statement. This is the claim that you will be arguing for in the essay.
    Be as clear and explicit as possible. (E.g. “In what follows, I will argue that
    _____________”)

    • An argument for your thesis statement.
    • A well-motivated worry or criticism pertaining to your argument
    • A reply to the worry/criticism

    Formatting guidelines:

    Please observe standard university formatting guidelines for the essay. Failure to do so may cost
    you points.

    • 12 point serif font (Times or Times New Roman)
    • Double spaced
    • 1 inch margins all around
    • Your name at the top
    • Page numbers
    • Citations where necessary
    • A bibliography
    • A descriptive title (“Paper #1” is not a descriptive title). Feel free to have fun with it!

    Assignment Submission

    To submit your assignment, visit the Assignments section of our course’s Quercus site.

    Academic Integrity

    Ignorance of the rules governing academic integrity does not excuse violations of the university’s
    policies. Visit http://academicintegrity.utoronto.ca for information.

    TA Assignments

    Your TA will send a class email announcing their office hours. Please refer to the table below to
    determine who your TA is.

    Student Surname Begins With TA

    A – Hui C Dalrymple-Fraser – c.dalrymple.fraser@mail.utoronto.ca

    Hur – Rit Chris Longley – chris.longley@mail.utoronto.ca

    Riz – Zou Nate Oppel – nate.oppel@mail.utoronto.ca

  • Writing Support for Students
  • The Philosophy Department offers an essay clinic for all undergraduates enrolled in a philosophy
    course. Want to discuss a draft of your essay? This is the place to go. Unfortunately, your TA
    simply does not have time to read drafts. Go here for details: http://uoft.me/essayclinicatutsg

    Language Support for Students
    Whether you are an ESL student or simply want to improve your English language skills, check
    out the English Language Learning resources available to all UofT students enrolled in the
    Faculty of Arts and Science. Information is available at the following website:
    http://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/advising/ell

    Academic Integrity

    http://uoft.me/essayclinicatutsg

    http://www.artsci.utoronto.ca/current/advising/ell

  • Other Support for Students
  • UofT offers support services of many kinds, including support for mental health, housing crises,
    sexual assault, and financial distress. If you need help, please ask for it. There are good people
    ready and waiting to offer assistance. For more information, visit the following website:
    http://studentlife.utoronto.ca/feeling-distressed

    Administrative Notes

    • It is your responsibility to ensure that your paper has been uploaded to Quercus. Once
    you believe your file to be submitted, double check that it actually has been.

    • It is also your responsibility to ensure that you have uploaded your final draft to
    Quercus. Your TA will only read and grade the file that is there at the deadline. PLEASE
    double-check that you have uploaded the file you intended to upload.

    • Back your work up. Computers and hard drives die, but ensuring that this does not result
    in lost work is trivially easy. Here is a list of syncing/backup software that freely provide
    more than enough space to keep your academic work backed up and/or synced between
    different computers:
    ◦ tresorit
    ◦ sync.com
    ◦ idrive
    ◦ mega.nz
    ◦ dropbox
    ◦ onedrive
    ◦ google drive

    http://studentlife.utoronto.ca/feeling-distressed

      Writing Support for Students
      Other Support for Students

    *

    Food Ethics

    PAUL POJMAN
    Towson University

    ~., WADSWORTH
    t1 CENGAGE Learning·

    WADSWORTH
    CENGAGE Learning·

    Food Ethics

    Paul Pojman

    Publisher: Clark Baxter

    Sr. Sponsoring Editor: Joann Kozyrev

    Assistant Editor: Joshua Duncan

    Editorial Assistant: Marri Straton

    Media Editor: Kimberly Apfelbaum

    Marketing Manager: Mark T. Haynes

    Marketing Coordinator: Josh Hendrick

    Marketing Communications Manager:

    Laura Localio

    Content Project Management: PreMediaGlobal

    Senior Art Director: Jennifer Wahi

    Print Buyer: Mary Beth Hennebury

    Senior Rights Acquisitions Specialist, Images:

    Jennifer Meyer Dare

    Senior Rights Acquisition Specialist, Text:

    Katie Huha

    Production Service: PreMediaGlobal

    Cover Designer: Michelle DiMercurio

    Cover Image: © Eric lsselee/Ermin
    Gutenberger/Getty Images

    Compositor: PreMediaGlobal

    Printed in the United States of America
    3 4 5 6 7 14 13 1

    2

    © 2012 Wadsworth, Cengage Learning

    ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. No part of this work covered by the copyright herein

    may be reproduced, transmitted, stored, or used in any form or by any means

    graphic, electronic, or mechanical, including but not limited to photocopying,

    recording, scanning, digitizing, taping, Web distribution, information

    networks, or information storage and retrieval systems, except as permitted

    under Section 107or108 of the 1976 United States Copyright Act, without the

    prior written permission of the publisher.

    I
    i

    For product information and technology assistance, contact us at
    Cengage Learning Customer & Sales Support, 1-800-354-9706

    For permission to use material from this text or product,
    submit all requests online at www.cengage.com/permissions.

    Further permissions questions can be emailed to

    permissionrequest@cengage.com.

    Library of Congress Control Number: 2010940887

    ISBN-13: 978-1-111-77230-7

    ISBN-10: 1-111-77230-

    4

    Wadsworth

    20 Channel Center Street

    Boston, MA 02210

    USA

    Cengage Learning is a leading provider of customized learning solutions

    with office locations around the globe, including Singapore, the United

    Kingdom, Australia, Mexico, Brazil and Japan. Locate your local office at

    international.cengage.com/region.

    Cengage Learning products are represented in Canada by

    Nelson Education, Ltd.

    For your course and learning solutions, visit www.cengage.com.

    Purchase any of our products at your local college store or at our preferred

    online store www.cengagebrain.com.

    Instructors: Please visit login.cengage.com and log in to access

    instructor-specific resources.

    *
    To Louis and Theo Pojman: From Ancestors to Descendants

    30 CH A PT ER 2 • ANIMAL RIGHTS

    average, or nonnal, intelligence quotient for two
    different races, say whites and blacks. Then substi-
    tute the term “white” for every occurrence of
    “men” and “black” for every occurrence of “dog”
    in the passage quoted; and substitute “high I.Q.”
    for “rationality” and when Benn talks of “imbe-
    ciles” replace this term by “dumb whites”-that
    is, whites who fall well below the nom1al white
    I.Q. score. Finally, change “species” to “race.”
    Now re-read the passage. It has become a defence
    of a rigid, no-exceptions division between whites
    and blacks, based on I.Q. scores, not withstanding an
    admitted overlap between whites and blacks in this

    respect. The revised passage is, of course, outra-
    geous, and this is not only because we have made
    fictitious assumptions in our substitutions. The
    point is that in the original passage Benn was de-
    fending a rigid division in the amount of consider-
    ation due to members of different species, despite
    admitted cases of overlap. If the original did not, at
    first reading strike us as being as outrageous as the
    revised version does, this is largely because although
    we are not racists ourselves, most of us are specie-
    sists. Like the other articles, Benn’s stands as a warn-
    ing of the ease with which the best minds can fall
    victim to a prevailing ideology.

    NOTES

    1. The Methods of Ethics (7th Ed.), p. 382.

    2. For example, R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason
    (Oxford, 1963); and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice
    (Harvard, 1972). For a brief account of the essential
    agreement on this issue between these and other
    positions, see R. M. Hare, “Rules of War and
    Moral Reasoning,” Philosophy and Public Affairs,
    vol. 1, no. 2 (1972).

    3. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,
    ch. XVII.

    4. I owe the term “speciesism” to Richard Ryder.

    5. In order to produce 1 lb. of protein in the form of
    beef or veal, we must feed 21 lbs. of protein to the
    animal. Other forms of livestock are slightly less
    inefficient, but the average ratio in the U.S. is still
    1 :8. It has been estimated that the amount of
    protein lost to humans in this way is equivalent to
    90% of the annual world protein deficit. For a brief
    account, see Frances Moore Lappe, Diet for a Small
    Planet (Friends of The Earth/Ballantine, New York,
    1971), pp. 4-11.

    6. Ruth Harrison, Animal Machines (Stuart, London,
    1964). For an account of farming conditions, see
    my Animal Liberation (New York Review Com-
    pany, 1975).

    7. In R. Brandt (ed.), Social Justice (Prentice-Hall,
    Englewood Cliffs, 1962), p. 19.

    8. Frankena, Op. cit., p. 23.

    9. H. A. Bedau, “Egalitarianism and the Idea of
    Equality” in Nomos IX: Equality, ed. J. R. Pennock
    and J. W. Chapman (Atherton Press, New York,
    1967).

    10. G. Vlastos, ”Justice and Equality” in Brandt, Social
    Justice, p. 48.

    11. For example, Bernard Williams, “The Idea of
    Equality,” in Philosophy, Politics and Society (second
    series), ed. P. Laslett and W. Runciman (Blackwell,
    Oxford, 1962), p. 118; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice,
    pp. 509-10.

    12. Nomos IX: Equality; the passages quoted are on
    p. 62ff.

    STUDY QUESTIONS

    1. According to Singer, what is the relationship
    between civil rights movements and the animal
    rights movement?

    2. What is speciesism? Why is it bad, according to
    Singer? Do you agree?

    3. Are all humans equal, according to Singer? In
    what way are all sentient beings equal?

    4. How does Singer apply the notion of equal
    consideration of interests?

    TOM REGAN• THE RADICAL EGALITARIAN CASE FOR ANIMAL RIGHTS 3

    1

    4

    The Radical Egalitarian Case for Animal Rights
    TOM REGAN

    Professor of philosophy at North Carolina State University and a leading animal rights
    advocate in the United States, Tom Regan is the author ef several articles and books on
    moral philosophy, including The Case for Animal Rights (1983).

    Regan disagrees with Singer’s utilitarian program for animal liberation, for he rejects
    utilitarianism as lacking a notion of intrinsic worth. Regan’s position is that animals and
    humans all have equal intrinsic value on which their right to life and concern are based.
    Regan is revolutionary. He calls for not reform but the total abolition of the use ef animals
    in science, the total dissolution ef the commercial animal agriculture system, and the total
    elimination ef commercial and sport hunting and trapping. “The fundamental wrong is the
    system that allows us to view animals as our resources . … Lab animals are not our tasters; we
    are not their kings.”

    I regard myself as an advocate of animal rights-as a
    part of the animal rights movement. That move-
    ment, as I conceive it, is committed to a number
    of goals, including:

    1. the total abolition of the use of animals in science

    2. the total dissolution of commercial animal
    agriculture

    3. and the total elimination of commercial and
    sport hunting and trapping.

    There are, I know, people who profess to be-
    lieve in animal rights who do not avow these goals.
    Factory farming they say, is wrong-violates ani-
    mals’ rights-but traditional animal agriculture is
    all right. Toxicity tests of cosmetics on animals
    violate their rights; but not important medical
    research-cancer research, for example. The club-
    bing of baby seals is abhorrent; but not the harvest-
    ing of adult seals. I used to think I understood this

    reasoning. Not any more. You don’t change unjust
    institutions by tidying them up.

    What’s wrong-what’s fundamentally wrong-:
    with the way animals are treated isn’t the details ‘
    that vary from case to case. It’s the whole system.
    The forlornness of the veal calf is pathetic-heart
    wrenching; the pulsing pain of the chimp with elec-
    trodes planted deep in her brain is repulsive; the
    slow, torturous death of the raccoon caught in the
    leg hold trap, agonizing. But what is funda-:
    mentally wrong isn’t the pain, isn’t the suffering,
    isn’t the deprivation. These compound what’s wrong.
    Sometimes–often-they make it much worse. But
    they are not the fundamental wrong.

    The fundamental wrong is the system that allows us
    to view animals as our resources, here for us-to be
    eaten, or surgically manipulated, or put in our cross
    hairs for sport or money. Once we accept this view
    of animals-as our resources-the rest is as predict-
    able as it is regrettable. Why worry about their

    From In Defense ef Animals, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985). Reprinted by permission of Blackwell Publishers.

    32 CHAPTER 2 •ANIMAL RIGHTS

    loneliness, their pain, their death? Since animals ex-
    ist for us, here to benefit us in one way or another,
    what hanns them really doesn’t matter-or matters
    only if it starts to bother us, makes us feel a trifle
    uneasy when we eat our veal scampi, for example.
    So, yes, let us get veal calves out of solitary confine-
    ment, give them more space, a little straw, a few
    companions. But let us keep our veal scampi.

    But a little straw, more space, and a few com-
    panions don’t eliminate-don’t even touch-the
    fundamental wrong, the wrong that attaches to our
    viewing and treating these animals as our resources.
    A veal calf killed to be eaten after living in close
    confinement is viewed and treated in this way: but
    so, too, is another who is raised (as they say) “more
    humanely.” To right the fundamental wrong of our
    treatment of farm animals requires more than mak-
    ing rearing methods “more human” -requires
    something quite different-requires the total dissolu-
    tion of commercial animal agriculture.

    How we do this-whether we do this, or as in
    the case of animals in science, whether and how we
    abolish their use-these are to a large extent politi-
    cal questions. People must change their beliefs be-
    fore they change their habits. Enough people,
    especially those elected to public office, must be-
    lieve in change-must want it-before we will
    have laws that protect the rights of animals. This
    process of change is very complicated, very de-
    manding, very exhausting, calling for the efforts of
    many hands-in education, publicity, political or-
    ganization and activity, down to the licking of en-
    velopes and stamps. As a trained and practicing
    philosopher the sort of contribution I can make is
    limited, but I like to think, important. The cur-
    rency of philosophy is ideas-their meaning and
    rational foundation-not the nuts and bolts of the
    legislative process say, or the ‘mechanics of commu-
    nity organization. That’s what I have been explor-
    ing over the past ten years or so in my essays and
    talks and, more recently, in my book, The Case for
    Animal Rights.

    1
    I believe the major conclusions I

    reach in that book are true because they are sup-
    ported by the weight of the best arguments. I believe
    the idea of animal rights has reason, not just emo-
    tion, on its side.

    In the space I have at rn.y disposal here I can only
    sketch, in the barest outlines, some of the main fea-
    tures of the book. Its main themes-and we should
    not be surprised by this-involve asking and answer-
    ing deep foundational moral questions, questions
    about what morality is, how it should be understood,
    what is the best moral theory all considered. I hope I
    can convey something of the shape I think this theory
    is. The attempt to do this will be–to use a word
    a friendly critic once used to describe my work-
    cerebral. In fact I was told by this person that my
    work is “too cerebral.” But this is misleading. My
    feelings about how animals sometimes are treated
    are just as deep and just as strong as those of my
    more volatile compatriots. Philosophers do-to use
    the jargon of the day-have a right side to their brains.
    If it’s the left side we contribute or mainly should-
    that’s because what talents we have reside there.

    How to proceed? We begin by asking how the
    moral status of animals has been understood by
    thinkers who deny that animals have rights. Then
    we test the mettle of their ideas by seeing how well
    they stand up under the heat of fair criticism. If we
    start our thinking in this way we soon find that
    some people believe that we have no duties directly
    to animals-that we owe nothing to them-that we
    can do nothing that wrongs them. Rather, we can do
    wrong acts that involve animals, and so we have
    duties regarding them, though none to them.
    Such views may be called indirect duty views. By
    way of illustration:

    Suppose your neighbor kicks your dog. Then
    your neighbor has done something wrong. But
    not to your dog. The wrong that has been done
    is a wrong to you. After all, it is wrong to upset
    people, and your neighbor’s kicking your dog up-
    sets you. So you are the one who is wronged, not
    your dog. Or again: by kicking your dog your
    neighbor damages your property. And since it is
    wrong to damage another person’s property, your
    neighbor has done something wrong-to you, of
    course, not to your dog. Your neighbor no more
    wrongs your dog than your car would be wronged
    if the windshield were smashed. Your neighbor’s
    duties involving your dog are indirect duties to
    you. More generally, all of our duties regarding

    TOM REGAN• THE RADICAL EGALITARIAN CASE FOR ANIMAL RIGHTS 33

    animals are indirect duties to one another-to
    humanity.

    How could someone try to justify such a view?
    One could say that your dog doesn’t feel anything
    and so isn’t hurt by your neighbor’s kick, doesn’t
    care about the pain since none is felt, is as unaware
    of anything as your windshield. Someone could say
    this but no rational person will since, among other
    considerations, such a view will commit one who
    holds it to the position that no human being feels
    pain either-that human beings also don’t care
    about what happens to them. A second possibility
    is that though both humans and your dog are hurt
    when kicked, it is only human pain that matters.
    But, again, no rational person can believe this.
    Pain is pain wheresoever it occurs. If your neigh-
    bor’s causing you pain is wrong because of the pain
    that is caused, we cannot rationally ignore or dis-
    miss the moral relevance of the pain your dog feels.

    Philosophers who hold indirect duty views-
    and many still do-have come to understand that
    they must avoid the two defects just noted-avoid,
    that is, both the view that animals don’t feel any-
    thing as well as the idea that only human pain can
    be morally relevant. Among such thinkers the sort
    of view now favored is one or another form of
    what is called contractarianism.

    Here, very crudely, is the root idea: morality
    consists of a set of rules that individuals voluntarily
    agree to abide by-as we do when we sign a con-
    tract (hence the name: contractarianism). Those
    who understand and accept the terms of the con-
    tract are covered directly-have rights created by,
    and recognized and protected in, the contract. And
    these contractors can also have protection spelled
    out for others who, though they lack the ability
    to understand morality and so cannot sign the con-
    tract themselves, are loved or cherished by those
    who can. Thus young children, for example, are
    unable to sign and lack rights. But they are pro-
    tected by the contract nonetheless because of the
    sentimental interests of others, most notably their
    parents. So we have, then, duties involving these
    children, duties regarding them, but no duties to
    them. Our duties in their case are indirect duties
    to other human beings, usually their parents.

    As for animals, since they cannot understand
    the contract, they obviously cannot sign; and since
    they cannot sign; they have no rights. Like children,
    however, some animals are the objects of the
    sentimental interest of others. You, for example,
    love your dog . . . or cat. So these animals-those
    enough people care about: companion animals,
    whales, baby seals, the American bald eagle-these
    animals, though they lack rights themselves, will be
    protected because of the sentimental interests of ,
    people. I have, then, according to contractarianism,
    no duty directly to your dog or any other animal,
    not even the duty not to cause them pain or suffer-
    ing; my duty not to hurt them is a duty I have to
    those people who care about what happens to
    them. As for other animals, where no or little sen-
    timental interest is present-farm animals, for ex-
    ample, or laboratory rats-what duties we have
    grow weaker and weaker, perhaps to the vanishing
    point. The pain and death they endure, though
    real, are not wrong if no one cares about them.

    Contractarianism could be a hard view to re-
    fute when it comes to the moral status of animals if
    it was an adequate theoretical approach to the moral
    status of human beings. It is not adequate in this
    latter respect, however, which makes the question
    of its adequacy in the former-regarding animals-
    utterly moot. For consider: morality, according to
    the (crude) contractarian position before us, consists
    of rules people agree to abide by. What people?
    Well, enough to make a difference-enough, that
    is, so that collectively they have the power to en-
    force the rules that are drawn up in the contract.
    That is very well and good for the signatories-but
    not so good for anyone who is not asked to sign.
    And there is nothing in contractarianism of the sort
    we are discussing that guarantees or requires that
    everyone will have a chance to participate equita-
    bly in framing the rules of morality. The result is
    that this approach to ethics could sanction the most
    blatant forms of . social, economic, moral, and
    political injustice, ranging from a repressive caste
    system to systematic racial or sexual discrimination.
    Might, on this theory, does make right. Let those
    who are the victims of injustice suffer as they
    will. It matters not so long as no one else-no

    34 CHAPTER 2 •ANIMAL RIGHTS

    contractor, or too few of them-cares about it.
    Such a theory takes one’s moral breath away …
    as if, for example, there is nothing wrong with
    apartheid in South Africa if too few white South
    Africans are upset by it. A theory with so little to
    recommend it at the level of the ethics of our
    treatment of our fellow humans cannot have any-
    thing more to recommend it when it comes to the
    ethics of how we treat our fellow animals.

    The version of contractarianism just examined
    is, as I have noted, a crude variety, and in fairness to
    those of a contractarian persuasion it must be noted
    that much more refined, subtle, and ingenious va-
    rieties are possible. For example, John Rawls, in his
    A Theory ef Justice, sets forth a version of contractar-
    ianism that forces the contractors to ignore the ac-
    cidental features of being a human being-for
    example, whether one is white or black, male or
    female, a genius or of modest intellect. Only by
    ignoring such features, Rawls believes, can we in-
    sure that the principles of justice contractors would
    agree upon are not based on bias or prejudice.
    Despite the improvement a view such as Rawls’s
    shows over the cruder forms of contractarianism,
    it remains deficient: it systematically denies that
    we have direct duties to those human beings who
    do not have a sense of justice-young children, for
    instance, and many mentally retarded humans. And
    yet it seems reasonably certain that, were we to
    torture a young child or a retarded elder, we would
    be doing something that wrongs them, not some-
    thing that is wrong if (and only if) other humans
    with a sense of justice are upset. And since this is
    true in the case of these humans, we cannot ratio-
    nally deny the same in the case of animals.

    Indirect duty views, then, including the best
    among them, fail to command our rational assent.
    Whatever ethical theory we rationally should ac-
    cept, therefore, it must at least recognize that we
    have some duties directly to animals, just as we
    have some duties directly to each other. The next
    two theories I’ll sketch attempt to meet this
    requirement.

    The first I call the cruelty-kindness view. Simply
    stated, this view says that we have a direct duty to
    be kind to animals and a direct duty not to be cruel

    to them. Despite the familiar, reassuring ring of
    these ideas, I do not believe this view offers an
    adequate theory. To make this clearer, consider
    kindness. A kind person acts from a certain kind
    of motive-compassion or concern, for example.
    And that is a virtue. But there is no guarantee
    that a kind act is a right act. If I am a generous
    racist, for example, I will be inclined to act kindly
    toward members of my own race, favoring their
    interests above others. My kindness would be real
    and, so far as it goes, good. But I trust it is too
    obvious to require comment that my kind acts
    may not be above moral reproach-may, in fact,
    be positively wrong because rooted in injustice.
    So kindness, not withstanding its status as a virtue
    to be encouraged, simply will not cancel the weight
    of a theory of right action.

    Cruelty fares no better. People or their acts are
    cruel if they display either a lack of sympathy for or,
    worse, the presence of enjoyment in, seeing another
    suffer. Cruelty in all its guises is a bad thing-is a
    tragic human failing. But just as a person’s being
    motivated by kindness does not guarantee that they
    do what is right, so the absence of cruelty does not
    assure that they avoid doing what is wrong. Many
    people who perform abortions, for example, are not
    cruel, sadistic people. But that fact about their char-
    acter and motivation does not settle the terribly dif-
    ficult question about the morality of abortion. The
    case is no different when we examine the ethics of
    our treatment of animals. So, yes, let us be for kind-
    ness and against cruelty. But let us not suppose that
    being for the one and against the other answers ques-
    tions about moral right and wrong.

    Some people think the theory we are looking
    for is utilitarianism. A utilitarian accepts two moral
    principles. The first is a principle of equality: every-
    one’s interests count, and similar interests must be counted
    as having similar weight or importance. White or black,
    male or female, American or Iranian, human or
    animal: everyone’s pain or frustration matter and
    matter equally with the like pain or frustration of
    anyone else. The second principle a utilitarian ac-
    cepts is the principle of utility: do that act that will
    bring about the best balance ef satisfaction over frustration
    for everyone affected by the outcome.

    TOM REGAN• THE RADICAL EGALITARIAN CASE FOR ANIMAL Kll..:JH 1 ~

    As a utilitarian, then, here is how I am to ap-
    proach the task of deciding what I morally ought to
    do: I must ask who will be affected ifl choose to do
    one thing rather than another, how much each in-
    dividual will be affected, and where the best results
    are most likely to lie-which option, in other
    words, is most likely to bring about the best results,
    the best balance of satisfaction over frustration. That
    option, whatever it may be, is the one I ought to
    choose. That is where my moral duty lies.

    The great appeal of utilitarianism rests with its
    uncompromising egalitarianism: everyone’s interests

    · count and count equally with the like interests of
    everyone else. The kind of odious discrimination
    some forms of contractarianism can justify-
    discrimination based on race or sex, for example–
    seems disallowed in principle by utilitarianism, as is
    speciesism-systematic discrimination based on spe-
    cies membership.

    The sort of equality we find in utilitarianism,
    however, is not the sort an advocate of animal or
    human rights should have in mind. Utilitarianism
    has no room for the equal moral rights of dijferent in-
    dividuals because it has no room for their equal inherent
    value or worth. What has value for the utilitarian is
    the satisfaction of an individual’s interests, not the
    individual whose interests they are. A ·universe in
    which you satisfy your desire for water, food, and
    warmth, is, other things being equal, better than a
    universe in which these desires are frustrated. And
    the same is true in the case of an animal with similar
    desires. But neither you nor the animal have any
    value in your own right. Only your feelings do.

    Here is an analogy to help make the philosoph-
    ical point clearer: a cup contains different liquids-
    sometimes sweet, sometimes bitter, sometimes a
    mix of the two. What has value are the liquids:
    the sweeter the better, the bitter the worse. The
    cup-the container-has no value. It’s what goes
    into it, not what they go into, that has value. For
    the utilitarian, you and I are like the cup; we have
    no value as individuals and thus no equal value.
    What has value is what goes into us, what we serve
    as receptacles for; our feelings of satisfaction have
    positive value, our feelings of frustration have neg-
    ative value.

    Serious problems arise for utilitarianism when
    we remind ourselves that it enjoins us to bring
    about the best consequences. What does this

    1

    mean? It doesn’t mean the best consequences for
    me alone, or for my family or friends, or any other
    person taken individually. No, what we must do is,
    roughly, as follows: we must add up-somehow!-
    the separate satisfactions and frustrations of
    everyone likely to be affected by our choice, the
    satisfactions in one column, the frustrations in the
    other. We must total each column for each of
    the opinions before us. That is what it means to
    say the theory is aggregative. And then we must
    choose that option which is most likely to bring
    about the best balance of totaled satisfactions over
    totaled frustrations. Whatever act would lead to
    this outcome is the one we morally ought to per-
    form-is where our moral duty lies. And that act
    quite clearly might not be the same one that
    would bring about the best results for me person-
    ally, or my family or friends, or a lab animal. The
    best aggregated consequences for everyone con-
    cerned are not necessarily the best for each
    individual.

    That utilitarianism is an aggregative theory-
    that different individuals’ satisfactions or frustrations
    are added, or summed, or totaled-is the key ob-
    jection to this theory. My Aunt Bea is old, inactive,
    a cranky, sour person, though not physically ill. She
    prefers to go on living. She is also rather rich. I
    could make a fortune if I could get my hands on
    her money, money she intends to give me in any
    event, after she dies, but which she refuses to give
    me now. In order to avoid a huge tax bite, I plan to
    donate a handsome sum of my profits to a local
    children’s hospital. Many, many children will ben-
    efit from my generosity, and much joy will be
    brought to their parents, relatives, and friends. If I
    don’t get the money rather soon, all these ambitions
    will come to naught. The once-in-a-lifetime-
    opportunity to make a real killing will be gone.
    Why, then, not really kill my Aunt Bea? Oh, of
    course I might get caught. But I’m no fool and,
    besides, her doctor can be counted on to cooperate
    (he has an eye for -the same investment and I hap-
    pen to know a good deal about his shady past). The

    36 CHAPTER 2 •ANIMAL RIGHTS

    deed can be done … professionally, shall we say.
    There is very little chance of getting caught. And
    as for my conscience being guilt ridden, I am a
    resourceful sort of fellow and will take more than
    sufficient comfort-as I lie on the beach at
    Acapulco-in contemplating the joy and health I
    have brought to so many others.

    Suppose Aunt Bea is killed and the rest of the
    story comes out as told. Would I have done any-
    thing wrong? Anything immoral? One would have
    thought that I had. But not according to utilitari-
    anism. Since what I did brought about the best
    balance of totaled satisfaction over frustration for
    all those affected by the outcome, what I did was
    not wrong. Indeed, in killing Aunt Bea the physi-
    cian and I did what duty required.

    This same kind of argument can be repeated in
    all sorts of cases, illustrating time after time, how the
    utilitarian’s position leads to results that impartial
    people find morally callous. It is wrong to kill my
    Aunt Bea in the name of bringing about the best
    results for others. A good end does not justify an
    evil means. Any adequate moral theory will have to
    explain why this is so. Utilitarianism fails in this
    respect and so cannot be the theory we seek.

    What to do? Where to begin anew? The place
    to begin, I think, is with the utilitarian’s view of the
    value of the individual-or, rather, lack of value. In
    its place suppose we consider that you and I, for
    example, do have value as individuals-what we’ll
    call inherent value. To say we have such value is to
    say that we are something more than, something
    different from, mere receptacles. Moreover, to in-
    sure that we do not pave the way for such injustices
    as slavery or sexual discrimination, we must believe
    that all who have inherent value have it equally,
    regardless of their sex, race, religion, birthplace,
    and so on. Similarly to be discarded as irrelevant
    are one’s talents or skills, intelligence and wealth,
    personality or pathology, whether one is loved and
    admired-or despised and loathed. The genius and
    the retarded child, the prince and the pauper, the
    brain surgeon and the fruit vendor, Mother Theresa
    and the most unscrupulous used car salesman-all
    have inherent value, all possess it equally, and all have
    an equal right to be treated with respect, to be treated in
    ways that do not reduce them to the status of

    things, as if they exist as resources for others. My
    value as an individual is independent of my useful-
    ness to you. Yours is not dependent on your
    usefulness to me. For either of us to treat the other
    in ways that fail to show respect for the other’s
    independent value is to act immorally-is to violate
    the individual’s rights.

    Some of the rational virtues of this view-what
    I call the rights view-should be evident. Unlike
    (crude) contractarianism, for example, the rights
    view in principle denies the moral tolerability of
    any and all forms of racial, sexual, or social discrim-
    ination; and unlike utilitarianism, this view in prin-
    ciple denies that we can justify good results by using
    evil means that violate an individual’s rights-denies,
    for example, that it could be moral to kill my Aunt
    Bea to harvest beneficial consequences for others.
    That would be to sanction the disrespectful treatment
    of the individual in the name of the social good,
    something the rights view will not-categorically
    will not-ever allow.

    The rights view-or so I believe-is rationally
    the most satisfactory moral theory. It surpasses all
    other theories in the degree to which it illuminates
    and explains the foundation of our duties to one
    another-the domain of human morality. On this
    score, it has the best reasons, the best arguments, on
    its side. Of course, if it were possible to show that
    only human beings are included within its scope,
    then a person like myself, who believes in animal
    rights, would be obliged to look elsewhere than to
    the rights view.

    But attempts to limit its scope to humans only
    can be shown to be rationally defective. Animals, it
    is true, lack many of the abilities humans possess.
    They can’t read, do higher mathematics, build a
    bookcase, or make baba ghanoush. Neither can
    many human beings, however, and yet we don’t
    say-and shouldn’t say-that they (these humans)
    therefore have less inherent value, less of a right to
    be treated with respect, than do others. It is the
    similarities between those human beings who
    most clearly, most noncontroversially have such
    value-the people reading this, for example-it is
    our similarities, not our differences, that matter
    most. And the really crucial, the basic similarity is
    simply this; we are each ef us the experiencing subject ef a

    TOM REGAN• THE RADICAL EGALITARIAN CASE FOR ANIMAL RIGHTS 37 ii

    life, each of us a conscious creature having an individual
    welfare that has importance to us whatever our usefulness
    to others. We want and prefer things; believe and
    feel things; recall and expect things. And all these
    dimensions of our life, including our pleasure and
    pain, our enjoyment and suffering, our satisfaction
    and frustration, our continued existence or our un-
    timely death-all make a difference to the quality
    of our life as lived, as experienced by us as indivi-
    duals. As the same is true of those animals who
    concern us (those who are eaten and trapped, for
    example), they, too, must be viewed as the
    experiencing subjects of a life with inherent value
    of their own.

    There are some who resist the idea that animals
    have inherent value. “Only humans have such
    value,” they profess. How might this narrow view
    be defended? Shall we say that only humans have
    the requisite intelligence, or autonomy, or reason?
    But there are many, many humans who will fail to
    meet these standards and yet who are reasonably
    viewed as having value above and beyond their
    usefulness to others. Shall we claim that only hu-
    mans belong to the right species-the species Homo
    sapiens? But this is blatant speciesism. Will it be said,
    then, that all-and only-humans have immortal
    souls? Then our opponents more than have their
    work cut out for them. I am myself not ill-
    disposed to there being immortal souls. Personally,
    I profoundly hope I have one. But I would not
    want to rest my position on a controversial, ethical
    issue on the even more controversial question about
    who or what has an immortal soul. That is to dig
    one’s hole deeper, not climb out. Rationally, it is
    better to resolve moral issues without making more
    controversial assumptions than are needed. The
    question of who has inherent value· is such a ques-
    tion, one that is more rationally resolved without
    the introduction of the idea of immortal souls than
    by its use.

    Well, perhaps some will say that animals .have
    some inherent value, only less than we do. Once
    again, however, attempts to defend this view can
    be shown to lack rational justification. What could
    be the basis of our having more inherent value than
    animals? Will it be their lack of reason, or auton-
    omy, or intellect? Only if we are willing to make

    the same judgment in the case of humans who are
    similarly deficient. But it is not true that such
    humans-the retarded child, for example, or the
    mentally deranged-have less inherent value than
    you or I. Neither, then, can we rationally sustain
    the view that animals like them in being the
    experiencing subjects of a life have less inherent
    value. All who have inherent value have it equally,
    whether they be human animals or not.

    Inherent value, then, belongs equally to those
    who are the experiencing subjects of a life.
    Whether it belongs to others-to rocks and rivers,
    trees and glaciers, for example-we do not know. , l
    And may never know. But neither do we need to
    know, if we are to make the case for animal rights.
    We do not need to know how many people, for
    example, are eligible to vote in the next presidential
    election before we can know whether I am. Simi-
    larly, we do not need to know how many individuals
    have inherent value before we can know that some
    do. When it comes to the case for animal rights,
    then what we need to know is whether the animals
    who, in our culture are routinely eaten, hunted,
    and used in our laboratories, for example, are like
    us in being subjects of a life. And we do know this.
    We do know that many-literally, billions and
    billions-of these animals are subjects of a life in
    the sense explained and so have inherent value if
    we do. And since, in order to have the best theory
    of our duties to one another, we must recognize our
    equal inherent value, as individuals, reason-not sen-.
    timent, not emotion-reason compels us to recognize
    the equal inherent value ef these animals. And, with
    this, their equal right to be treated with respect.

    That, very roughly, is the shape and feel of the
    case for animal rights. Most of the details of the
    supporting argument are missing. They are to be
    found in the book I alluded to earlier. Here, the
    details go begging and I must in closing, limit my-
    self to four final points.

    The first is how the theory that underlies the case
    for animal rights shows that the animal rights move-
    ment is a part of, not antagonistic to, the human rights
    movement. The theory that rationally grounds the .
    rights of animals also grounds the rights of humans.
    Thus are those involved in the animal rights move-
    ment partners in the struggle to secure respect for

    human rights-the rights of women, for example, or
    minorities and workers. The animal rights movement
    is cut from the same moral cloth as these.

    Second, having set out the broad outlines of the
    rights view, I can now say why its implications for
    farming and science, for example, are both clear and
    uncompromising. In the case of using animals in sci-
    ence, the rights view is categorically abolitionist. Lab
    animals are not our tasters; we are not their kings. Because
    these animals are treated-routinely, systematically-
    as if their value is reducible to their usefulness to
    others, they are routinely systematically treated
    with a lack of respect, and thus their rights routinely,
    systematically violated. This is just as true when they
    are used in trivial, duplicative, unnecessary or unwise
    research as it is when they are used in studies that
    hold out real promise of ~uman benefits. We can’t
    justify harming or killing a human being (my Aunt
    Bea, for example) just for these sorts of reasons.
    Neither can we do so even in the case of so lowly
    a creature as a laboratory rat. It is not just refinement
    or reduction that are called for, not just larger,
    cleaner cages, not just more generous use of anes-
    thetic or the elimination of multiple surgery, not
    just tidying up the system. It is replacement-
    completely. The best we can do when it comes to
    using animals in science is-not to use them. That is
    where our duty lies, according to the rights view.

    As for commercial animal agriculture, the rights
    view takes a similar abolitionist position. The fun-
    damental moral wrong here is not that animals are
    kept in stressful close confinement, or in isolation,
    or that they have their pain and suffering, their
    needs and preferences ignored or discounted. All
    these are wrong, of course, but they are not the
    fundamental wrong. They are symptoms and effects
    of the deeper, systematic wrong that allows these
    animals to be viewed and treated as lacking inde-
    pendent value, as resources , for us-as, indeed, a
    renewable resource. Giving farm animals more space,
    more natural environments, more companions does
    not right the fundamental wrong, any more than
    giving lab animals more anesthesia or bigger, cleaner
    cages would right the fundamental wrong in their
    case. Nothing less than the total dissolution of com-
    mercial animal agriculture will do this, just as, for

    similar reasons I won’t develop at length here, mo-
    rality requires nothing less than the total elimination
    of commercial and sport hunting and trapping. The
    rights view’s implications, then, as I have said, are
    clear-and are uncompromising.

    My last two points are about philosophy-my
    profession. It is most obviously, no substitute for
    political action. The words I have written here
    and in other places by themselves don’t change a
    thing. It is what we do with the thoughts the words
    express-our acts, our deeds-that change things.
    All that philosophy can do, and all I have at-
    tempted, is to offer a vision of what our deeds could
    aim at. And the why. But not the how.

    Finally, I am reminded of my thoughtful critic, the
    one I mentioned earlier, who chastised me for being
    “too cerebral.” Well, cerebral I have been: indirect
    duty views, utilitarianism, contractarianism-hardly
    the stuff deep passions are made 0£ I am also re-
    minded, however, of the image another friend once
    set before me–the image of the ballerina as expres-
    sive of disciplined passion. Long hours of sweat and
    toil, of loneliness and practice, of doubt and fatigue;
    that is the discipline of her craft. But the passion is
    there, too: the fierce drive to excel, to speak through
    her body, to do it right, to pierce our minds. That is
    the image of philosophy I would leave with you; not
    “too cerebral,” but disciplined passion. Of the disci-
    pline, enough has been seen. As for the passion:

    There are times, and these are not infrequent,
    when tears come to my eyes when I see, or read, or
    hear of the wretched plight of animals in the hands
    of humans. Their pain, their suffering, their loneli-
    ness, their innocence, their death. Anger. Rage.
    Pity. Sorrow. Disgust. The whole creation groans
    under the weight of the evil we humans visit upon
    these mute, powerless creatures. It is our heart, not
    just our head, that calls for an end, that demands of
    us thq.t we overcome, for them, the habits and
    forces behind their systematic oppression. All great
    movements, it is written, go through three stages:
    ridicule, discussion, adoption. It is the realization of
    this third stage-adoption-that demands both our
    passion and our discipline, our heart and our head.
    The fate of animals is in our hands. God grant we are
    equal to the task.

    NOTE

    1. Tom Regan, The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley:
    University of California Press, 1983).

    STUDY QUESTIONS

    1. How is Regan’s position on animal rights dif-
    ferent from Singer’s? Explain.

    2. What are Regan’s reasons for granting animals
    equal moral rights?

    5

    3. Does Regan allow for experimentation on
    animals? If we have to test a dangerous AIDS
    vaccine, on whom should we test it?

    A Critique of Regan’s Animal Rights Theory
    MARY ANNE WARREN

    The author of many articles in moral philosophy, Mary Anne Warren teaches philosophy at
    San Francisco State University.

    Warren reconstructs Regan’s argument for animal rights and criticizes it for depending
    on the obscure notion of inherent value. She then argues that all rational human beings
    are equally part of the moral community since we can reason with each other about our
    behavior, whereas we cannot so reason with an animal. She puts forth a “weak animal
    rights theory,” which asserts that we ought not to be cruel to animals or kill them without

    good reason.

    Tom Regan has produced what is perhaps the de-
    finitive defense of the view that the basic moral
    rights of at least some non-human animals are in
    no way inferior to our own. In The Case for Animal
    Rights, he argues that all normal mammals over a
    year of age have the same basic moral rights.

    1
    Non-

    human mammals have essentially the same right not

    to be harmed or killed as we do. I shall call this “the
    strong animal rights position,” although it is weaker
    than the claims made by some animal liberationists
    in that it ascribes rights to only some sentient
    animals.

    2

    I will argue that Regan’s case for the strong
    animal rights position is unpersuasive and that this

    Reprinted from Between the Species, Vol. 2, No. 4 (Fall 1987) by pennission of Mary Anne Warren.

    What Will You Get?

    We provide professional writing services to help you score straight A’s by submitting custom written assignments that mirror your guidelines.

    Premium Quality

    Get result-oriented writing and never worry about grades anymore. We follow the highest quality standards to make sure that you get perfect assignments.

    Experienced Writers

    Our writers have experience in dealing with papers of every educational level. You can surely rely on the expertise of our qualified professionals.

    On-Time Delivery

    Your deadline is our threshold for success and we take it very seriously. We make sure you receive your papers before your predefined time.

    24/7 Customer Support

    Someone from our customer support team is always here to respond to your questions. So, hit us up if you have got any ambiguity or concern.

    Complete Confidentiality

    Sit back and relax while we help you out with writing your papers. We have an ultimate policy for keeping your personal and order-related details a secret.

    Authentic Sources

    We assure you that your document will be thoroughly checked for plagiarism and grammatical errors as we use highly authentic and licit sources.

    Moneyback Guarantee

    Still reluctant about placing an order? Our 100% Moneyback Guarantee backs you up on rare occasions where you aren’t satisfied with the writing.

    Order Tracking

    You don’t have to wait for an update for hours; you can track the progress of your order any time you want. We share the status after each step.

    image

    Areas of Expertise

    Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

    Areas of Expertise

    Although you can leverage our expertise for any writing task, we have a knack for creating flawless papers for the following document types.

    image

    Trusted Partner of 9650+ Students for Writing

    From brainstorming your paper's outline to perfecting its grammar, we perform every step carefully to make your paper worthy of A grade.

    Preferred Writer

    Hire your preferred writer anytime. Simply specify if you want your preferred expert to write your paper and we’ll make that happen.

    Grammar Check Report

    Get an elaborate and authentic grammar check report with your work to have the grammar goodness sealed in your document.

    One Page Summary

    You can purchase this feature if you want our writers to sum up your paper in the form of a concise and well-articulated summary.

    Plagiarism Report

    You don’t have to worry about plagiarism anymore. Get a plagiarism report to certify the uniqueness of your work.

    Free Features $66FREE

    • Most Qualified Writer $10FREE
    • Plagiarism Scan Report $10FREE
    • Unlimited Revisions $08FREE
    • Paper Formatting $05FREE
    • Cover Page $05FREE
    • Referencing & Bibliography $10FREE
    • Dedicated User Area $08FREE
    • 24/7 Order Tracking $05FREE
    • Periodic Email Alerts $05FREE
    image

    Our Services

    Join us for the best experience while seeking writing assistance in your college life. A good grade is all you need to boost up your academic excellence and we are all about it.

    • On-time Delivery
    • 24/7 Order Tracking
    • Access to Authentic Sources
    Academic Writing

    We create perfect papers according to the guidelines.

    Professional Editing

    We seamlessly edit out errors from your papers.

    Thorough Proofreading

    We thoroughly read your final draft to identify errors.

    image

    Delegate Your Challenging Writing Tasks to Experienced Professionals

    Work with ultimate peace of mind because we ensure that your academic work is our responsibility and your grades are a top concern for us!

    Check Out Our Sample Work

    Dedication. Quality. Commitment. Punctuality

    Categories
    All samples
    Essay (any type)
    Essay (any type)
    The Value of a Nursing Degree
    Undergrad. (yrs 3-4)
    Nursing
    2
    View this sample

    It May Not Be Much, but It’s Honest Work!

    Here is what we have achieved so far. These numbers are evidence that we go the extra mile to make your college journey successful.

    0+

    Happy Clients

    0+

    Words Written This Week

    0+

    Ongoing Orders

    0%

    Customer Satisfaction Rate
    image

    Process as Fine as Brewed Coffee

    We have the most intuitive and minimalistic process so that you can easily place an order. Just follow a few steps to unlock success.

    See How We Helped 9000+ Students Achieve Success

    image

    We Analyze Your Problem and Offer Customized Writing

    We understand your guidelines first before delivering any writing service. You can discuss your writing needs and we will have them evaluated by our dedicated team.

    • Clear elicitation of your requirements.
    • Customized writing as per your needs.

    We Mirror Your Guidelines to Deliver Quality Services

    We write your papers in a standardized way. We complete your work in such a way that it turns out to be a perfect description of your guidelines.

    • Proactive analysis of your writing.
    • Active communication to understand requirements.
    image
    image

    We Handle Your Writing Tasks to Ensure Excellent Grades

    We promise you excellent grades and academic excellence that you always longed for. Our writers stay in touch with you via email.

    • Thorough research and analysis for every order.
    • Deliverance of reliable writing service to improve your grades.
    Place an Order Start Chat Now
    image

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code Happy